Home
  By Author [ A  B  C  D  E  F  G  H  I  J  K  L  M  N  O  P  Q  R  S  T  U  V  W  X  Y  Z |  Other Symbols ]
  By Title [ A  B  C  D  E  F  G  H  I  J  K  L  M  N  O  P  Q  R  S  T  U  V  W  X  Y  Z |  Other Symbols ]
  By Language
all Classics books content using ISYS

Download this book: [ ASCII | HTML | PDF ]

Look for this book on Amazon


We have new books nearly every day.
If you would like a news letter once a week or once a month
fill out this form and we will give you a summary of the books for that week or month by email.

Title: The Origin of the Knowledge of Right and Wrong
Author: Brentano, Franz
Language: English
As this book started as an ASCII text book there are no pictures available.


*** Start of this LibraryBlog Digital Book "The Origin of the Knowledge of Right and Wrong" ***


produced from images generously made available by The
Internet Archive)



                              THE ORIGIN
                          OF THE KNOWLEDGE OF
                            RIGHT AND WRONG



                              THE ORIGIN
                          OF THE KNOWLEDGE OF
                            RIGHT AND WRONG

                           BY FRANZ BRENTANO

                          ENGLISH TRANSLATION
                            BY CECIL HAGUE

                          FORMERLY LECTOR AT
                           PRAGUE UNIVERSITY

                       WITH A BIOGRAPHICAL NOTE

                              WESTMINSTER
                     ARCHIBALD CONSTABLE & CO LTD
                          2 WHITEHALL GARDENS
                                 1902

                           BUTLER & TANNER,
                      THE SELWOOD PRINTING WORKS,
                          FROME, AND LONDON.


The present translation owes its origin to a desire on the part of the
translator of bringing to the wider notice of his fellow-countrymen a
work which has proved beneficial and stimulating to himself. Written
during short intervals of leisure while studying with Professor Anton
Marty of Prague University, it has had the advantage of his careful and
constant supervision. Without his aid it would scarcely have seen the
light. The translator has especially to thank Professor S. A. Alexander,
of Owens College, Manchester, for his valuable help in the general
revision and the translation of several difficult passages. It is now,
alas, too late to do more than record the translator’s debt to the late
Professor Adamson, of Glasgow University, whose revision and correction
of this essay was one of the last services rendered to the cause of
truth by a life-long disciple.

_West Dulwich, 1902._



AUTHOR’S PREFACE


This lecture, which I now bring before the notice of a larger public,
was delivered by me before the Vienna Law Society on January 23, 1889.
It then bore the title: “Of the Natural Sanction for Law and Morality.”
This title I have changed in order to bring its general purport more
clearly into prominence; otherwise I have made scarcely any further
alteration. Numerous notes have been added, and an already published
essay: “Miklosich on Subjectless Propositions” appended. In what way it
bears upon inquiries apparently so remote will be evident in the sequel.

The occasion of the lecture was an invitation extended to me by Baron
Von Hye, President of the Society. It was his wish that what had been
said here a few years ago by Ihering, as jurist, in his address, _Über
die Entstehung des Rechtsgefühls_, might in the same Society be
illustrated by me from the philosophic point of view. It would be a
mistake to assume from the incidental nature of the circumstances to
which it owed its first appearance that the Essay was only a fugitive,
occasional study. It embraces the fruits of many years’ reflection. The
discussions it contains form the ripest product of all that I have
hitherto published.

These thoughts form a fragment of a Descriptive Psychology, which, as I
now venture to hope, I may be enabled in the near future to publish in
its complete form. In its wide divergence from all that has hitherto
been put forward, and especially by reason of its being an essential
stage in the further development of some of the views advocated in my
_Psychology from the Empirical Standpoint_ it will be sufficiently
evident that during the period of my long literary retirement I have not
been idle.

Specialists in philosophy will find also in this lecture what will be at
once recognized as new. As regards the general reader, the rapidity with
which I pass from one question to another might at first completely
conceal many a sunken reef which required to be circumnavigated, many a
precipice which had to be avoided. Surely I, if any one, have reason,
owing to the conciseness of statement employed, to remember the saying
of Leibnitz and pay little attention to refutation and much to
demonstration. A glance at the notes--which, were they to do full
justice to the subject, would need to be multiplied an hundredfold--will
give him a further idea of those bye-paths which have misled so many,
and prevented their finding an issue to the labyrinth. Meantime I would
be well content--nay, I would regard it as the crown to all my
efforts--should all that has been said appear so self-evident to him
that he does not deem himself bound to thank me once in return.

No one has determined the principles of ethics as, on the basis of new
analyses, I have found it necessary to determine them, no one,
especially among those who hold that in the foundation of those
principles the feelings must find a place, have so radically and
completely broken with the subjective view of ethics. I except only
Herbart. But he lost himself in the sphere of aesthetic feeling, until
at last we find him so far from the track that he, who in the
theoretical philosophy is the irreconcilable enemy of contradiction,
nevertheless in practical philosophy (i.e. ethics) tolerates it when his
principles--the highest universally valid ideas--rush into conflict with
one another. Still his teaching remains in a certain aspect truly
related with mine, while, on other sides, other celebrated attempts to
discover a basis for ethics find in it points of contact.

In the notes, individual points are more sharply defined, a very
detailed examination of which would have been too prolix in the lecture.
Many an objection already urged has been met, many an expected rejoinder
anticipated. I also hope that some will be interested in the several
historical contributions, especially in the inquiries concerning
Descartes, where I trace back the doctrine of evidence to its causes and
point out two further thoughts, one of which has been misunderstood, the
other scarcely noticed, neither treated with the consideration they
deserve. I refer to his fundamental classification of mental states and
to his doctrine of the relation of love to joy, and of hate to sadness.

With several highly honoured investigators of the present--assuredly not
least honoured by myself--I have entered into a polemical debate, and
indeed most vigorously with those whose previous attack has compelled
me to a defence. I hope that they do not regard it as a violation of
_their_ claims, when I seek, to the utmost of my power, to help the
truth, which we in common serve, to her rights, and I assure them in
turn, that as I myself speak frankly, so also none the less do I welcome
with all my heart every sincere word of my opponent.

FRANZ BRENTANO.



CONTENTS


THE ORIGIN OF THE KNOWLEDGE OF RIGHT AND WRONG

A LECTURE

                                                                    PAGE

1. Value of History and Philosophy for Jurisprudence; the new proposals
for the reform of legal studies in Austria                             1

2. Our theme; Relation to Ihering’s lecture before the Vienna Law
Society                                                                2

3. Twofold meaning of the expression “natural right”                   2

4. Points of agreement with Ihering; rejection of the “jus naturae”
and “jus gentium”; pre-ethical political statutes                      3

5. Opposition to Ihering; There exists a universally valid naturally
recognizable moral law. Relative independence of the question          4

6. The notion “natural sanction”                                       4

7. Manifold misconception of the same by philosophers                  6

8. Habitually developed feeling of compulsion as such is no sanction   6

9. Motives of hope and fear as such not yet sanction                   6

10. The thought of the arbitrary command of a higher power is not the
natural sanction                                                       7

11. The ethical sanction is a command similar to the logical rule      8

12. The aesthetic point of view; as little in ethics as in logic
the right one                                                          9

13. Kant’s Categorical Imperative an impracticable fiction            10

14. Necessity for preliminary psychological inquiries                 10

15. No willing without a final end                                    10

16. The problem: which end is right? the chief problem of ethics      11

17. The right end is the best among attainable ends; obscureness
 of this definition                                                   11

18. Of the origin of the conception of the good; it has not its origin in
the sphere of the so-called external impression                       12

19. The common characteristic of everything psychical                 12

20. The three fundamental classes of psychical phenomena; idea
(Vorstellung), judgment, feeling (Gemütsbewegung)                     13

21. The contrasts, belief and denial, love and hate                   15

22. Of these opposed modes of relation one is always right, one wrong  15

23. The conception of the good                                        15

24. Distinction of the good in the narrow sense from what is good for
the sake of some other good                                           16

25. Love is not always a proof that an object is worthy to be loved   16

26. “Blind” and “self-evident” judgment                               17

27. Analogous distinction in the sphere of pleasure and displeasure;
criterion of the good                                                 18

28. Plurality of the good; problems associated therewith              21

29. Whether by “the better” is to be understood that which deserves
to be loved with more intensity                                       21

30. Right determination of the conception                             22

31. When and how do we recognize that anything is in itself preferable?
The case of the opposite, of absence, of the addition of
like to like                                                          23

32. Cases where the problem is insoluble                              25

33. Whether the Hedonists in this respect would have the advantage    26

34. Why these failures prove less disadvantageous than might
be feared                                                             27

35. The sphere of the highest practical good                          28

36. The harmonious development                                        28

37. The natural sanction respecting the limits of right               29

38. The natural sanction for positive ethical laws                    29

39. The power of the natural sanction                                 30

40. True and false relativity respecting ethical rules                30

41. Derivation of well known special enactments                       32

42. Why other philosophers, by other ways, arrive at the same goal    32

43. Whence arise the universally extended ethical truths? Unclearness
concerning processes in one’s own consciousness                       33

44. Trace of the influence of the moments severally mentioned         35

45. Lower currents exercising an influence                            37

46. Necessity of guarding against overlooking the distinction between
ethical and pseudo-ethical development                                39

47. Value of such developments in the pre-ethical time; establishment
of the social order; formation of dispositions; outlines of laws
at the disposal of legislative ethical authority; security against
doctrinaire tendencies                                                39

48. Beneficent influences which still operate continually
from this side                                                        41

49. A further word on the reform of politico-legal studies            42



NOTES.

                                                                    PAGE

13. In defence of my characterization of Herbart’s ethical criterion  44

14. Of Kant’s Categorical Imperative                                  44

16. The Nicomachean Ethics and Ihering’s “fundamental idea” in
his work; _Der Zweck im Recht_                                        46

17. Of the cases of smaller chances in the effort after higher ends   46

18. Of the dependence of the conceptions upon concrete perceptions    46

19. The term “intentional”                                            47

21. The fundamental classification of mental states in Descartes      47

22. Windelband’s error in respect of the fundamental classification of
mental states; short defence of various attacks upon my _Psychology
from the Empirical Standpoint_; Land, on a supposed improvement on
formal logic; Steinthal’s criticism of my doctrine of judgment        50

23. In criticism of Sigwart’s theories of the existential and
negative judgments                                                    55

24. Descartes on the relation of “love” to “joy” and of “hate” to
“sadness”                                                             69

25. Of the notions of truth and existence                             69

26. Of the unity of the notion of the good                            71

27. Of “evidence.” Descartes “Clara et distincta perceptio.” Sigwart’s
doctrine of “evidence” and his “postulates”                           71

28. Of ethical subjectivism. Aristotle’s oversight in respect of the
source of our knowledge of the good. Parallels between his
error in respect of the feelings (Gemütsthätigkeit), and Descartes’
doctrine of the “Clara et distincta perceptio” as a pre-condition
of the logically justified judgment; modern views which approach
to this doctrine                                                      78

29. Of the expressions “gut gefallen” and “schlecht gefallen”         84

31. Typical case of a constant geometrical relation of mental values  85

32. Cases in which something at the same time both pleases and
displeases                                                            85

33. Establishment of universal laws of valuation on the basis of a
single experience                                                     86

34. Certain moments in the theory of ethical knowledge are of more
importance for the theodicy than for ethics itself                    87

35. Explanation of the manner in which anything in certain cases is
recognized as preferable                                              87

36. The two cases, unique in their kind, in which preferability becomes
clear for us from a certain character in the act of preference        87

39. Gauss on the measurement of intensities                           89

40. Against exaggerated expectations from the so-called psycho-physical
law                                                                   89

40. Defence against the objection of a too great ethical rigour       90

41. Love of neighbour in harmony with greater care of one’s own good  91

43. Why the narrowness of human foresight should not do injury to
moral courage                                                         92

44. In criticism of Ihering’s view of the notion of right and of his
criticism of older views                                              93

45. Of the provisional ethical sanction of objectionable laws         96

60. Self-contradiction of Epicurus                                    97

64-65. Proof for the law of addition of like to like; testimony for it in
the teaching of the Stoa, of the theistic Hedonists, and in the
demand for immortality; Helmholtz                                     98

67. The great theologians are opponents of the arbitrary character of
the divine law of morals                                              99

68. John Stuart Mill on the doctrine of the distinction between
“blind” and “self-evident judgments”                                  99

(The numbers missing in the index contain only literary references.)


MIKLOSICH ON SUBJECTLESS PROPOSITIONS

(Appendix to pages 14 and 55).

I. Short sketch of the essential features treated in Miklosich’s
article                                                              105

II. Critical remarks                                                 110

Biographical Note                                                    119



A LECTURE


1. The invitation to lecture extended to me by the Law Society was the
more binding as it gave expression in strong terms to a conviction
which, unfortunately, seems on the point of falling into abeyance.
Proposals for a reform of legal studies have been heard (and they are
even said to have proceeded from university circles) which can only mean
that the roots of jurisprudence deeply implanted as they are in the
spheres of ethics and national history may be severed, without the
organism itself suffering any vital injury.

As regards history, this counsel is to me, I confess, utterly
inexplicable; in respect of philosophy, I can excuse it only on the
ground that the men who at present occupy the chairs in the legal
faculty have taken a deep and gloomy impression of the mistakes of a
period which has lately passed away. A personal reproach may therefore
well be spared them. Yet indeed such suggestions were every bit as wise
as would be the case if a medical faculty were to propose to erase from
their plan of obligatory studies zoology, physics and chemistry.

If Leibnitz in his _Vita a se ipso lineata_, speaking of himself, says:
“I found that my earlier studies in history and philosophy lightened
materially my study of law,” and if, as in his _Specimen difficultatis
in jure_, deploring the prejudices of contemporary jurists, he exclaims:
“Oh! that those who busy themselves with the study of law would throw
aside their contempt of philosophy and see that without philosophy most
of the questions of their jus form a labyrinth without issue!” what
indeed would he say were he to rise again to-day, to these retrograde
reform movements?


2. The worthy President of the Society, who has retained such a lively
and wide sense of the real scientific needs of his profession, expressed
to me his own special wishes respecting the theme to be chosen. The
question as to the existence of a natural right was, he said, a subject
which enjoyed an exceptional interest with the members of the Law
Society; and he himself was anxious to learn what attitude I would adopt
with regard to the views there expressed by Ihering some years ago.[1]

I consented gladly, and have therefore designated as the subject of my
lecture the natural sanction for law and morality, wishing thereby, at
the same time, to indicate in what sense alone I believe in a natural
right.


3. For a two-fold meaning may be associated with the term “natural”:--

     (1) It may mean as much as “given by nature,” “innate,” in
     contradistinction to what has been acquired during historical
     development either by deduction or by experience.

     (2) It may mean, in contradistinction to what is determined by the
     arbitrary will of a dictator, the rules which, in and for
     themselves and in virtue of their nature are recognized as right
     and binding.

Ihering rejects natural right in either of these meanings.[2] I, for my
part, agree as thoroughly with him regarding the one meaning as I differ
from him regarding the other.


4. I agree completely with Ihering when, following the example of John
Locke, he denies all innate moral principles.

Further, like him, I believe neither in the grotesque _jus naturae_,
i.e. _quod natura ipsa omnia animalia docuit_, nor in a _jus gentium_,
in a right which, as the Roman jurists defined it, is recognized as a
natural law of reason by the universal agreement of all nations.

It is not necessary to have gone deeply into zoology and physiology in
order to see that we can no longer use the animal world as a criterion
for the setting up of ethical standards, even if one is not disposed to
go so far as Rokitansky in pronouncing protoplasma, with its aggressive
character, an unrighteous and evil principle.

As to a common code of right for all nations, such a belief was a
delusion which might hold good in the antique world; in modern times
when the ethnographical horizon has been extended, and the customs of
barbarous races drawn upon for comparison, these laws can no longer be
recognized as a product of nature, but only as a product of culture
common to the more advanced nations.

As regards all this, therefore, I am in agreement with Ihering; I am
also substantially in agreement with him when he asserts that there have
been times without any trace of ethical knowledge and ethical feeling;
at any rate without anything of the kind that was commonly accepted.

Indeed I acknowledge unhesitatingly that this state of things continued
even when larger communities under state government had been
constituted. When Ihering, in support of this view, points to Greek
mythology with its gods and goddesses destitute of moral thought and
feeling, and maintains that, by the lives of the gods, the life of
mankind in the period in which these myths took shape may be
interpreted,[3] he does but use a method of proof which Aristotle has
already employed in a similar manner in his _Politics_.[4] This also
must therefore be conceded him, and we shall, on this ground, no longer
deny that the earliest political laws supported by penal sanction were
established without the help of any feeling of right founded upon moral
insight. There are, therefore, no natural moral laws and legal precepts
in the sense that they are given by nature herself, that they are
innate; in this respect, Ihering’s views have our entire approval.


5. We have now to meet the second and far more important question: Do
there exist truths concerning morality, taught by nature herself, and is
there moral truth, independent of all ecclesiastical, political, in fact
every kind of social authority? Is there a natural moral law which, in
its nature, is universally and incontestably valid for men of every
place and time, valid indeed for every kind of thinking and sentient
being; and does the knowledge of it lie within the realm of our mental
faculties? Here we are at the point where I join issue with Ihering. To
this question, which Ihering answers in the negative, I return a decided
affirmative. Which of us is here in the right our present inquiry into
the natural sanction for law and morality will, I hope, make clear.

At any rate, the decision as to the former question, whatever Ihering[5]
himself may think to the contrary, does not in any way prejudge the
latter. Innate prejudices do exist; these are natural in the former
sense, but they lack natural sanction; whether true or false, they
possess no immediate validity. On the other hand, there are many
propositions recognized after a natural manner, which are incontestably
certain and have universal validity for all thinking beings, which,
however, as, for example, the Pythagorean theorem are anything but
innate, else the blissful first discoverer had never offered his
hecatomb to the god.


6. In what has been said I have made it sufficiently evident how, when I
speak of natural sanction, I understand the notion of sanction. Yet it
will be well to linger a moment in order to exclude another inadequate
view.

“Sanction” signifies “making fast.” Now a law may be fixed in a double
sense:

     (1) It may be fixed in the sense of becoming law, as when a
     proposed law receives validity by ratification on the part of the
     highest legislative authority.

     (2) In the sense of being rendered more effectual by attaching to
     it positive punishments, perhaps also rewards.

It is in this latter sense that sanction was spoken of by writers of
antiquity, as when Cicero[6] says of the leges Porciae: “Neque quicquam
praeter sanctionem attulerunt novi”; and Ulpian:[7] “Interdum in
sanctionibus adijicitur, ut qui ibi aliquid commisit, capite puniatur.”
It is in the former sense that the expression is more usual in modern
times; a law is said to be “sanctioned” when it secures validity by
receiving confirmation at the hands of the highest authority.

Manifestly sanction in the second sense presupposes sanction in the
first, which sanction is the more essential, since, without it, the law
would not truly be law at all. Such a natural sanction therefore is of
the last necessity if anything whatever is to bear by nature the stamp
of law or morality.


7. If we now compare with such a view what has been said by philosophers
concerning the natural sanction for morality, it will be easily seen how
often they have overlooked its essential character.


8. Many think that they have discovered a natural sanction in respect of
a certain line of conduct when they have shown that a certain feeling of
compulsion so to act is developed within the individual. Since every
one, for example, renders services to others in order to receive similar
services in return, there at last arises a habit of performing such
services even in cases where there has been no thought of recompense.[8]
This it is which is thought to constitute the sanction for love of our
neighbour.

But this view is entirely erroneous. Such a feeling of compulsion is
certainly a force driving to action, but it is assuredly not a sanction
conferring validity. Besides, the inclination to vice develops according
to the same law of habit, and exercises, as an impulse, the most
unbounded sway. The miser’s passion which leads him, in his desire of
amassing riches, to submit to the heaviest sacrifices and to commit the
most extreme cruelties, certainly constitutes no sanction for his
conduct.


9. Again, motives of hope or fear that a certain manner of behaviour,
as, for example, regard for the general good, will render us agreeable
or disagreeable to other and more powerful beings, these it has often
been sought to regard as a sanction for such conduct.[9] But it is
manifest that the most cringing cowardice, the most servile flattery
might then boast a natural sanction. As a matter of fact virtue shines
out most brightly where neither threats nor entreaties are able to
divert her from the right path.


10. Some speak of an education in which man, as belonging to an order of
living beings accustomed to live in society, receives from those by whom
he is surrounded. An injunction is repeatedly laid upon him, the
command: “You ought.” It lies in the nature of things that certain
actions are very frequently and generally required of him. There is thus
formed an association between his mode of action and the thought: “You
ought.” And so it may happen that he may come to regard, as the source
of this command, the society in which he lives, or even something
vaguely conceived to be higher than an individual, that is to say,
something regarded in a way as superhuman. The “ought” associated by him
with such a being would then constitute the sanction of conscience.[10]

In this case the natural sanction would then consist in the naturally
developed belief in the command of a more powerful will.

But it is manifest that such a belief in the command of a more powerful
being contains, as yet, nothing which deserves the name of a sanction.
Such a conviction is shared by one who knows himself to be at the mercy
of a tyrant or of a robber horde. Whether he obey, or bid defiance, the
command itself contains nothing able to give to the required act a
sanction similar to that of the conscience. Even if he obey he does so
through fear, not because he regards the command as one based on right.

The thought, therefore, that an act is commanded by some one does not
constitute a natural sanction. In the case of every command issued by an
external will the question arises: Is such a command authorized or is
it not? Neither is there any reference here to a command enforced by a
still higher power enjoining obedience to the former. For then the
question would again reappear, and we should proceed from one command to
another enjoining obedience to the former, and from that to a third
enjoining in like manner obedience to the second, and so on _ad infin_.

Just as in the case of the feeling of compulsion, and in that of the
fear or hope of recompense, so also the thought of the command of an
external will cannot possibly be the sanction for law and morality.


11. But there are also commands in an essentially different sense;
commands in the sense in which we speak of the commands of logic
respecting our judgments and conclusions. We are not here concerned with
the will of logic, since a will logic manifestly has not, nor with the
will of the logician, to which we have in no way sworn allegiance. The
laws of logic are naturally valid rules of judging, that is to say, we
are obliged to conform to them, since conformity to these rules ensures
certainty in our judgments, whereas judgments diverging from these rules
are liable to error. What we therefore mean is a natural superiority
which thought-processes in conformity with law have over such as are
contrary to law. So also in ethics, we are not concerned with the
command of an external will but rather with a natural preference similar
to that in logic, and the law founded on that preference. This has been
emphasized not only by Kant but also by the majority of great thinkers
before him. Nevertheless there are still many--unfortunately even among
the adherents of the empirical school to which I myself belong--by whom
this fact has neither been rightly understood nor appreciated.


12. In what then lies this special superiority which gives to morality
its natural sanction? Some regarded it as, in a sense, external, they
believed its superiority to consist in beauty of appearance. The Greeks
called noble and virtuous conduct Τὀ καλὁν, the beautiful, and the
perfect man of honour καλοκἀγαθός; though none of the philosophers of
antiquity set up this aesthetic view as a criterion. On the other hand,
David Hume[11], among modern thinkers, has spoken of a moral sense of
the beautiful which acts as arbiter between the moral and the immoral,
while still more recently the German philosopher, Herbart,[12] has
subordinated ethics to aesthetics.

Now I do not deny that the aspect of virtue is more agreeable than that
of moral perversity. But I cannot concede that in this consists the only
and essential superiority of ethical conduct. It is rather an inner
superiority which distinguishes the moral from the immoral will, in the
same way that it is an inner superiority which distinguishes true and
self evident judgments and conclusions from prejudices and fallacies.
Here also it cannot be denied that a prejudice, a fallacy has in it
something unbeautiful, often indeed something ridiculously
narrow-minded, which makes the person so scantily favoured by Minerva
appear in a most disadvantageous attitude; yet who, on this account,
would class the rules of logic among those of aesthetics, or make logic
a branch of aesthetics?[13] No, the real logical superiority is no mere
aesthetic appearance but a certain inward rightness which then carries
with it a certain superiority of appearance. It will, therefore, be
also a certain inward rightness which constitutes the essential
superiority of one particular act of will over another of an opposite
character; in which consists the superiority of the moral over the
immoral.

The belief in this superiority is an ethical motive; the knowledge of it
is the right ethical motive, the sanction which gives to ethical law
permanence and validity.


13. But are we capable of attaining to such knowledge? Here lies the
difficulty which philosophers have for a long time sought in vain to
solve. Even to Kant it seemed as though none had found the right end of
the thread by means of which to unravel the skein. This the Categorical
Imperative was to do. It resembled however, rather the sword drawn by
Alexander to cut the Gordian knot. With such a palpable fiction the
matter is not to be set right.[14]


14. In order to gain an insight into the true origin of ethical
knowledge it will be necessary to take some account of the results of
later researches in the sphere of descriptive psychology. The limited
time at my disposal makes it necessary for me to set forth my views very
briefly, and I have reason to fear that by its conciseness the
completeness of the statement may suffer. Yet it is just here that I ask
your special attention, in order that what is most essential to a right
understanding of the problem be not overlooked.


15. The subject of the moral and immoral is termed the will. What we
will is, in many cases, a means to an end. In that case we will this end
also, and even in a higher degree than the means. The end itself may
often be the means to a further end; in a far reaching plan there may
often appear a whole series of ends, the one being always connected in
subordination to the other as a means. There must be present, however,
one end, which is desired above all others and for its own sake; without
this essential and final end all incentive would be lacking, and this
would involve the absurdity of aiming without a goal at which to aim.


16. The means we employ in order to gain an end may be manifold, may be
right or wrong. They are right when they are really adapted to the
attainment of the end.

The ends, also, even the most essential and final ends, may be manifold.
It is a mistake which appeared especially in the eighteenth century,
nowadays the tendency is more and more to abandon it, that every one
seeks the same end, namely, his own highest possible pleasure.[15]
Whoever can believe that the martyr facing with full consciousness the
most terrible tortures for the sake of his conviction--and there were
some who had no hope of recompense hereafter--was thus inspired by a
desire after the greatest possible pleasure, such a man must have either
a very defective sense of the facts of the case, or, indeed, have lost
all measure of the intensities of pleasure and pain.

This, therefore, is certain: even final ends are manifold, between them
hovers the choice, which, since the final end is for everything the
determining principle, is of the most importance. What ought I to strive
after? Which end is the right one, which wrong? This, as Aristotle long
ago declared, is the essential, the cardinal question in ethics.[16]


17. Which end is right, for which should our choice declare itself?

Where the end is fixed and it is merely a question as to the choice of
means, we reply: Choose means which will certainly attain the end. Where
it is a question as to the choice of ends we would say: Choose an end
which reason regards as really attainable. This answer is, however,
insufficient, many a thing attainable is rather to be shunned than
sought after; choose the best among attainable ends, this alone is the
adequate answer.[17]

But the answer is obscure; what do we mean by “the best”? what can be
called “good” at all? and how can we attain to the knowledge that one
thing is good and better than another?


18. In order to answer this question satisfactorily, we must, above all,
inquire into the origin of the conception of the good, which lies, like
the origin of all our conceptions, in certain concrete impressions.[18]

We possess impressions with _physical_ content. These exhibit to us
sensuous qualities localized in space. Out of this sphere arise the
conceptions of colour, sound, space and many others. The conception of
the good, however, has not here its origin. It is easily recognizable
that the conception of the good like that of the true, which, as having
affinity, is rightly placed side by side with it, derives its origin
from concrete impressions with _psychical_ content.


19. The common feature of everything psychical consists in what has been
called by a very unfortunate and ambiguous term, consciousness; i.e. in
a subject-attitude; in what has been termed an _intentional_ relation to
something which, though perhaps not real, is none the less an inner
object of perception[19] No hearing without the heard, no believing
without the believed, no hoping without the hoped for, no striving
without the striven for, no joy without the enjoyed, and so with other
mental phenomena.


20. The sensuous qualities which are given in our impressions with
physical content exhibit manifold differences. So also do the
intentional relations given in our impressions with psychical content.
And, as in the former case, the number of the senses is determined by
reference to those distinctions between sensuous qualities which are
most fundamental (called by Helmholtz distinctions of modality), so in
the latter case the number of fundamental classes of mental phenomena is
fixed by reference to the most fundamental distinctions of intentional
relation.[20]

In this way we distinguish three fundamental classes. Descartes in his
_Meditations_[21] was the first to exhibit these rightly and completely;
but sufficient attention has not been paid to his observations, and they
were soon quite forgotten, until in recent times, and independently of
him, these were again discovered. Nowadays they may lay claim to
sufficient verification.[22]

The first fundamental class is that of ideas (Vorstellungen) in the
widest sense of the term (Descartes’ ideae). This class embraces
concrete impressions, those for example which are given to us through
the senses, as well as every abstract conception.

The second fundamental class is judgment (Descartes’ judicia). Previous
to Descartes these were thought of as forming, along with ideas, _one_
fundamental class, and since Descartes’ time philosophy has fallen once
more into this error. This view regarded judgment as consisting
essentially in a combination or relation of ideas to one another. This
was a gross misconception of its true nature. We may combine or relate
ideas as we please, as in speaking of a golden mountain, the father of a
hundred children, a friend of science; but as long as nothing further
takes place there can be no judgment. Equally true is it that an idea
always forms the basis of a judgment, as also of a desire; but it is not
true that, in a judgment, there are always several ideas related to one
another as subject and predicate. This is certainly the case when I say:
“God is just,” though not when I say: “There is a God.”

What, therefore, distinguishes those cases where I have not only an idea
but also a judgment? There is here added to the act of presentation a
second intentional relation to the object given in presentation, a
relation either of recognition or rejection. Whoever says: “God,” gives
expression to the idea of God; whoever says: “There is a God,” gives
expression to a belief in him.

I must not linger here, and can only assure you that this, if anything,
admits to-day of no denial. From the philological standpoint Miklosich
confirms the results of psychological analysis.[23]

The third fundamental class consists of the emotions in the widest sense
of the term, from the simple forms of inclination or disinclination in
respect of the mere idea, to joy and sadness arising from conviction and
to the most complicated phenomena as to the choice of ends and means.
Aristotle long since included these under the term Ὄρεζις. Descartes
says this class embraces the _voluntates sive affectus_. As in the
second fundamental class the intentional relation was one of recognition
or rejection, so in the third class it is one of love or hate, (or, as
it might be equally well expressed,) a form of pleasing or displeasing.
Loving, pleasing, hating, displeasing, these are given in the simplest
forms of inclination or disinclination, in victorious joy as well as in
despairing sorrow, in hope and fear, and in every form of voluntary
activity. “Plait-il?” asks the Frenchman; “es hat Gott gefallen,” one
reads in (German) announcements of a death; while the “Placet,” written
when confirming an act, is the expression of the determining fiat of
will.[24]


21. In comparing these three classes of phenomena it is found that the
two last mentioned show an analogy which, in the first, is absent. There
exists, that is, an opposition of intentional relation; in the case of
judgment, recognition or rejection, in the case of the emotions, love or
hate, pleasure or displeasure. The idea shows nothing of a similar
nature. I can, it is true, conceive of opposites, as for example white
and black, but whether I believe in this black or deny it, I can only
represent it to myself in one way; the representation does not alter
with the opposite act of judgment; nor again, in the case of the
feelings, when I change my attitude towards it according as it pleases
or displeases me.


22. From this fact follows an important conclusion. Concerning acts of
the first class none can be called either right or wrong. In the case of
the second class on the other hand, one of the two opposed modes of
relation, affirmation and rejection, is right the other wrong, as logic
has long affirmed. The same naturally holds good of the third class. Of
the two opposed modes of relation, love and hate, pleasure and
displeasure, in each case one is right the other wrong.


23. We have now reached the place where the notions of good and bad,
along with the notions of the true and the false which we have been
seeking, have their source. We call anything true when the recognition
related to it is right.[25] We call something good when the love
relating to it is right. That which can be loved with a right love, that
which is worthy of love, is good in the widest sense of the term.


24. Since everything which pleases does so, either for its own sake, or
for the sake of something else which is thereby produced, conserved or
rendered probable, we must distinguish between a primary and a secondary
good, i.e. what is good in itself, and what is good on account of
something else, as is specially the case in the sphere of the useful.

What is good in itself is the good in the narrower sense. It alone can
stand side by side with the true. For everything which is true is true
in itself, even when only mediately known. When we speak of good later
we shall therefore mean, whenever the contrary is not expressly
asserted, that which is good in itself.

In this way we have, I hope, made clear the notion of good.[26]


25. There follows now the still more important question: How are we to
know that anything is good? Ought we to say that whatever is loved and
is capable of being loved is worthy of love and is good? This is
manifestly untrue, and it is almost inconceivable that some have fallen
into this error. One loves what another hates, and, in accordance with a
well known psychological law already previously referred to it often
happens that what at first was desired merely as a means to something
else, comes at last from habit to be desired for its own sake. In such a
way the miser is irrationally led to heap up riches and even to
sacrifice himself for their sake. The actual presence of love,
therefore, by no means testifies unconditionally to the worthiness of
the object to be loved, just as affirmation is no unconditional proof of
what is true.

It might even be said that the first statement is even more _evident_
than the second, since it can hardly happen that he who affirms anything
at the same time holds it to be false, whereas it frequently happens
that a person, even while loving something, confesses himself that it is
unworthy of his love:

     “Video meliora proboque,
    Deteriora sequor.”

How then are we to know that anything is good?


26. The matter appears enigmatical, but the enigma finds a very easy
solution.

As a preliminary step to answering the question, let us turn our glance
from the good to the true.

Not everything which we affirm is on this account true. Our judgments
are frequently quite blind. Many a prejudice which we drank in, as it
were, with our mother’s milk presents to us the appearance of an
irrefutable principle. To other equally blind judgments all men have, by
nature, a kind of instinctive impulsion, as, for example, in trusting
blindly to the so-called external impression, or to a recent
remembrance. What is so recognized may often be true, but it may equally
well be false since the affirming judgment contains nothing which gives
to it the character of rightness.

Such, however, is the case in certain other judgments, which in
contradistinction to these blind judgments may be termed “obvious,”
“self-evident” judgments; as, for example, the Principle of
Contradiction, and every so-called inner perception which informs me
that I am now experiencing sensations of sound or colour, or think and
will this or that.

In what, then, does the distinction between these lower and higher forms
of judgment essentially consist? Is it a distinction in the degree of
belief, or is it something else? It is not a distinction in the degree
of belief; the instinctive blind assumptions arising from habit are
often not in the slightest degree weakened by doubts, and we are unable
to get rid of some even when we have already seen their logical falsity.
But such assumptions are the results of blind impulse, they have nothing
of the clearness peculiar to the higher forms of judgment. Were the
question to be raised: “What is then your reason for believing that?” no
rational answer would be forthcoming. It is quite true that if the same
inquiry were to be made respecting the immediately evident judgment here
also no reason could be given, but in face of the clearness of the
judgment the inquiry would appear utterly beside the point, in fact
ridiculous. Every one experiences for himself the difference between
these two classes of judgment, and in the reference to this experience,
consists, as in the case of every conception, the final explanation.


27. All this is, in its essentials, universally known,[27] and is
contested only by a few, and then not without great inconsistency. Far
fewer have noticed an analogous distinction between the higher and lower
forms of the feelings of pleasure and displeasure.

Our pleasure or displeasure is often quite like blind judgment, only an
instinctive or habitual impulse. This is so in the case of the miser’s
pleasure in piling up, in those powerful feelings of pleasure and pain
connected in men and animals alike with the appearance of certain
sensuous qualities, moreover, as is especially noticeable in tastes,
different species and even different individuals, are affected in a
quite contrary manner.

Many philosophers, and among them very considerable thinkers, have
regarded only that mode of pleasure which is peculiar to the lower
phenomena of the class, and have entirely overlooked the fact that there
exists a pleasure and a displeasure of a higher kind. David Hume, for
example, betrays almost in every word that he has absolutely no idea of
the existence of this higher class.[28] How general this oversight has
been may be judged from the fact that language has no common name for
it.[29] Yet the fact is undeniable and we propose now to elucidate it by
a few examples.

We have already said that we are endowed by nature with a pleasure for
some tastes and an antipathy for others, both of which are purely
instinctive. We also naturally take pleasure in clear insight,
displeasure in error or ignorance. “All men,” says Aristotle in the
beautiful introductory words of his _Metaphysics_,[30] “naturally desire
knowledge.” This desire is an example which will serve our purpose. It
is a pleasure of that higher form which is analogous to _self-evidence_
in the sphere of judgment. In our species it is universal. Were there
another species which, while having different preferences from us in
respect of sensible qualities, were opposed to us in loving error for
its own sake and hating insight, then assuredly we should not in the
latter as in the former case say: that it was a matter of taste, “de
gustibus non est disputandum”; rather we should here answer decisively
that such love and hatred were fundamentally absurd, that such a species
hated what was undeniably good, and loved what was undeniably bad in
itself. Now why, where the feeling of compulsion is equally strong, do
we answer differently in the one case than in the other? The answer is
simple. In the former case the feeling of compulsion was an instinctive
impulse; in the latter the natural feeling of pleasure is a higher love,
having the character of rightness.[31] We therefore notice when we
ourselves have such a feeling, that its object is not merely loved and
lovable, its opposite hated and unlovable, but also that the one is
worthy of love, the other worthy of hatred, and therefore that one is
good, the other bad.

Another example. As we prefer insight to error, so also, generally
speaking, we prefer joy (unless indeed it be joy in what is bad) to
sadness. Were there beings among whom the reverse held good, we should
regard such conduct as perverse, and rightly so. Here too it is because
our love and our hatred are qualified as right.

A third example is found in feeling itself so far as it is right and has
the character of rightness. As was the case with the rightness and
evidence of the judgment, so also the rightness and higher character of
the feelings are also reckoned as good, while love of the bad is itself
bad.[32]

In order that, in the sphere of ideas, we may not leave the
corresponding experiences unmentioned: here in the same way every idea
is found to be something good in itself, and that with every enlargement
in the realm of our ideas, quite apart from what of good or bad may
result therefrom, the good within us is increased.[33]

Here then, and from such experiences of love qualified as right, arises
within us the knowledge that anything is truly and unmistakably good in
the full extent to which we are capable of such knowledge.[34]

This last clause is added advisedly; for we must not, of course, conceal
from ourselves the fact that we have no guarantee that everything which
is good will arouse within us a love with the character of rightness.
Wherever this is not the case our criterion fails, and the good then, so
far as our knowledge and practical account of it are concerned, is as
much as non-existent.[35]


28. It is, however, not _one_ but many things which we thus recognize as
good. And so the questions remain: In that which is good, and especially
in what, as good, is attainable, which is the better? and further, which
is the highest practical good? so that it may become the standard for
our actions.


29. We must first inquire: When is anything better than anything else
and recognized by us as better? and what is meant by “the better” at
all?

The answer now lies ready to hand though not in such a way as to render
it unnecessary to exclude a very possible error. If by “good” is meant
that which is worthy of being loved for its own sake, then by “better”
appears to be meant that which is worthy of being loved with a greater
love. But is this really so? What is meant by “with greater love”? Is it
spatial magnitude? Hardly; no one would propose to measure pleasure or
displeasure in feet and inches. “The intensity of the pleasure,” some
will perhaps say, “is what is meant in speaking of love as great.”
According to this “better” would mean that which pleases with a more
intense pleasure. But such a definition closely examined would involve
the greatest absurdities. According to this view, each single case in
which joy is felt in anything would seem only to admit of a certain
measure of joy, whereas one would naturally think that it could not
possibly be reprehensible to rejoice in what is really good to the
fullest extent possible. Or, as we say, “with all one’s heart.”
Descartes has already observed that the act of loving (when directed
towards what is good at all) can never be too intense.[36] And he is
manifestly right. Were it otherwise what cautiousness should we not be
called upon to exercise considering the limits of our mental strength!
Every time one wished to rejoice over something good, an anxious survey
would be necessary respecting other existing goods in order that the
measure of proportion to our total strength might in no way be exceeded.
And if one believes in a God, understanding thereby the Infinite Good,
the Ideal of all ideals, then, since a man, even with his whole soul and
strength can only love God with an act of love of finite intensity he
will therefore be compelled to love every other good with an infinitely
small degree of intensity, and, since this is impossible, must cease as
a matter of fact to love it at all.

All this is manifestly absurd.


30. And yet it must be said that the better is that which is rightly
loved with a greater love, which is rightly more pleasing, though in
quite another sense. The “more” refers not to the relation of intensity
between the two acts, but rather to a peculiar species of phenomena
belonging to the general class of pleasure and displeasure, i.e., to the
phenomena of choice. Thereby are meant relating acts which in their
peculiar nature are known to every one in experience. In the province of
ideas there is nothing analogous. In the province of judgment there are,
it is true, alongside the simple, subjectless propositions, predicative
judgments which are acts of a relative character, but this resemblance
is very imperfect. The case here which has most similarity is that of a
decision respecting a dialectically propounded question: “Is this true
or false?” in which a sort of preference is given to one above the
other. But even here it is always something true which is, so to speak,
preferred to something false, never something more true over something
less true. Whatever is true is true in a like degree, but whatever is
good is not good in equal degree, and by “better” nothing else is meant
than what, when compared with another good, is preferable, i.e.
something which for its own sake, is preferred with a right preference.
For the rest a somewhat wider usage of language allows us also to speak
of a good as “better” over against a bad or purely indifferent, or even
to call something bad over against something still worse “the better.”
We then say not of course that it is good, but still better than the
other.

This shortly in explanation of the notion of the better.


31. Next the question: How do we know that anything is really the
better? Assuming the existence of simple knowledge of things as good and
bad, we appear, so analogy suggests, to derive this insight from certain
acts of preferring which have the character of rightness. For, like the
simple exercise of pleasure, so also the act of preferring is sometimes
of a lower or impulsive, and sometimes of a higher kind, and like the
evident judgment, is qualified as right. The cases in point are,
however, of such a nature that many might say, and perhaps with a better
right, that it is analytical judgments which furnish us here with the
means of progress, and that instead of our learning the preferability
from the actual preferences, the preferences have the qualification of
rightness because they already presume the recognition of the standard
of preferability.[37]

Chiefly belonging to this class are obviously (1) the case where we
prefer something good, and recognized as good, to something bad, and
recognized as bad. Also (2) the case where we prefer the existence of
something recognized as good to its non-existence, or the non-existence
of something recognized as bad to its existence.

This case embraces in itself a series of important cases, as the case
where we prefer a good to the same good with an admixture of the bad;
and, on the other hand, where we prefer something bad, with an admixture
of good, to the same bad purely for its own sake. Further, the cases in
which we prefer the whole of a good to its part, and again, the part of
something bad to its whole. Aristotle has already called attention to
the fact that in the case of the good the sum is always better than the
separate parts which together make up its sum. Such a case of summation
presents itself wherever a state has a certain permanence. The same
amount of joy which endures an hour is better than if it only lasted for
a moment. Whoever denies this, like Epicurus when he would console us on
account of the mortality of the soul, may easily be led into still more
striking absurdities. For then an hour’s torture would be no worse than
that of a moment. And, by combining both these propositions, we should
have to assume that an entire life full of joy with a single moment of
pain is in no way preferable to an entire life full of pain with a
single moment of joy. This is a result at which not only every sound
mind in general would demur, but also one respecting which Epicurus in
particular, expressly asserts the contrary.

Closely related to this is the case (3) where one good is preferred to
another, which, while forming no part of the first, is yet similar in
every respect to one of its parts. It is not merely by adding a good to
the same good but also by adding it to a good which is in every respect
similar that we get a better for total. The case is analogous when to a
similar bad another bad is thought of as added. When therefore, for
example, a fine picture is seen, the first time as a whole, the second
time only partially though exactly in the same way, we must then say
that the first view, considered in itself, is better: Or, when one
imagines something that is good and a second time not only imagines it
even as perfectly as before, but also loves it, this latter sum of
psychical acts is then something better.

Cases of difference in degree belong also to this third class, and are
especially worthy of mention. If one good, e.g. one joy is in every
respect quite equal to another, only more intense, then the preference
which is given to the more intense is qualified as right, the more
intense is the better. Conversely, the bad which is more intense, e.g. a
more intense pain, is worse. That is to say: the degree of intensity
corresponds with the distance from the zero point, and the distance of
the greater degree of intensity from zero is compounded of its distance
from the weaker degree of intensity plus the distance of this from zero.
We have, therefore, really to do with a kind of addition, a view which
has been disputed.


32. Many a one will, perhaps, think to himself that the three cases
which I have set forth are so self-evident and insignificant that it is
a matter for surprise that I have lingered over them at all.
Self-evident they are of course, and this must be so, since we have
here to do with what has to serve as a fundamentum. The case would be
worse if they were insignificant; for, I confess it frankly, I have
scarcely another further case to add: in all, or, at any rate, most of
the cases not here included a criterion fails us completely.[38]

An example. All insight is, we have said, something good in itself, and
all noble love is likewise something good in itself. We recognize both
these things clearly. But who shall say whether this act of insight or
that act of love is in itself, the better? There have, of course, not
been wanting those who have given a verdict on this point; some have
even asserted that it is certain every act of noble love for its own
sake is a good so high that, taken by itself, it is better than all
scientific insight taken together. In my judgment this view is not only
doubtful but altogether absurd. For a single act of noble love worthy as
it is, is yet a certain finite good. But every act of insight is also a
finite good and if I keep adding this finite quantity to itself _ad
libitum_, its sum is bound some time to exceed every given finite
measure of good. On the other hand, Plato and Aristotle were inclined to
regard the act of knowing considered in itself as higher than ethically
virtuous acts, this also quite unjustly, and I only mention it since the
opposition of opinions here is a confirmatory proof of the absence of
any criterion. As often happens in the sphere of the psychical,[39] so
also here, real measurements are impossible. Now where the inner
preference is not to be detected there holds good here what was said in
a similar case of simple goodness--as far as our knowledge and practical
concern go it is as good as non-existent.


33. There are some who, in opposition to the clear teaching of
experience, assert that only pleasure is good for its own sake, and
pleasure is _the_ good. Assuming this view to be right, would it have
the advantage, as many have believed, and as Bentham in particular
maintained in its favour,[40] that we should at once attain to a
determination of the relative value of goods, seeing that now we should
have only homogeneous goods and these admit of being measured side by
side? Every more intense pleasure would then be a greater good than one
less intense, and a good having double the intensity would be equal to
two of half the intensity. In this way everything would become clear.

A moment’s reflection only is needed to shatter an illusion born of such
hope. Are we really able to find out that one pleasure is twice as great
as another? Gauss[41] himself, who knew something about measurements,
has denied this. A more intense pleasure is never really made up of
twelve less intense pleasures distinguishable as equal parts within it,
as a foot is made up of twelve inches. So the matter presents itself
even in simpler cases. But how foolish would any one appear were he to
assert that the pleasure he had in smoking a good cigar increased 127,
or, let us say, 1077 times in intensity yielded a measure of the
pleasure experienced by him in listening to a symphony of Beethoven or
contemplating one of Raphael’s madonnas![42] I think I have said enough,
and do not need to allude to the further difficulty involved in
comparing the intensity of pleasure with that of pain.


34. Only therefore to this very limited extent are we able to derive
from experience a knowledge of what is better in itself.

I can well understand how any one, reflecting upon this for the first
time, will be led to fear that the great gaps which remain must, in
practice, prove in the highest degree embarrassing. Yet as we proceed
and make a vigorous use of what we do possess, we shall find that the
most sensible deficiencies may fortunately turn out harmless in
practice.


35. For, from the cases we adduced of preference qualified as right, the
important proposition follows that the province of the highest practical
good embraces everything which is subject to our rational operation in
so far as a good can be realized in such matter. Not merely the self but
also the family, the town, the state, the whole present world of life,
even distant future times, may here be taken into account. All this
follows from the principle of the summation of the good. To promote as
far as possible the good throughout this great whole, that is manifestly
the right end in life, towards which every act is to be ordered; that is
the one, the highest command upon which all the rest depend.[43]
Self-devotion and, on occasion, self-sacrifice are, therefore, duties;
an equal good wherever it be, and therefore in the person of another
also, is, in proportion to its value, and, therefore, everywhere equally
to be loved, and jealousy and malignant envy are excluded.


36. And now, since all lesser goods are to be made subservient to the
good of this widest sphere, light may also be shed from utilitarian
considerations upon those dark regions where before we found a standard
of choice wanting. If, for example, it was true that acts of insight and
acts of noble love are not to be measured as to their inner worth in
terms of one another, it is now clear that at any rate neither of these
two sides may be entirely neglected at the expense of the other. If one
person had perfect knowledge without noble love, and another perfect
noble love without knowledge, neither would be able to use his gifts in
the service of the still greater collective good. A certain harmonious
development and exercise of all our noblest powers seems, therefore,
from this point of view to be, at any rate, what we must strive
after.[44]


37. And now after seeing how many duties of love towards the highest
practical good come to light, we proceed to the origin of duties of law.
That association which renders possible a division of labour is the
indispensable condition of the advancement of the highest good as we
have learnt to understand it. Man therefore is morally destined to live
in society, and it is easily demonstrable that limits must exist in
order that one member of society may not be more of a hindrance than a
help to another,[45] and that these limits (though much in this respect
is settled by considerations of natural common-sense) require to be more
exactly marked by positive laws, and need the further security and
support of public authority.

And while in this way our natural insight demands and sanctions positive
law in general, it may, in particular, raise demands on the fulfillment
of which depends the measure of the blessing which the state of law is
to bring with it.

In this way does truth, bearing the supreme crown, give, or refuse, to
the products of positive legislation its sanction, and it is from this
crown that they derive their true binding force.[46] For as the old sage
of Ephesus says in one of his pregnant Sibyl-like utterances: “All human
laws are fed from the _one_ divine law.”[47]


38. Besides the laws referring to the limits of right, in every society
there are other positive enactments as to the way in which an individual
is to act inside his own sphere of right, how he is to make use of his
liberty and his property. Public opinion approves industry, generosity,
and economy each in its place, while disapproving idleness, greed,
prodigality and much else. In the statutes no such laws are to be found,
but they stand written within the hearts of the people. Nor are reward
and punishment lacking as regards this kind of positive law. These
consist in the advantages and disadvantages of good and bad reputation.
There exists here, as it were, a positive code of morality, the
complement of the positive code of law. This positive code of morality
also may contain both right and wrong enactments. To be truly binding
they need to be in accord with the rules which, as we have already seen,
are capable of recognition by the reason, as a duty of love towards the
highest practical good.

And so we have really found the natural sanction of morality which we
sought.


39. I do not linger here to show how this sanction operates. Every one
would rather say to himself: “I am acting rightly,” than “I am acting
foolishly.” And to no one capable of recognizing what is better is this
fact entirely indifferent in choosing. In the case of some it is nearly
so, whereas for others it is of the very first importance. Innate
dispositions are themselves diverse and much advance may be made by
education and one’s own ethical conduct. Enough, truth speaks, and
whoever is of the truth hears her voice.


40. Throughout the multiplicity of derived laws graven by nature herself
upon the tables of the law, utilitarian considerations, as we have seen,
form the standard. As now, in different situations, we resort to
different means, so also with regard to these different situations
different special precepts must hold good. They may be quite conflicting
in their tenour without of course being really contradictory, since they
are intended for different circumstances. In this sense, then, a
relativity in ethics is rightly asserted.

Ihering has drawn attention to this,[48] but he is not as he seems to
think, one of the first. On the contrary the doctrine was known of old
and is insisted upon by Plato in his _Republic_.[49] Aristotle in his
_Ethics_, and with special emphasis in his _Politics_ has affirmed
it.[50] The scholastic philosophers also held fast to the doctrine, and
in modern times men even of such energetic ethical and political
convictions as Bentham[51] have not denied it. If the fanatics of the
French Revolution failed to recognize it, still the clear-headed among
their fellow-citizens, even in that time, did not fall into such a
delusion. Laplace, for example, in his _Essai philosophique sur les
probabilités_ occasionally bears witness to the true teaching and raises
his voice in warning.[52]

Thus it happens that the distinguished investigator who has disclosed to
us the spirit of Roman law and to whom, as the author of _Der Zweck im
Recht_, we also are bound in many respects to tender our thanks, has yet
here, as we see, done nothing else than render the doctrine unclear by
confounding it with an essentially different and false doctrine of
relativity. According to this doctrine, no proposition in ethics, not
even the proposition that the best in the widest sphere ought to be the
determining standard of action, would have unexceptional validity. In
primitive times and even later, throughout long centuries, such a
procedure would, he expressly says, have been as immoral as, in later
times, the opposite conduct. We must, he thinks, on looking back into
the times of cannibalism sympathize rather with the cannibals, and not
with those who perhaps, in advance of their time, preached even then the
universal love of neighbour.[53] These are errors which have been
crushingly refuted not merely by philosophical reflection upon the
fundamental principles of ethics, but also by the successes of Christian
missionaries.


41. Thus the road leading to the goal which we set before us has been
traversed. For a time it led us through strange and rarely trodden
districts, finally, however, the results at which we have arrived smile
upon us like old acquaintances. In declaring love of neighbour and
self-sacrifice, both for our country and for mankind to be duties, we
are only echoing what is proclaimed all around us. We should also find
by going further into particulars that lying, treachery, murder,
debauchery and much besides that is held to be morally base are,
measured by the standard of the principles we have set up, condemned,
one as unjust, another as immoral.

All this would seem, in a measure, familiar to us as the shores of his
native land to the sea-farer when, after a voyage happily consummated,
he sees them rise suddenly into view, and the smoke curling from the old
familiar chimney.


42. And certainly we are at liberty to rejoice over this. The absolute
clearness with which all this follows is good omen for the success of
our undertaking, since it is the method by which we arrived at our
result, which is obviously the most essential feature in it. Without it
what advantage can our inquiry be said to have over that of others?
Even Kant, for example, whose doctrines concerning the principles of
ethics were quite different, arrived, in the further course of his
statement, pretty much to the popular view. But what we miss in him is
strict logical coherence. Beneke has shown that the Categorical
Imperative as Kant used it, may be so employed as to prove, in the same
case, contradictory statements and so everything and nothing.[54] If,
none the less, Kant is able to arrive so often at right conclusions,
this must be attributed to the fact that from the outset he had
harboured such opinions. Even Hegel, had he not known in other ways that
the sky was blue, would certainly never have succeeded by means of his
dialectic in deducing this _à priori_. Did he not equally succeed in
demonstrating that there were seven planets, a number accepted in his
day, but which in our time science has long left behind?

The causes of this phenomenon, therefore, are easily understood.


43. But there is another point which appears enigmatical. How does it
happen that the prevailing public opinion respecting law and morality is
itself, in so many respects, obviously right? If a thinker like Kant was
unable to discover the sources from which ethical knowledge flows, how
can we believe that the common folk succeeded in drawing therefrom? And
if this were not the case, how were they able, while ignorant of the
premises, still to reach the conclusions? Here the phenomenon cannot
possibly be explained from the fact that the right view was long before
established.

This difficulty also resolves itself in a very simple manner when we
reflect that much in our store of knowledge exists, and contributes
towards the attainment of new knowledge, without the knowledge of the
process itself being clearly present to consciousness.

It must not be supposed that in saying this I am an adherent of the
wonderful philosophy of the unconscious. I am speaking here only of
undeniable and well known truths. Thus it has often been observed that
for thousands of years men have drawn right conclusions without bringing
the procedure and the principles which form the condition of the formal
validity of the inference into clear consciousness by means of
reflection. Indeed when Plato first took the step of reflecting upon it,
he was led to set up an entirely false theory which assumed that every
inference was a process of reminiscence.[55] What was perceived and
experienced on earth recalled to the memory knowledge acquired in a
pre-mundane existence. Nowadays this error has disappeared. Still, false
theories concerning the fundamental principles of syllogism are
continually emerging, as, for example, when Albert Lange,[56] finds them
in space-perceptions and in synthetic propositions _à priori_, or
Alexander Bain[57] in the experience that the moods Barbara, Celarent,
etc., have up to the present time been found to be valid in every case:
mere crude errors which overlook the immediate intuitions forming the
conditions of right conclusions, but which do not prevent Plato, Lange,
and Bain from arguing in general exactly like other people. In spite of
their false conception of the true fundamental principles, these still
continue to operate in their reasoning.

But why do I go so far for examples? Let the experiment be made with the
first “plain man” who has just drawn a right conclusion, and demand of
him that he give you the premises of his conclusion. This he will
usually be unable to do and may perhaps make entirely false statements
about it. On requiring the same man to define a notion with which he is
familiar, he will make the most glaring mistakes and so show once again
that he is not able rightly to describe his own thinking.


44. Meantime, however dark the road to ethical knowledge might appear,
both to the “plain man” and to the philosopher, we must still expect,
since the process is a complicated one and many combined principles
operate therein, that the traces of the operation of each separate
principle will be evident in history, and this fact, even more than
agreement in respect of the final results, is a confirmation of the
right theory.

This also, if only the time permitted, in what fulness would I not be
able to lay before you! Who is there, for example, who would not, as we
have done, regard joy as something evidently good in itself, if only it
were not joy in what is bad. Nor has there been any lack of writers on
ethics who have asserted that pleasure and the good were strictly
identical conceptions.[58] Opposed to these were others who bore witness
to the inner worth of insight and such will be supported by all
unprejudiced minds. Many philosophers have wished to exalt knowledge
above all else as the highest good.[59] They recognized, however, at the
same time, a certain inner worth in each act of virtue, while others
have carried this view so far as to recognize only in virtuous action
the highest good.[60]

On the one hand, therefore, we have had sufficient confirmatory tests in
support of our view.

Next with regard to the principles of choice, how often do we not see
the principle of summation applied as, for example, when it is said that
the measure of the happiness of life as a whole and not that of the
passing moment is to be considered.[61] And, again, passing beyond the
limits of the self, when, for example, Aristotle says, that the
happiness of a nation seems to be a higher end than that of an
individual happiness,[62] and that in the same way in a work of art, or
in an organism and similarly in the case of the family, the part always
exists for the sake of the whole; everything is here subordinate to the
“common” (“εἰς τὀ κοινόν”).[63] Even in the case of the whole creation
he makes the same principle hold good. “In what,” he asks,[64]
“regarding all created things consists the good, and the best, which is
its final aim”? Is it immanent or transcendent? And he answers: “Both,”
setting forth as the transcendent aim the divine first cause, likeness
to which everything strives after, while the immanent aim is the
world-order as a whole. The like testimony to the principle of summation
might be taken from the lips of the Stoics.[65] It reappears in every
attempt to construct a theodicy from Plato down to Leibnitz and even
later.[66]

In the precepts of our popular religion, again, the operation of this
principle is also distinctly visible. When it ordains us to love our
neighbour as ourselves, what else is taught but that, in the right
choice, equality (be it our own or that of others) shall fall with equal
weight into the balance, from which follows the subordination of the
single individual to the good of the collective whole; just as the
ethical ideal of Christianity--the Saviour--offers himself as a
sacrifice for the salvation of the world.

And when it is said: “Love God above all else” (and Aristotle also says
that God is much rather to be called the best than the world as a
whole),[67] here also there is a special application of the law of
summation. For how else do we think of God than as the sum of all that
is good raised to an infinite degree?

And so the two propositions: that we should love our neighbour as
ourselves, and love God above all else, are manifestly so closely
related that we are no longer surprised to find added the words that the
one law is like unto the other. The law that we are to love our
neighbour, it should be carefully noted, is not subordinated to that of
love of God, and derived from it, it is, according to the Christian
view, not right because God has required it, rather he requires it
because it is by nature right;[68] and this rightness is made manifest
in the same way, and with the same clearness by means, so to speak, of
the same ray of natural knowledge.

Sufficient testimony has perhaps been offered to the shaping operation
of those factors which have been separately set forth by us, and so we
have, on the one hand, a strengthening of our theory while, on the other
hand, we have in essentials the explanation of that paradoxical
anticipation of philosophical results.


45. We are not to suppose, however, that all has now been said. Not
every opinion regarding law and morality holding good in society to-day,
and which has also the sanction of ethics, flows from these pure and
noble sources which, even when hid, have none the less discharged their
waters in rich abundance. Many such views have arisen in a way quite
unjustifiable from a logical point of view, and an inquiry into the
history of their origin shows that they take their rise in lower
impulses, in egoistic desires through a transformation due, not to
higher influences, but simply to the instinctive force of habit. It is
really true, as so many utilitarians have pointed out, that egoism
prompts men to make themselves agreeable to others and that such
conduct continually practised, develops finally into a habit which is
blind to the original ends. The chief reason for this is the limits of
our mind, the so-called “narrowness of consciousness,” which does not
allow of our always keeping clearly before us the more remote and final
ends side by side with what is immediately in question. In such a way
many a one may be frequently led, by the blind force of habit, to have
regard also for the well-being of others with a certain
self-forgetfulness. Further, it is true, as some have particularly
insisted, that in history it must often have happened that a powerful
person has selfishly reduced to subjection a weaker individual, and
transformed him by force of habit more and more into a willing slave.
And then in this slave-soul an αὐτὀς ἒφα comes in the end to operate
with a blind, but none the less powerful force, an impelling “you
ought,” as though it were a revelation of nature regarding good and bad.
On every violation of a command he feels himself, like a well-trained
dog, uneasy and inwardly tormented. When such a tyrant had, in this way,
reduced many to subjection his prudent egoism would cause him to give
commands helpful to the maintenance of his horde. These orders would in
the same slavish manner become habitual, and as it were, natural to his
subjects. And so regard for the whole of this community would gradually
become for each subject something into which he felt himself driven in
the manner above described. At the same time, we may easily recognize
how, owing to the constant care exercised towards his subjects, habits
must be formed in the tyrant himself favourable to a regard for the
welfare of the community. It may even happen at last that, just as in
the case of the miser, who sacrifices himself for the sake of his gold,
the tyrant may be ready to die for the maintenance of his people.
Throughout the whole process thus described ethical principles do not
exercise the slightest influence. The compulsion which in this way
arises, and the opinions which as a result approve or disapprove of a
certain procedure have nothing whatever to do with the natural sanction
and are devoid of all ethical worth. It may, however, be easily
understood--especially if one considers how one tribe enters into
relations with another and considerations of friendliness begin here too
to prove advantageous,--how this kind of training may lead, indeed one
may venture to say _must_, sooner or later, lead to opinions in
agreement with the principles springing from a true appreciation of the
good.


46. Thus also the blind, purely habitual expectation of similar events
under similar circumstances which animals, and also we ourselves,
practise in countless instances, often coincide with the results which a
complete induction according to the principles of the calculation of
probability would, in the same case, have brought about. The very
similarity of result has led people even with a psychological
education,[69] to regard the two processes as exactly identical,
although they stand wide as the poles asunder, the one completing itself
by means of a purely blind instinct, while the other is illumined by
mathematical evidence. We ourselves should, therefore, be well on our
guard against supposing in such pseudo-ethical developments the
concealed influence of the true ethical sanction.


47. Great, however, as is the contrast, still even these lower processes
have their worth. Nature--and this has been often insisted
on[70]--frequently does well in leaving much which concerns our welfare
to instinctive impulses like hunger and thirst rather than leave
everything to our reason. This, also, is confirmed in our case.

In those very early times in which, as I conceded to Ihering, (why you
will, perhaps, now be better able to see,) nearly every trace of ethical
thought and feeling was absent, much nevertheless was done which was a
preparation for true virtue. Public laws, however much in the first
instance established under the influence of lower motives, were yet
preliminary conditions for the free unfolding of our noblest capacities.

Nor is it a matter of no consequence that, under the influence of this
training, certain passions became moderated and certain dispositions
implanted which made it easier to follow the true moral law in the same
direction. Catiline’s courage was assuredly not the true virtue of
courage if Aristotle is right when he says that they only have such who
go to danger and to death “τοῦ καλοῦ ἔνεκα,” “for the sake of the
morally beautiful.”[71] Augustine might have made use of this instance
when he said: “virtutes ethnicorum splendida vitia.” But who will deny
that if such a man as Catiline had been converted, the dispositions he
had acquired earlier would have made it easier for him to venture to
extremes in the service of the good too? In this way, the ground was
made receptive for the admission of truly ethical impulses and therein
lay a powerful encouragement to the propagation of truth on the part of
those who were foremost in the discovery of ethical knowledge, and first
to hear the voice of a natural sanction. It is in this sense that
Aristotle observed that it is not every one who can study ethics. He who
is to hear about law and morality, must be already well conducted by
dint of habit. In the case of others, he thinks, it is but a waste of
pains.[72]

Indeed, still more may be said in praise of the services rendered to the
recognition of natural law and morality by these pre-ethical, though not
pre-historical, times. The legal ordinances and customs formed in this
time, owing to the reasons previously assigned, approached so closely to
what ethics demands, that this peculiar kind of mimicry blinded many to
the absence of a more thorough going affinity. What, in the one case, a
blind impulse and in the other, knowledge of the good exalts into a law,
is often completely the same in substance. The legislative moral
authority found therefore in these already codified laws and customs the
rough drafts, as it were, of laws, which with a few changes, it could
sanction without more ado. These were the more valuable because, as
seems required from a utilitarian point of view, they were adapted to
the special circumstances of the people. A comparison of the one
constitution with the other made this noticeable, and early helped to
lead to the important knowledge of the real relativity of natural right
and of natural morality. Who knows whether otherwise, it would have been
possible, even for an Aristotle, to succeed to the degree in which he
did in steering clear of all cut and dried doctrinaire theories?

So much, therefore, concerning the pre-ethical times, in order that
these may not be denied the acknowledgment which they deserve.


48. Nevertheless it was then night; though a night which heralded the
coming day, and the dawn of that day witnessed assuredly the most
glorious sunrise which, in the history of the world is yet to rise into
full splendour. I say, is to rise, not has risen, for we still see the
light struggling with the powers of darkness. True ethical motives, in
private as in public life, are still far from being everywhere the
determining standard. These forces--to use the language of the
poet[A]--prove themselves still too little developed to hold together
the structure of the world; and so nature,--and we have need to be
thankful that it is so--keeps the machine going by hunger and love, and,
we must also add, by all those other dark strivings which, as we have
seen, may be developed from self-seeking desires.

 [A] Schiller.


49. Of these, and their psychological laws the jurist must, therefore,
if he would truly understand his time, and influence it beneficially,
take cognizance, as well as of the doctrines of natural right and
natural morality which our inquiry has shown to be not the first but--in
so far as hope in the realization of a complete ideal may be cherished
at all--will be the last in the history of the development of law and
morality.

Thus the near relationships of jurisprudence and politics of which
Leibnitz spoke, become evident in their full range.

Plato has said: “It will never be well with the state until the true
philosopher is king, or kings philosophize rightly.” In our
constitutional times we should express ourselves better by saying that
there will never be a change for the better regarding the many evils in
our national life until the authorities, instead of abolishing the
limited philosophical culture required for law students by the existing
regulations, shall rather strive hard to secure that for their noble
profession they shall really receive an adequate philosophical culture.



NOTES


 [1] (_p. 2_). Cf. “Über die Entstehung des Rechtsgefühls.” Lecture by
 Dr. Rudolf von Ihering, delivered before the Vienna Law Society, March
 12, 1884 (_Allgem. Juristenzeitung_, 7 Jahrg., No. 11 seq., Vienna,
 March 16-April 13, 1884). Cf. further, v. Ihering, _Der Zweck im
 Recht_, vol. ii. Leipzig, 1877-83.

 [2] (_p. 2_). For the first point, cf. _Allgem. Juristenzeitung_, 7
 Jahrg. p. 122 seq., _Zweck im Recht_, vol. ii. p. 109 seq. For the
 second point _Allgem. Juristenzeitung_, 7 Jahrg. p. 171, _Zweck im
 Recht_, pp. 118-123. It is here denied that there is any absolutely
 valid ethical rule (pp. 118, 122 seq.); further every “psychological”
 treatment of ethics, according to which ethics is represented “as twin
 sister of logic” is contested.

 [3] (_p. 4_). _Allgem. Juristenzeitung_, 7 Jahrg., p. 147; cf. _Zweck
 im Recht_, vol. ii. p. 124 seq.

 [4] (_p. 4_). Aristotle, _Politics_, i. 2, p. 1252 b. 24.

 [5] (_p. 4_). Cf. e.g. _Allgem. Juristenzeitung_, 7 Jahrg. p. 146.

 [6] (_p. 5_). _Rep._ 2. 31.

 [7] (_p. 5_). _Dig._ 1. 8, 9.

 [8] (_p. 6_). Amongst the numerous adherents of this view and one of
 its best advocates is J. S. Mill in his _Utilitarianism_, chap. iii.

 [9] (_p. 6_). Here also, along with many others, J. S. Mill may
 be cited. The motives of hope and fear are, according to him, the
 _external_; the motives first described, the feelings developed by
 habit, the internal sanction. _Utilitarianism_, chap. iii.

 [10] (_p. 7_). Cf. espec. here a discussion in James Mill’s _Fragment
 on Mackintosh_, printed by J. S. Mill in the second edition of his
 _Analysis of the phenomena of the human mind_, vol. ii. p. 309 seq.;
 and Grote’s powerful essay published by A. Bain under the title,
 “_Fragments on Ethical Subjects_, by the late George Grote, F.R.S.,”
 being a selection from his posthumous papers, London, 1876; Espec.
 Essay 1, _On the Origin and Nature of Ethical Sentiment_.

 [11] (_p. 9_). D. Hume, _An Enquiry concerning the Principles of
 Morals_, London, 1751.

 [12] (_p. 9_). Herbart, _Lehrbuch zur Einleitung in die Philosophie_,
 81 seq. _Collected Works_, vol. i. p. 124 seq.

 [13] (_p. 9_). This comparison with logic should be my best defence
 against the charge of placing Herbart’s doctrine in a false light.
 Were the logical criterion to consist in judgments of taste
 experienced on the appearance of thought-processes in accordance with
 or opposition to rule, it would then, in comparison with what it
 actually is (the internal self-evidence of a process in accordance
 with rule) have to be called external. Similarly Herbart’s criterion
 of ethics is rightly characterized as external, however loudly
 Herbartians may insist that in the judgment of taste which arises
 spontaneously on the contemplation of certain relations of will, an
 inner superiority regarding these relations is recognizable.

 [14] (_p. 10_). In his _Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten_, Kant
 enunciates his Categorical Imperative in the following forms: “Act
 only in accordance with that maxim which you can at the same time
 will should become a universal law,” and “Act as if the maxim of your
 action were by your will to be raised to a universal law.”

 In the _Critique of Practical Reason_ it runs “Act so that the
 maxim of your will could on each occasion be valid as a universal
 legislative principle,” i.e. as Kant himself explains, in such a way
 that the maxim, when raised to a universal law, does not lead to
 contradictions and consequent self-abrogation. The consciousness of
 this fundamental law was, for Kant, a fact of pure reason, thereby
 proclaiming itself to be legislative (sic volo sic jubeo). Beneke has
 already observed (_Grundlinien der Sittenlehre_, vol. ii. p. xviii.,
 1841; cf. his _Grundlegung zur Physik der Sitten_, a counterpart to
 Kant’s _Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten_, 1822) that it is
 nothing more than a “psychologische Dichtung,” and to-day no one able
 to judge is any longer in doubt concerning it. It deserves to be noted
 that even philosophers like Mansel, who have the highest reverence
 for Kant, admit that the Categorical Imperative is a fiction and
 absolutely untenable.

 The Categorical Imperative has at the same time another and not less
 serious defect, i.e. that even when admitted, it leads to no ethical
 conclusions. Kant fails, as Mill (_Utilitarianism_, chap. i.) rightly
 says “in an almost grotesque fashion” to deduce what he seeks. His
 favourite example of a deduction, by which he illustrates his manner
 of procedure not only in his _Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten_
 but also in the _Critique of Practical Reason_ is as follows: May
 a person, he asks, retain for himself a possession which has been
 entrusted to him without a receipt or other acknowledgment? He
 answers, No. For he thinks, were the opposite maxim to be raised to
 a law, nobody, under such circumstances, would entrust anything to
 anybody. The law would then be without possibility of application,
 therefore impracticable and so self-abrogated.

 It may easily be seen that Kant’s argumentation is false, indeed
 absurd. If, in consequence of the law, certain actions ceased to be
 practised, the law exercises an influence; it therefore still exists
 and has in no way annulled itself. How ridiculous would it appear if
 the following question were treated after an analogous fashion: “May
 I yield to a person who desires to bribe me?” Yes, since, were I to
 think of the opposite maxim as raised to a universal law, then nobody
 would seek any longer to bribe another; therefore the law would be
 without application, therefore, impracticable, and so self-abrogated.

 [15] (_p. 11_). Cf. J. S. Mill, _System of Deductive and Inductive
 Logic_, vol. iv. chap. iv. section vi. (towards the end); vol. vi.
 chap. ii. section iv. and elsewhere, e.g. in his _Utilitarianism_,
 _Essays on Religion_, and in his article on _Comte and Positivism_,
 part ii.

 [16] (_p. 11_). Cf. with what has been said in the lecture the first
 chapter of the Nicomachian Ethics, and it will be seen that Ihering’s
 “fundamental thought” in his work _Der Zweck im Recht_, vol. i. p.
 vi., viz.: “that no legal formula exists which does not owe its origin
 to an end,” is as old as ethics itself.

 [17] (_p. 12_). Cases may arise where the consequence of certain
 efforts remains in doubt, and two courses are open: one presenting
 the prospect of a greater good but with less probability, the other a
 lesser good but with a greater probability. In choosing here, account
 must be taken of the degree of probability. If A is three times better
 than B, but B has ten times as many chances of being attained as A,
 then practical wisdom will prefer course B. Supposing that, under
 like circumstances, such a procedure always takes place, then (in
 accordance with the law of great numbers) the better would, generally
 speaking, be realized, a sufficient number of cases being assumed,
 and so such a manner of choosing would still obviously correspond to
 the principle laid down in the text, i.e. “Choose the best that is
 attainable.” The full significance of this remark will be made still
 more evident in the course of the inquiry.

 [18] (_p. 12_). This truth was familiar to Aristotle (cf. e.g. _De
 Anima_, iii. 8). The Middle Ages maintained it, but expressed it
 unfortunately in the proposition: _nihil est in intelluctu, quod
 non prius fuerit in sensu_. The notions “willing,” “concluding” are
 not gained from sensuous perception; the term “sensuous” would in
 that case have to be taken so generally that all distinction between
 “sensuous” and “super-sensuous” disappears. These notions have
 their origin in certain concrete impressions with psychical content
 (Anschauungen psychischen Inhalts). From the same source arise the
 notions “end,” “cause” (we observe, for example, a causal relation
 existing between our belief in the premises and in the conclusion),
 “impossibility” and “necessity” (we gain these from judgments which
 accept or reject not merely assertorically, but, as it is usually
 expressed, apodictically,) and many other notions which some modern
 philosophers, failing in detecting the true origin of them, have
 sought to regard as categories given _à priori_. I may mention, by
 the way, that I am well aware Sigwart and others influenced by him
 have recently questioned the peculiar nature of apodictic as opposed
 to assertorical judgments. But this is a psychological error which it
 is not the place to discuss here. Cf. note 27, p. 83 sub.

 [19] (_p. 12_). This doctrine in germ is also found in Aristotle; cf.
 espec. _Metaph._: Δ 15, p. 1021 a. 29. This term “intentional,” like
 many other terms for important notions, comes from the scholastics.

 [20] (_p. 13_). The question of the grounds of this division
 is discussed in more detail in my _Psychologie vom empirischen
 Standpunkte_ (1874, Bk. ii. chap. vi.; cf. also chap. i. section 5).
 The statements there made regarding this division I still consider to
 be substantially correct in spite of many modifications respecting
 points of detail.

 [21] (_p. 13_). Meditat. iii. “Nunc autem ordo videtur exigere, ut
 prius omnes meas cogitationes (all psychical acts) in certa genera
 distribuam.... Quaedam ex his tanquam rerum imagines sunt, quibus
 solis proprie convenit _ideae_ nomen, ut cum hominem, vel chimaeram,
 vel coelum, vel angelum, vel Deum cogito; aliae vero alias quasdam
 praeterea formas habent, ut cum volo cum timeo, cum affirmo, cum nego,
 semper quidem aliquam rem ut subjectum meae cogitationis apprehendo,
 sed aliquid etiam amplius quam istius rei similitudinem cogitatione
 complector; et ex his aliae _voluntates_ sive _affectus_ aliae autem
 _judicia_ appellantur.”

 Strangely enough this clear passage has not prevented Windelband
 (_Strassb. philos. Abhandl._ p. 171) from ascribing to Descartes the
 view that the judgment is an act of volition. What led him astray
 is a discussion in the fourth Meditation on the influence of the
 will in the formation of judgment. Even scholastics like Suarez had
 ascribed too much to this influence, and Descartes goes so far in
 exaggeration of this dependence that he considers every judgment (even
 the self-evident judgments) as the work of the will. But to “produce
 the judgment” and “to be the judgment” are yet manifestly not one
 and the same. And, therefore, although Descartes, in the passage
 cited, allows his view as to the influence of the will to appear, and
 probably it is only on this account that he assigns to the judgment
 the third place in the fundamental classification of psychical
 phenomena, yet none the less he says without contradiction: _aliae_
 voluntates--_aliae_ judicia appellantur.

 More illusive are a couple of passages in his later writings, i.e.
 in his _Principia Philosophiae_ (i. 32), published three years after
 the Meditations, and in a work also written three years later: Notae
 in Programma quoddam, sub finem Anni 1647 in Belgio editum, cum
 hoc Titulo: Explicatio mentis humanae sive animae rationalis, ubi
 explicatur quid sit, et quid esse possit.” Particularly might the
 passage in the _Principles_ lead to the opinion that Descartes must
 have changed his view, and it is astonishing that Windelband has not
 appealed to this passage rather than to that in the Meditations. We
 read here:--Ordines _modi cognitandi_ quos in nobis experimur, _ad
 duos generales_ referri possunt; quorum unus est, _perceptio sive
 operatio intellectus_; alius vero _volitio sive operatio voluntatis_.
 Nam sentire, imaginari, et pure intellegere, sunt tantum diversi modi
 percipiendi; _ut et cupere, aversari, affirmare, negare, dubitare,
 sunt diversi modi volendi_.

 At first sight this passage appears to be so clearly in contradiction
 to the one in the third Meditation that, as we have said, it is
 scarcely possible to avoid the supposition that Descartes had meantime
 rejected his thesis as to the three fundamental classes of psychical
 phenomena, so shunning Scylla only to plunge into Charybdis; avoiding
 the old mistake of confusing the judgment with the idea (Vorstellung),
 he would now seem to confound it with the will. But a more attentive
 examination of all the circumstances will suffice to exonerate
 Descartes from such a charge, and this on the following grounds: (1)
 There is not the slightest sign that Descartes was ever conscious of
 having become untrue to the view expressed in the Meditations. (2)
 Further, in the year 1647 (three years after the publication of the
 Meditations and shortly before writing the Notae to his Programma) the
 Meditations appeared in a translation revised by Descartes himself,
 where, remarkably enough, not the slightest alteration is to be
 found in the decisive passage in the third Meditation. “Entre mes
 pensées,” it reads, “quelques unes sont commes les images des choses,
 et c’est à celles-là scules que convient proprement le nom d’idée....
 D’autres, outre cela ont quelques autres formes; ... et de ce genre de
 pensées _les unes sont appelées volontés ou affections, et les autres
 jugements_.” (3) In the _Principles_ itself he says directly after
 (i. No. 42) that all our errors depend upon our will (a voluntate
 pendere); but so far is he from regarding the “error” as an act of
 volition, that he says there is no one who errs voluntarily (nemo est
 qui velit falli). Still clearer is it that he does not regard the
 judgment like the desires and dislikes as inner activities of the will
 itself, but only as a product of the will, since he at once adds:
 sed longe aliud est velle falli quam velle assentiri iis, in quibus
 contingit errorem reperiri,” etc. He does not say of the will that it
 desires, affirms, assents, but that it wills the assent; so also, not
 that it _is_ true but that it desires the truth (veritatis assequendae
 cupiditas ... _efficit_, ut ... judicium ferant).

 As to Descartes’ real view, therefore, there can be no doubt; his
 doctrine has not in this respect suffered the slightest change.
 It only remains, therefore, to come to an understanding of his
 obviously variable modes of expression, and this is, I believe,
 solved incontrovertibly in the following manner. Descartes, while
 regarding will and judgment as two classes differing fundamentally,
 none the less finds that in contradistinction to the first fundamental
 class--that of ideas--these have something in common. In the third
 Meditation he designates (cf. the above passage) as the common element
 the fact that although essentially based upon an idea, in both alike
 there is contained a further special form. In the fourth Meditation
 a further common character appears, i.e. that the will decides
 concerning them; not only can it determine and suspend its own acts,
 but also those of the judgment. It is this common character which he
 was bound to regard as especially, indeed all important, in the first
 part of the _Principles_, xxix.-xlii. Accordingly, he classes them, in
 opposition to the ideas (which he calls operationes intellectus) under
 the term operationes voluntatis. In the Notae to the Programma he
 calls them distinctly in the same sense, “determinationes voluntatis.”
 “Ego enim, cum viderem, praeter perceptionem, quae praerequiritur
 ut judicemus, opus esse affirmatione vel negatione ad formam
 judicii constituendam, _nobisque saepe esse liberum ut cohibeamus
 assensionem_, etiamsi rem percipiamus, ipsum actum judicandi, qui non
 nisi in assensu, hoc est in affirmatione vel negatione consistit, non
 retuli ad perceptionem intellectus sed ad determinationem voluntatis.”
 He does not even hesitate in the _Principles_ to term both these two
 classes of _modi cogitandi_, “_modi volendi_” the context seeming
 sufficiently to indicate that he means only to express thereby the
 fact that they fall within the domain of the will.

 In further support of this explanation we may compare the scholastic
 terminology into which Descartes as a young man was initiated. It was
 customary to denote under the term _actus voluntatis_ not merely the
 movement of the will itself but also the act performed in obedience
 to the will. In accordance with this custom, the _actus voluntatis_
 fell into two classes; the _actus elicitus voluntatis_ and the _actus
 imperatus voluntatis_. In a similar manner Descartes groups the class
 which, according to him, was only possible as an _actus imperatus_ of
 the will along with his _actus elicitus_. There is here, therefore, no
 question of a common fundamental character of the intentional relation.

 Clear as all this is to those who carefully attach due weight to
 the various moments, it would yet appear that Spinoza (probably
 misled rather by the passage in the _Principles_ than by that cited
 by Windelband), anticipates Windelband in this misunderstanding of
 the Cartesian doctrine. In his _Ethics_, ii. prop. 49, he actually,
 and in the most real sense, regards the _affirmatio_ and _negatio_
 as “_volitiones mentis_,” and by a further confusion, comes finally
 to obliterate the distinction between the two classes _ideae_ and
 _voluntates_. “_Voluntas et intellectus unum et idem sunt_” his thesis
 now reads, so overthrowing not only the three-fold classification of
 Descartes, but also the old Aristotelian dual classification. Spinoza
 has here, as usual, done nothing else than corrupt the teaching of his
 great master.

 [22] (_p. 13_). I do not mean to say that the classification is,
 universally recognized to-day. It would not even be possible to regard
 as certain the Principle of Contradiction if in order to do so we
 were to await universal assent. In the present instance it is not
 difficult to understand that old, deeply-rooted prejudices cannot all
 at once be banished. But that even under such circumstances it has not
 been possible to urge a single important objection affords the best
 confirmation of our doctrine.

 Some, as for instance, Windelband--while giving up the attempt at
 including judgment and idea (Vorstellung) in _one_ fundamental class,
 on the other hand believe it possible to subsume judgment under
 feeling, thus falling back into the error which Hume committed earlier
 in his inquiry into the nature of belief. According to these writers,
 to affirm implies an act of approval, an appreciation on the part of
 the feelings, while denial is an act of disapproval, a feeling of
 repugnance.

 Despite a certain analogy the confusion is hard to understand. There
 are people who recognize both the goodness of God and the wickedness
 of the devil, the being of Ormuzd and the being of Ahriman, with an
 equal degree of conviction, and yet, while prizing the nature of the
 one above all else, they feel themselves absolutely repelled by that
 of the other. Since we love knowledge and hate error it is, of course,
 proper that those _judgments_ we hold to be right (and this is true
 of all those judgments which we ourselves make) are for this very
 reason dear to us, i.e. we estimate them in some way or other through
 feeling. But who on this account would be misled into regarding the
 judgments themselves which are loved as acts of loving?. The confusion
 would be almost as gross as if we should fail to distinguish wife and
 child, money and possessions, from the activity which is directed
 towards these, inasmuch they are the objects of affection. Cf. also
 what has been said (note 21) with regard to Windelband, where,
 misunderstanding Descartes, he ascribes to him the same teaching;
 further, note 26 (on the unity of the idea of the good) as well as
 what is urged by Sigwart in the note (in part much to the point) on
 Windelband (_Logic_, vol. i. chap. ii. p. 156 seq.). To those who,
 despite all that has been said, still wish further arguments for the
 distinction between the second and third fundamental classes, I may,
 perhaps, be allowed to refer them, by anticipation, to my _Descriptive
 Psychology_, which I have alluded to in the preface as an almost
 completed work, and which will appear if not as a continuation, yet
 still as a further development of my _Psychology from the Empirical
 Standpoint_.

 As against Windelband, I here add the following observations:

 1. It is false and a serious oversight, as he himself will be
 convinced on reading again in my _Psychology_, vol. i. p. 262, when
 he (p. 172) makes me assert, and that too as a quotation from my own
 work, that “love and hate” is not an appropriate term for the third
 fundamental class.

 2. It is false, and a quite unjustifiable supposition when (p. 178)
 he ascribes to me the opinion that the classification of judgments
 according to quality is the only essential classification belonging
 to the act of judgment itself. I believe exactly the contrary. I
 regard, for example (of course in opposition to Windelband), the
 distinction between assertorical and apodictic judgments (cf. here
 note 27, p. 83), as also the distinction between self-evident and
 blind judgments as belonging and highly essential, to the act of
 judgment itself. Other differences, again, especially the distinction
 between simple and compound acts of judgment, I might mention. For
 it is not every compound judgment that can be resolved into quite
 simple elements, and something similar takes place also in the case
 of certain notions, a fact known to Aristotle. What is red?--Red
 colour. What is colour?--The quality of colour. The difference, it is
 seen, contains in both cases the notion of the genus. The separating
 of the one logical element from the other is only possible from the
 one side. A similar one-sided capacity to separate appears also in
 certain compound judgments. J. S. Mill is, therefore, quite wrong when
 he (_Deductive and Inductive Logic_, vol. i. chap. iv. section 3),
 regards as ridiculous the old classification of judgments into simple
 and compound, and thinks that the procedure in such a case is exactly
 as if one should wish to divide horses into single horses and teams
 of horses; otherwise the same argument would hold good against the
 classification of conceptions into simple and compound.

 3. It is false, though an error which finds almost universal
 acceptance, and one from which I myself at the time of writing the
 first volume of my _Psychology_ was not yet free, that the so-called
 degree of conviction consists in a degree of intensity of the
 judgment which can be brought into analogy with the intensity of
 pleasure and pain. Had Windelband charged me with _this_ error I
 would have acknowledged the complete justice of the charge. Instead
 of this he finds fault with me because I recognize intensity with
 regard to the judgment, only in a sense analogous, and not identical
 to that in the case of feeling, and because I assert the impossibility
 of comparing in respect of magnitude, the supposed intensity of the
 belief and the real intensity of feeling. Here we have one of the
 results of his improved theory of judgment!

 If the degree of conviction of my belief that 2 + 1 = 3 were one of
 intensity how powerful would this be! And if the said belief were to
 be identified, as by Windelband (p. 186), with feeling, not merely
 regarded as analogous to feeling, how destructive to our nervous
 system would the violence of such a shock to the feelings prove! Every
 physician would be compelled to warn the public against the study
 of mathematics as calculated to destroy health. (Cf. with regard to
 this so-called degree of conviction the view of Henry Newman in his
 interesting work: _An Essay in Aid of a Grammar of Assent_--a work
 scarcely noticed in Germany.)

 4. When Windelband (p. 183) wonders how I can regard the word “is” in
 such propositions as “God is,” “A man is” (ein Mensch ist), “A lack
 is” (ein Mangel ist), “A possibility is,” “A truth is,” (i.e. There is
 a truth), etc., as having the same meaning and finds it extraordinary
 (184, note 1) in the author of _Von der mannigfachen Bedeutung des
 Seienden nach Aristoteles_ that he should fail to recognize the
 manifold significance of “to be,” I can only reply that he who in
 this view does not perceive the simple consequence of my theory of
 the judgment can hardly have understood this doctrine. With regard to
 Aristotle it never occurs to him, while dividing the “ὄν” in the sense
 of reality into various categories, and into an “ ὂν ὲνεργεία and ὂν
 δυνάμει”, to do the same with the “ἔστιν” transforming what is the
 expression of an idea into that of a judgment and the “ὂν ὡς ἀληθές”
 as he calls it. This could only be done by those who, like Herbart
 and many others after him, did not know how to hold apart the notion
 of being in the sense of absolute position and being in the sense of
 reality (cf. the following note).

 5. I have just said that there exist simple and compound judgments,
 and that many a compound judgment is not, without a residue,
 resolvable into simple judgments. Special attention must be paid to
 this in seeking to convert judgments otherwise expressed into the
 existential form. It is self-evident that only simple judgments, i.e.
 such as are, strictly speaking, without parts, are so convertible. I
 may therefore be excused for not thinking it necessary to emphasize
 this expressly in my _Psychology_. If this restriction hold good
 universally it is, of course, valid also of the categorical form.
 In the propositions categorical in form, which the formal logicians
 have denoted by the signs A.E.I. and O. they wish to express strictly
 simple judgments. These are therefore one and all convertible into
 the existential form (cf. my _Psychology_, vol. i. p. 283). The same,
 however, will not hold good when propositions categorical in form
 contain in consequence of an ambiguity of expression (cf. p. 120, note
 to Appendix) a plurality of judgments. In such a case the existential
 form may certainly be the expression of a simple judgment equivalent
 to the compound one, but cannot be the expression of the judgment
 itself.

 This is a point which Windelband ought to have considered in examining
 (p. 184) the proposition: “The rose is a flower” with respect to its
 convertibility into an existential proposition. He is quite right
 in protesting against its conversion into the proposition: “There
 is no rose which is not a flower,” but he is not equally right in
 ascribing this conversion to me. Neither in the passage cited by him
 nor elsewhere have I made such a conversion, and I consider it just as
 false as that attempted by Windelband and all such as may be attempted
 by anybody else. The judgment here expressed in the proposition is
 made up of two judgments of which one is the recognition of the
 subject (whether it be that thereby is meant “rose” in the ordinary
 sense, or “what is called rose,” “what is understood by rose”), and
 this, as we have just said, is not always the case where a proposition
 is given of the form: All A is B.

 Unfortunately Land also has overlooked this, the only one among
 my critics who has succeeded in comprehending, in their necessary
 connection with the principle, what Windelband has termed the
 “mysterious” hints which I have thrown out towards the reform of
 elementary logic, and in deducing them correctly from it. (Cf. Land,
 “On a supposed improvement in Formal Logic” in the papers of the _Kgl.
 Niederländischen Akademie der Wissenschaften_, 1876.)

 I conclude with a curiosity recently furnished by Steinthal in his
 _Zeitschrift für Völkerpsychologie_ (chap. xviii. p. 175). I there
 read with astonishment: “Brentano’s confusion in completely severing
 judgments from idea and thoughts (!) and grouping the judgments as
 acts of recognition or rejection, with love and hate (!!) is instantly
 removed if such (?) a judgment, as an aesthetic judgment is termed
 “Beurteilen” (!). Probably Steinthal has never once glanced into my
 _Psychology_, and has only read Windelband’s statement concerning it;
 this, however, so hastily that I hope he will not be ungrateful at my
 sending his lines to Windelband for correction.

 [23] (_p. 14_). Miklosich, _Subjectlose Sätze_, second edition,
 Vienna, 1883.

 In order to make the reader familiar with the contents of this
 valuable little book a notice written at the time for the _Vienna
 Evening Post_ may prove useful. Through an oversight it was printed
 as a feuilleton in the Vienna newspaper. As no one certainly would
 look for it there, I will include it here by way of an appendix.
 Meantime, Sigwart’s monograph, _The Impersonalia_ has appeared, in
 which he opposes Miklosich. Marty has submitted this, as well as
 (shortly before) the corresponding section in Sigwart’s _Logic_ to a
 telling criticism in the _Vierteljahrsschrift für wissenschaftliche
 Philosopie_, with regard to which criticism Sigwart, though without
 any reasonable ground, has shown himself highly indignant. “Il se
 fache,” the French say, “donc il a tort.” That Sigwart’s theory in
 its essential points has not succeeded, even Steinthal really allows,
 though in his _Zeitschrift_ (chap. xviii. p. 172 seq.) he burns thick
 clouds of incense to the writer of the monograph, and even in his
 preface to the fourth edition of his _Origin of Language_ applauds
 a form of conduct which every true friend of that deserving man
 (Sigwart) must regret. After the high praise awarded to him at the
 outset, one feels somewhat disappointed finally by the criticism.
 Steinthal rejects (pp. 177-180) Sigwart’s theory on its grammatical
 side. There would only remain therefore as really successful Sigwart’s
 psychological theory. But the psychological portion is not that
 concerning which Steinthal’s estimate is authoritative; for in that
 case, one would be bound to take seriously the following remark: “In
 the proposition: “Da bückt sich’s hinunter mit liebendem Blick” (a
 line from Schiller’s _Diver_), it is obvious that everybody must think
 of the king’s daughter, but it is not she which stands before me but
 a subjectless “sich hinunter-bücken,” and now I have all the more
 fellow-feeling for her. According to my (Steinthal’s) psychology, I
 should say the idea of the king’s daughter “fluctuates” (schwingt) but
 does not enter into consciousness.” This calls for something more than
 the old saying: _Sapienti sat_.


 I

 The psychological theory of Sigwart shows itself in all its weakness
 when he seeks to give an account of the notion of “_existence_.” It
 has been already recognized by Aristotle, that this notion is gained
 by reflection upon the affirmative judgment. But Sigwart, like most
 modern logicians, neglects to make use of this hint. Instead of saying
 that to the existent belongs everything of which the affirmative
 judgment is true, he becomes repeatedly, and once more in the second
 edition of his logic (pp. 88-95) involved in diffuse discussions upon
 the notion of being and upon existential propositions, which cannot
 in any way conduce to clearness, seeing that they move in false
 directions.

 “To be,” according to Sigwart, expresses a relation (pp. 88, 95);
 if it be asked: What kind of a relation? the answer would, at first
 sight (92), appear to be, a relation to me as thinking. But no; the
 existential proposition asserts just this: “that the existing also
 exists, apart from its relation to me and to another thinking being.”
 It cannot, therefore, be “a relation to me as thinking.” But what
 other relation can be meant? Not until p. 94 is this brought out more
 clearly. The relation ought to mean (of course he adds “zunächst”,
 provisionally) the agreement (“identity” ib.) of the thing represented
 with a possible impression (“einem Wahrnehmbaren” ib. “something which
 may be perceived by me,” ib. p. 90).

 Now it will be immediately recognized that this notion of existence is
 too narrow; for it might very well be asserted that much exists which
 it is not possible to perceive, e.g. a past and a future, an empty
 space, and any sort of deficiency, a possibility or impossibility,
 etc., etc. It is therefore not surprising that Sigwart himself seeks
 to widen the notion. But he does this in a manner which I find it
 difficult to understand. At first sight he appears to say in order
 that something may exist it is not necessary that it can be perceived
 by me; it is enough if it can be perceived by anybody. Or what else
 can be meant when Sigwart, after what has just been said, that
 existence was the agreement of the thing represented with a possible
 impression, thus continues: “That which exists stands not merely _in
 this relation_ to me but to all other existing beings?” It cannot
 surely mean that Sigwart is inclined to ascribe to every existing
 being the capacity to receive every impression. It may be he only
 wishes to say that everything which exists stands to every other
 existing being in the relation of existence, and then it might be
 concluded from what immediately follows that this rather meaningless
 definition is intended to express that existence is the capacity to
 act or to be acted upon. (“What exists ... stands in causal relations
 to the rest of the world”; similar also is p. 91, note: the existent
 is something which “can exercise effects upon me and others.”)
 Finally, however, there is some ground for thinking Sigwart would
 say: what exists is that which can be perceived or can be inferred
 as perceivable, for he adds: “hence (on account of this causal
 relation) from what is _perceivable_ also an existence which is merely
 _inferred_ may be asserted.”

 That all this is equally to be rejected it is not difficult to
 recognize.

 For (1) To “infer” the existence of something does not mean so much as
 “to infer that it is capable of being perceived.” If, for example, the
 existence of atoms and of empty spaces could be assured by inference,
 we should still be very far from proving their perceptibility either
 to ourselves or to some other being. If any one were to conclude the
 existence of God while giving up the attempt “to give vividness” to
 the thought by anthropomorphic means, he would not on this account
 believe that God must be perceptible to one of his creatures or even
 that he is the object of his own perception.

 2. From this point of view it would be absurd for any one to say: “I
 am convinced that there is much the existence of which can neither be
 perceived at any time or even inferred by anybody.” For that would
 mean: “I am convinced that much can be perceived or can be inferred
 to be capable of perception which yet can never be perceived or
 inferred.” Who does not recognize here how far Sigwart has strayed
 from the true notion of existence!

 3. Should Sigwart wish in this passage to widen the notion of
 existence to such a degree as to think that existence is that which
 can either be perceived or inferred from some perceivable object, or
 again, stands in some sort of causal relation to what is perceivable,
 it might be replied--if indeed such a monstrous notion of existence
 still require refutation--that even this notion is still too narrow.
 If, for example, I say: It may be that an empty space exists but
 this can never with certainty be known by any one, I thereby confess
 that existence may perhaps belong to empty space; but I deny most
 definitely that it is perceptible, or that it is to be inferred from
 that which is perceptible. In regard to relations of cause and effect
 on the other hand, it is of course impossible that empty space (which
 is certainly no thing) can stand in such a relation to anything
 perceivable. We should thus once again arrive at an absurd meaning in
 interpretation of an assertion in no way absurd.

 How wrongly Sigwart has analysed the notion of existence is also
 proved very simply by means of the following proposition: A real
 centaur does not exist; a centaur _in idea_, however, certainly
 exists, and that as often as I imagine it. Whoever does not clearly
 recognize here the distinction of the “ὂν ὡς ἀληθές i.e. in the sense
 of existing, from ὂν in the sense of real (wesenhaft) will I fear
 hardly be brought to recognize it by the fullest illustrations which
 might be furnished by further examples. We may, however, also consider
 briefly the following point: According to Sigwart, the knowledge of
 the existence of anything consists in the knowledge of the agreement
 of something represented in idea with, let us say, χ, since I do
 not clearly understand with what. What now is necessary in order to
 recognize the agreement of something with something else? Manifestly,
 the knowledge of everything which is required in order that this
 agreement should really exist. But this requires (1) that the one
 element exist, (2) that the other element exist, and (3) that between
 them there exist the relation of identity since what does not exist
 can be neither like something nor different from it. But the knowledge
 of the first element constitutes already in itself a knowledge of
 existence. Hence the knowledge of the two remaining elements is no
 longer necessary to the recognition of any existence, and Sigwart’s
 theory leads to a contradiction. (Cf. with what has been said here,
 Sigwart’s polemic against my _Psychology_, book ii. chap. vii. in his
 work; _The Impersonalia_, p. 50 seq., and _Logic_, vol. i. second
 edition, p. 89 seq. note, as well as Marty’s polemic against Sigwart
 in the articles: “Über Subjectlose Sätze” in the _Vierteljahrsschrift
 für wissenschaftliche Philosophie_, viii. i. seq.)[A]

  [A] I had already written my Critique of Sigwart’s notion of existence
 when I became aware of a note in his _Logic_, second ed, p. 390, a
 passage which, while it has not made it necessary to alter anything
 which I had written, has led me to insert it for the purpose of
 comparison. “Das Seiende überhaupt,” Sigwart writes, “kann nicht als
 wahrer Gattungsbegriff zu dem einzelnen Seienden betrachtet werden;
 es ist, begrifflich betrachtet, nur ein gemeinschaftlicher Name.
 Denn, da ‘Sein’ für uns ein Relationsprädikat ist, kann es kein
 gemeinschaftliches Merkmal sein, es müsste denn gezeigt werden, dass
 dieses Prädikat in einer dem Begriffe alles Seienden gemeinsamen
 Bestimmung wurzle.” I fear that the reader will, just as little as
 myself, attain by this explanation to clearness concerning Sigwart’s
 notion of existence. He will perhaps the better understand why all my
 efforts regarding it have proved futile.
 s
 Sigwart has failed to grasp the nature of judgment in general he
 is not, of course, able to understand that of the _negative_ judgment
 in particular. He has gone so far in error as to deny to it an equal
 right as species along with the positive judgment; no negative
 judgment is, he thinks, a direct judgment, its object is rather always
 another actual judgment or the attempt to form such a judgment.

 In this assertion Sigwart is opposed to some important psychological
 views which I have made good in my lecture. It would therefore seem
 fitting to resist his attack. For this purpose I shall show: (1)
 that Sigwart’s doctrine is badly founded; (2) that it leads to an
 irremediable confusion, as in that case Sigwart’s affirmative judgment
 is a negative judgment, while his negative judgment if indeed a
 judgment at all, and not rather the absence of one, is a positive
 judgment, and that moreover his positive judgment really involves a
 negative one, along with other similar confusions. (3) Finally I think
 it will be possible--thanks to Sigwart’s detailed explanations--to
 show the genesis of his error.

 1. The first inquiry in the case of an assertion so novel and so
 widely diverging from the general view, will be as to its foundation.
 With regard to this, he insists above all (p. 150) that the negative
 judgment would have no meaning if the thought of the positive
 attribution of a predicate had not preceded. But what can this mean?
 Either there is here a clear _petitio principii_, or it cannot mean
 anything more than that a connection of ideas must have preceded. Now
 granting this for a moment (although I have in my _Psychology_ shown
 its falsity) this would by no means prove his proposition, since
 Sigwart himself recognizes (p. 89 note, and elsewhere) that such a
 “subjective connexion of ideas” would still not be a judgment; that
 there needs rather to be added to it a certain feeling of constraint.

 An argument follows later (p. 151) the logical connexion of which I
 understand just as little. It is rightly observed that in and for
 itself we have the right to deny of anything an infinite number of
 predicates, and it is with equal right added that in spite of this,
 we do not really pass all these negative judgments. And now what
 conclusion is drawn from these premisses? Perhaps this, that the
 fact that a certain negative judgment is warranted is not sufficient
 in itself to explain the entrance of the judgment. This we may
 without hesitation admit. But Sigwart concludes quite otherwise; he
 permits himself to assert, it follows from this that the further
 condition which is here lacking is that the corresponding positive
 affirmation has not yet been attempted. This is indeed a bold leap,
 and one which my logic at least is not able to follow. And why, if
 one were to inquire further, are not all the positive judgments here
 concerned really attempted? The most probable answer, judging by the
 examples given by Sigwart (this stone reads, writes, sings, composes;
 justice is blue, green, heptagonal, rotating), is, that this has
 not been done because the negative judgment has already been made
 with evident certainty; for this would best explain why there is no
 “danger of any one attributing these predicates to the stone or to
 justice.” If, however, any one prefer to answer that “the narrowness
 of consciousness” makes it impossible to attempt at the same time
 an infinite number of positive judgments, I am content with this
 expedient also, only it must then be asked if this appeal ought not to
 have been made directly and earlier, since Sigwart himself calls the
 possible negative judgments an “_immeasurable_ quantity.”

 It is also a curious error (Marty has already called attention to it),
 when Sigwart asserts that in contradistinction to what holds good of
 the negative judgment “every subject admits only of a limited number
 of predicates being affirmed.” But why? Can we not, for example, say a
 whole hour is greater than half an hour, greater than a third, greater
 than a fourth and so on _ad infin._?... If then, notwithstanding, I do
 not really make all these judgments, there are evidently good reasons
 for this; above all that the “narrowness of consciousness” forbids it.
 But then this might also be applied most successfully in regard to
 negative judgments.

 Somewhat later we meet a third argument which, as I have already by
 anticipation refuted it in my _Psychology_ (book ii. chap. 7, section
 v.), will be treated quite shortly here. If the negative judgment
 were a direct one, co-ordinated with the affirmative judgment as
 species then, thinks Sigwart (p. 155 seq.), whoever in an affirmative
 categorical proposition regards the affirmation of the subject as
 involved must, to be consistent, regard the denial of the subject
 as involved in the negative proposition, which is not the case. The
 latter observation is correct, the former assertion, however, quite
 untenable, as it involves in itself a contradiction. For exactly
 because the existence of each part in a whole is involved in the
 existence of the whole, the whole no longer exists if but one of its
 parts is missing.

 It only remains now to consider a point of language by which Sigwart
 believes himself able to support his view. A testimony for it is,
 he thinks, to be found in the fact that the symbol for the negative
 judgment is formed in every case by means of a combination with the
 symbol of affirmation, the word “not” being added to the copula. In
 order to judge what is here actually the fact, we will glance for a
 moment at the sphere of feeling. Sigwart agrees, I think, with me and
 everybody else that pleasing and displeasing, rejoicing and sorrowing,
 loving and hating, etc., are co-ordinate with each other. Yet a
 complete series of expressions denoting a disinclination of feeling
 are found in dependence upon the expression for the corresponding
 inclination. For example, inclination, disinclination; pleasure,
 displeasure; ease, disease; Wille, Widerwille; froh, unfroh; happy,
 unhappy; beautiful, unbeautiful; pleasant, unpleasant;--even “ungut”
 is used. The explanation of this is, I believe, not difficult for the
 psychologist, notwithstanding the equally primordial character of
 these opposite modes of feeling. Ought then the explanation of the
 phenomenon lying before us in the expression of the negative judgment,
 closely related as it is to the before mentioned phenomenon, to be
 really so very difficult, even assuming the primordial character?

 As a matter of fact the case must be very bad when thinkers like
 Sigwart in making statements so important in principle, and at the
 same time so unusual, have to resort to arguments so weak.

 2. The grounds on which Sigwart’s doctrine concerning the negative
 judgment rest have, therefore, each and all proved untenable. This
 must be so; for how could the truth of any doctrine be shown which
 would plunge everything into the greatest confusion?

 Sigwart finds himself compelled to distinguish between the positive
 and the affirmative judgment, and the affirmative judgment--one hears
 and wonders at the new terminology--is according to him, closely
 examined, a negative judgment. On page 150 he says literally: “The
 primordial judgment can certainly not be termed the affirmative
 judgment, but is better described as the positive judgment, for
 only in opposition to the negative judgment, and _in so far as it
 rejects_ the possibility of a negation, is the simple statement A is
 B an affirmation,” and so on. Inasmuch as it “rejects.” What else
 can that mean than “so far as it denies”? As a matter of fact only
 those negations can, according to this new and extraordinary use of
 language, be called affirmations! Yet this would really mean, and
 particularly when it is said that the proposition A is B _is_ often
 such a negation (cf. the expressions just quoted), that the use
 of language would be reduced to a confusion quite unnecessary and
 altogether unendurable.

 Not only is the affirmation--as set forth--according to Sigwart really
 a negation but also, paradoxical as it may seem, the negation, on
 close consideration, proves to be a positive judgment. It is true,
 Sigwart protests against those who, like Hobbes, would regard all
 negatives as affirmative judgments with negative predicates. But,
 following Sigwart, if this is not so, then these must be affirmative
 judgments with affirmative predicates, since he teaches that the
 subject is in every case a judgment, the predicate being the notion of
 invalidity. On p. 160 he says in the note the negation does away with
 a supposition, denies the validity, and this expression, considered
 in itself, might be taken to mean that Sigwart assumes here a special
 function of denial (absprechen) the contrary of that of affirmation
 (zusprechen). But no; a negative copula (cf. p. 153) according to him
 there is not.

 Now what in the world is one to understand by “denial” (absprechen)?
 Does it mean the simple suppression (Aufhörenlassen) of the positive
 judgment upon the given subject matter, that is, according to Sigwart,
 the falling away of the feeling of compulsion previously given in
 a connexion between ideas? This is impossible, since the removal
 of this would bring about a condition in which the connexion of
 ideas remains, without being either affirmed or denied. How often
 does something of which we were previously certain become uncertain
 without our on this account denying it. What then is this denying?
 May we perhaps say that according to Sigwart it is a feeling oneself
 compelled (sich-genötigt-fühlen) to annul, whereas affirming is a
 feeling oneself compelled to posit? We should then have to say that
 all the while we are passing a negative judgment, we are in reality
 always seeking to pass a positive judgment, but that we experience a
 hindrance in so doing. The same consciousness, however, is felt by
 one who is clearly aware of the entire absence of a positive ground.
 For how can any one succeed in believing anything which he at the
 same time holds to be entirely ungrounded? Of no one, especially if
 Sigwart’s definition of the judgment be applied as the standard,
 is this conceivable; that is to say, every one in such a case will
 experience failure in such an attempt. Accordingly there is, as
 yet, no negative judgment. If then the rejection does not signify a
 negative copula it must manifestly be regarded as an instance of the
 affirmation of the predicate “false,” or (to use Sigwart’s term) as
 its “identification” with the judgment which in this case should be
 the subject. This “false” also cannot simply mean “untrue,” for I
 can assert “untrue” of thousands of things with regard to which the
 predicate “false,” which appears in certain judgments, would not be
 in place. If only judgments are true, then of everything which is not
 a judgment the predicate “untrue” must be affirmed, though certainly
 not on that account the predicate “false.” “False” must therefore be
 regarded as a positive predicate; and so from Sigwart’s point of view
 absolutely false in principle, certain as it is that the merely not
 being convinced (nicht-überzeugt-sein) is no denial, it is equally
 certain that we have actually no choice; we should be compelled to
 regard every negative judgment as a positive judgment with a positive
 predicate. So we arrive at a second and greater paradox.

 But here a third factor enters which completes the confusion. If
 we examine Sigwart’s view as to the nature of judgment in general,
 it may be shown in the clearest manner possible that the simple
 positive judgment itself involves in turn, a negative judgment. That
 is to say, following Sigwart, every judgment involves besides a
 certain combination of ideas, a consciousness of the necessity of
 our “identification” (unseres Einssetzens) and the impossibility of
 its contradictory (cf. espec. p. 102), the consciousness, moreover,
 of such a necessity and impossibility valid for all thinking beings
 (cf. pp. 102 and 107), which, by the way, is of course quite as false
 as Sigwart’s whole view of the nature of judgment in general. All
 judgments without exception are, on account of this peculiarity,
 called by Sigwart apodictic: nor will he admit the validity of any
 distinction between the assertorical and apodictic forms of judgment
 (cf. p. 229 seq.). I now ask: Have we not here a negative judgment
 distinctly involved? Otherwise what meaning can be given to the
 statement when we hear Sigwart speak of a “consciousness of the
 impossibility of the contradictory.” Further I have already shown in
 my _Psychology_ how all universal judgments are negative, since to
 be conscious of universality means nothing else than to be convinced
 that there exists no exception; if this negative be not added, the
 most extensive list of positive assertions will never constitute a
 belief in universality. When therefore, a consciousness that every
 one must so think is here spoken of, there is in this fact a further
 proof of what I have asserted, namely that according to Sigwart’s
 doctrine of judgment the simplest positive acts of judgment must
 involve a negative act of judgment. And yet we are called upon at the
 same time to believe that the negative judgment, as set forth (p. 159
 seq.), arose relatively late, and that therefore on this, as well as
 on other grounds, it is unworthy of being placed side by side, with
 the positive judgment as a species equally primordial! Sigwart would
 surely not have expected this of us had he been conscious of all that
 I have here set forth in detail, and which is the more clearly seen to
 be involved in his exposition, often so difficult to comprehend the
 more carefully it is submitted to reflection. Of course expressions
 may be found where Sigwart, respecting this or that point of detail,
 asserts the contrary of what is here deduced; for what else can be
 expected where everything is left in such ambiguity, and where the
 attempt to make things clear exhibits the most manifold contradictions?

 3. Finally, we have still to show the genesis of the error in which
 this able logician has involved himself in a relatively simple
 question after having once mistaken the nature of the judgment. The
 _proton pseudos_ is to be sought in a delusion which has come down
 to us from the older logic that to the essence of the judgment there
 belongs the relation of two ideas with one another. Aristotle has
 described this relation as combination and separation (σύνθεσις καἰ
 διαίρεσις) although he was well aware of the imperfect propriety of
 the expressions, adding at the same time that in a certain sense
 both relations might be described as a combination (σύνθεσις, cf.
 _de Anima_, iii. 6). Scholastic and modern logic held fast to the
 expressions “combination” and “separation”; in grammar, however,
 both these relations were termed “combination,” and the symbol for
 this combination the “copula.” Sigwart now takes seriously the
 expressions “combination” and “separation,” and so a negative copula
 seems to him a contradiction (cf. p. 153), the positive judgment,
 on the other hand, appears to be a presupposition of the negative
 judgment, since, before a combination has been set up, it cannot be
 separated. And so it appears to him that a negative judgment without
 a preceding positive judgment is quite meaningless (cf. p. 150 and
 above). Consequently we find this celebrated inquirer in a position
 which compels him to put forth the most strenuous efforts all to no
 purpose--the negative judgment remains inexplicable.

 In a note (p. 159) he gives us, as a result of such attempts, a
 remarkable description of the process by which we arrive at the
 negative judgment--a result in which he believes himself finally
 able to rest satisfied. In this account the false steps which he
 successively makes become, each in turn, evident to the attentive
 observer. Long before the point is reached where he believes himself
 to have come upon the negative judgment, he has as a matter of fact
 already anticipated it.

 He sets out with the correct observation that the first judgments
 which we make are all positive in character. These judgments are
 evident and made with full confidence. “Now, however,” he continues,
 “our thought goes out beyond the given; by the aid of recollections
 and associations, judgments arise which are at first also formed in
 the belief that they express reality” (which means, according to
 other expressions of Sigwart, that the ideas are combined with the
 consciousness of objective validity; for this (xiv. p. 98) belongs
 to the essence of the judgment) “as, for example, when we expect to
 find something with which we are acquainted in its usual place or
 pre-suppose respecting a flower that it smells. Now, however, a part
 of what is thus supposed _contradicts_ our immediate knowledge.” (We
 leave Sigwart to show here how we are able to recognize anything as
 “contradictory” when we are not as yet in possession of negative
 judgments and negative notions. The difficulty becomes still more
 sharply apparent as he proceeds:) “when we do _not find_ what we
 expected, we become conscious of the _difference_ between what exists
 _merely_ in idea and what is real.” (What does “not find” mean here?
 I had not found it previously; obviously I now find that what was
 erroneously supposed to be associated with another object is _without_
 it, and this I can only do by recognizing the one and denying the
 other, i.e. recognize it as _not_ being with it. Further what is meant
 here by “difference”? To recognize difference means to recognize that
 of two things the one is _not_ the other. What is meant by existing
 “merely in idea”? Manifestly, “what exists in idea which is _not_ at
 the same time also real.” It would seem, however, that Sigwart is
 still unaware that in what he is describing the negative function
 of the judgment is already more than once involved. He continues:)
 “That of which we are immediately certain is _another_ than that”
 (i.e. it is not the same, it is indeed absolutely incompatible with
 that) “which we have judged in anticipation, and now” (i.e. after and
 since we have already passed all these negative judgments) “appears
 the negation which annuls the supposition and denies of it validity.
 _And here a new attitude is involved in so far as the subjective
 combination is separated from the consciousness of certainty._ The
 subjective combination is compared with one bearing the stamp of
 certainty, its distinction therefrom recognized, and out of this
 arises the notion of invalidity.” This last would almost seem to be
 a carelessness of expression, for if invalid were to mean as much
 as “false” and not “uncertain” it could not be derived from the
 distinction between a combination with and a combination without
 certainty, but only from the opposition existing between combination
 which is denied and one which is affirmed. As a matter of fact, the
 opposite affirmative judgment is not at all necessary to it. The
 opposition, the incompatibility of the qualities in a real, is already
 evident on the ground of the combination of ideas representing the
 opposite qualities which, as I repeat once more, cannot, according to
 Sigwart himself (p. 89 note; and p. 98 seq.), be called an attempt
 at positive judgment. Although this may now and again happen in the
 case of contradictory ideas, it certainly does not happen always. If,
 for example, the question is put to me: Does there exist a regular
 chiliagon with 1001 sides? then--assuming that I am not perfectly
 clear in my own mind, as will be the case with most men, that there
 does exist a regular chiliagon, I certainly do not attempt to form a
 judgment (i.e. according to Sigwart, confidently assume) that there
 exists a regular chiliagon having 1001 sides before forming the
 negative judgment that no such figure exists on the ground of the
 opposition between the qualities.

 Sigwart himself, as his language frequently betrays (cf. e.g. pp. 152
 and 150) recognizes at bottom, as he is bound to recognize, in spite
 of his attack upon the negative copula, that negation and denial are
 just as much a special function of the judgment as affirmation and
 recognition. If this be granted, then the range of their application
 is by no means so limited as he erroneously asserts. It is false that
 in every case where a denial takes place the predicate denied is the
 notion “valid.” Even of a judgment we may deny now its validity, now
 its certainty, now its _à priori_ character. And just in the same way
 the subject of the judgment can change most frequently. Of a judgment
 we may deny certainty, and validity; of a request, modesty; and so
 in every case, universally expressed, we may deny B of A. Sigwart
 himself, of course, does this just like any one else. Indeed he
 sometimes speaks unintentionally far more correctly than his theory
 would admit, and witnesses, as it were, instinctively to the truth;
 as, e.g. p. 151, where he declares not--as he elsewhere teaches--that
 the subject of a negative proposition is always a judgment, and its
 predicate the term “valid,” but “that of _every subject_ ... _a
 countless_ _number of predicates may be denied_.” This is certainly
 true and just on this account the old doctrine holds that affirmation
 and denial are equally primordial species.

 [24] (_p. 15_). The discovery that every act of love is a “pleasing,”
 every act of hate a “displeasing,” was very near to Descartes when
 he wrote his valuable little work on _The Affections_. In the second
 book, _Des Passions_, ii. art. 139, he says: “Lorsque les choses
 qu’elles (l’amour et la haine) nous portent à aimer sont véritablement
 bonnes, et celles qu’elles nous portent à haïr, sont véritablement
 mauvaises, l’amour est incomparablement meilleure que la haine; elle
 ne saurait être trop grande et elle ne manque jamais de produire la
 joie”; and this agrees with what he says a little later: “La haine, au
 contraire ne saurait être si petite qu’elle ne nuise, et elle n’est
 jamais sans tristesse.”

 In ordinary life, however, the expressions “joy” and “sadness,”
 “pleasure” and “pain” are only used when the pleasure and displeasure
 have attained a certain degree of liveliness. A sharp boundary in
 this unscientific division there is not; we may, however, be allowed
 to make use of it as it stands. It is enough that the expressions,
 “pleasure” and “displeasure” are not narrowed down by any such limit.

 [25] (_p. 16_). The expressions “true” and “false” are employed in a
 manifold sense; in one sense we employ them in speaking of true and
 false judgments; again (somewhat modifying the meaning), of objects,
 as when we say, “a true friend,” “false money.” I need scarcely
 observe that where I use the expressions “true” and “false” in this
 lecture, I associate therewith not the first and proper meaning, but
 rather a metaphorical one having reference to objects. True, is,
 therefore, what is; false, what is not. Just as Aristotle spoke of “ὂν
 ὡς ἀληθές” so we might also say, “ἀληθές ὡς ὂν.”

 Of truth in its proper sense it has often been said that it is
 the agreement of the judgment with the object (adequatio rei et
 intellectus, as the scholastics said). This expression, true in a
 certain sense, is yet in the highest degree open to misunderstanding,
 and has led to serious errors. The agreement is regarded as a kind of
 identity between something contained in the judgment, or in the idea
 lying at the root of the judgment and something situated without
 the mind. But this cannot be the meaning here; “to agree” means here
 rather as much as “to be appropriate,” “to be in harmony with,”
 “suit,” “correspond.” It is as though in the sphere of feeling one
 should say, the rightness of love and hate consists in the agreement
 of the feelings with the object. Properly understood this also would
 be unquestionably right; whoever loves and hates rightly, has his
 feelings adequately related to the object, i.e. the relation is
 appropriate, suitable, corresponds suitably, whereas it would be
 manifestly absurd were one to believe that in a rightly directed love
 or hate there was found to be an identity between these feelings or
 the ideas lying at their root on the one hand, and something lying
 outside the feelings on the other, an identity which is absent where
 the attitude of the feelings is unrightly directed. Among other
 circumstances this misunderstanding has also conduced towards bringing
 the doctrine of judgment into that sad confusion from which to-day
 psychology and logic seek with such painful efforts to set themselves
 free.

 The conceptions of existence and non-existence are the correlates
 of the conceptions of the truth of the (simple) affirmative and
 negative judgments. Just as to judgment belongs what is judged, to
 the affirmative judgment what is judged of affirmatively, to the
 negative judgment, what is judged of negatively, so to the rightness
 of the affirmative judgment belongs the existence of what is judged
 of affirmatively, to the rightness of the negative judgment the
 non-existence of what is judged of negatively; and whether I say an
 affirmative judgment is true, or, its object is existent; whether I
 say a negative judgment is true, or its object is non-existent; in
 both cases I am saying one and the same thing. In the same way, it is
 essentially one and the same logical principle whether I say, in each
 case either the (simple) affirmative or negative judgment is true, or,
 each is either existent or non-existent.

 Thus, for example, the assertion of the truth of the judgment, “a man
 is learned,” is the correlate of the assertion of the existence of
 the object, “a learned man”; and the assertion of the truth of the
 judgment, “no stone is alive,” is the correlate of the assertion of
 the non-existence of its object, “a living stone.” The correlative
 assertions are here, as everywhere, inseparable. The case is exactly
 the same as in the assertions A > B and that B < A; that A is the
 cause of B, and that B is produced by A.

 [26] (_p. 16_). The notion of the good, in and for itself, is
 accordingly a unity in the strict sense, and not, as Aristotle teaches
 (in consequence of a confusion which we shall have to speak of later)
 a unity in a merely analogous sense. German philosophers also have
 failed to grasp the unity of the conception. This is the case with
 Kant, and, quite recently, with Windelband. There is a defect in our
 ordinary way of speaking which may prove very misleading to Germans
 inasmuch as for the opposite of the term “good” there is no common
 expression current, but this is designated now as “schlimm,” now
 as “übel,” now as “böse,” now as “arg,” now as “abscheulich,” now
 as “schlecht,” etc. It might very well, as in similar cases, come
 to be thought that not only the common name is wanting, but also
 the common notion. And if the notion is wanting on the one side of
 the antithesis, it would also be wanting on the other, and so the
 expression “good” would seem an equivocal term.

 Of all the expressions quoted, it seems to me (and philologists
 also, whose advice I have asked, are of the same opinion), that the
 expression “schlecht,” like the Latin “malum,” is most applicable as
 the opposite of the good in its full universality, and in this way I
 shall allow myself to use this expression in what follows.

 The fact that I adhere to the view of a certain common character
 regarding the intentional relation of love and hate does not debar my
 recognizing along with this view, special forms for particular cases.
 If, therefore, “bad” is a truly universal simple class conception,
 there may yet be distinguished special classes within its domain of
 which one may be suitably termed “böse,” another “übel,” etc.

 [27] (_p. 18_). The distinction between “self-evident” and “blind”
 judgments is something too striking to have altogether escaped notice.
 Even the sceptical Hume is very far from denying the distinction.
 _Self-evidence_, according to him (_Enq. concerning Hum. Underst._
 iv.) may be ascribed, on the one hand, to analytic judgments (to which
 class belong also the axioms of mathematics and the mathematical
 demonstrations), and, on the other hand, to certain impressions, but
 not to the so-called truths of experience. Reason does not lead us
 here, but rather habit, after a manner entirely irrational; belief, in
 this case is _instinctive_ and _mechanical_ (_ib._ v.).

 But to observe a fact does not mean to set forth its nature clearly
 and distinctly. As the nature of the judgment has, until recent times,
 been almost universally misunderstood, how could it be possible
 rightly to understand its self-evidence? It is just here that even
 Descartes’ discernment fails him. How very closely the phenomenon
 occupied him a passage in the Meditations bears witness: “Cum hic dico
 me ita doctum esse a natura (he is speaking of the so-called external
 impressions) intelligo tantum _spontaneo quodam impetu_ me ferri ad
 hoc credendum _non lumine aliquo naturali_ mihi ostendi esse verum,
 quae duo multum discrepant. Nam quaecunque _lumine naturali_ mihi
 ostenduntur (ut quod ex eo quo dubitem sequatur me esse et similia)
 nullo modo dubia esse possunt quia nulla alia facultas esse potest,
 cui aeque fidam ac lumini isti, quaeque illa non vera esse possit
 docere; sed quantum ad impetus naturales jam saepe olim judicavi me
 ab illis in deteriorem partem fuisse impulsum cum de bono eligendo
 ageretur, nec video cur iisdem in ulla alia re magis fidam.”--(Medit.
 iii.).

 That Descartes did not mark the fact of self-evidence, that he did not
 observe the distinction between intuition and blind judgment certainly
 cannot be affirmed from the above. But, while separating the judgment
 as a class from the idea, he still leaves behind in the class of ideas
 the character of self-evidence which distinguishes the judgments of
 intuition. It consists, according to him, in a special mark of the
 perception, that is, of the idea lying at the root of the judgment.
 Descartes even goes so far as actually to call this act of perception
 a “cognoscere,” a “knowing.” A “knowing,” that is, and still not an
 act of judgment! These are rudimentary organs which after the progress
 made, owing to Descartes, in the doctrine of judgment, remind us of
 a stage of life in Psychology which has been surmounted; but with
 this distinction, in opposition to similar phenomena in the history of
 the development of the species, that these organs, in no way adapted,
 become in the highest degree troublesome, and render all Descartes’
 further efforts for the theory of knowledge ineffective. He remains,
 to use Leibnitz’ phrase, “in the antechamber of truth” (cf. here
 note 28, towards the end). Only in this way does Descartes’ clara et
 distincta perceptio--concerning which term itself it is so difficult
 to gain a clear and distinct idea--in its curious dual nature become
 perfectly intelligible. The only means of overcoming this confusion
 is to seek that which distinguishes insight in opposition to other
 judgments as an inner quality belonging to the act of insight itself.

 It is true that some who have sought here have yet failed to find. We
 saw (cf. note 23) how Sigwart conceives the nature of the judgment. To
 this, he teaches, there belongs a relation of ideas to one another,
 and along with this a feeling of obligation respecting this connexion.
 (Cf. sections 14 and 31, espec. 4 and 5.) Such a feeling therefore,
 always exists even in the case of the blindest prejudice. It is then
 abnormal, but is held (as Sigwart expressly explains) to be normal and
 of universal validity. And what now in contrast to this case, is given
 in the case of insight? Sigwart replies that its evidence consists
 in the same feeling (cf. e.g. section 3) which now, however, is not
 merely held to be normal and universally valid, but is really normal
 and universally valid.

 It seems to me that the weakness of this theory is at once apparent;
 and it is on many grounds to be rejected.

 1. The peculiar nature of insight, the clearness and evidence of
 certain judgments from which their truth is inseparable has little
 or nothing to do with any feeling of compulsion. It may well happen
 that at a given moment I cannot refrain from so judging, yet none the
 less the essence of its clearness does not consist in the feeling of
 compulsion, and no consciousness of an obligation so to judge could,
 as such, afford security as to its truth. He who disbelieves in every
 form of indeterminism in respect of judging, regards all judgments
 under the circumstances in which they were passed as necessary, but he
 does not--and with indisputable right--regard all of them as on that
 account true.

 2. Sigwart, in seeking the consciousness of insight in a feeling
 of necessity so to think, asserts that the consciousness of one’s
 being compelled is, at the same time, a consciousness of a necessity
 for all thinking beings whenever the same grounds are present. If
 he means, however, that the one conviction is doubtless connected
 with the other, this is an error. Why, when a person feels bound to
 pass a judgment upon certain data, should the same compulsion hold
 good in respect of every other thinking being to whom the same data
 are also given? It is obvious that only an appeal to the law of
 causality which, under like conditions demands like results, could
 be the ground of the logical connexion. Its application, however,
 to the present case would be entirely erroneous, since this would
 involve the ignoring of the special psychical dispositions, which,
 although they do not directly enter into consciousness at all, must
 yet be regarded, along with the conscious data, as pre-determining
 conditions, and these are very different in the case of different
 persons. Hegel and his school, misled by paralogisms, have denied the
 principle of contradiction; Trendelenburg, who opposed Hegel, has at
 least restricted its validity (cf. his _Abhandlungen über Herbarts
 Metaphysik_). The universal impossibility of inwardly denying the
 principle which Aristotle asserted cannot therefore, to-day, be any
 longer defended; Aristotle himself, however, for whom the principle
 was self-evident, assuredly found its denial impossible.

 Whatever is evident to any one is of course certain not only for him,
 but also for every one else who, in the same way, sees its evidence.
 The judgment, moreover, which is seen to be evident by any one has
 also universal validity, i.e. the contradictory of what is seen to be
 evident by one person, cannot be seen to be evident by another person,
 and every one who believes in its contradictory is in error. Further,
 since what is here said belongs to the essence of truth, whoever has
 evidence of the truth of anything may perceive that he is justified
 in regarding it as true for all. But he would be guilty of a flagrant
 confusion of ideas who should regard such a consciousness that a
 truth is true for all, as equivalent to a consciousness of a universal
 necessity of thinking.

 3. Sigwart involves himself in a multitude of contradictions. He
 asserts and must assert--if he is not to yield to the sceptics and
 relinquish his entire logical system--that evident judgments are
 not merely different from non-evident judgments, but that they are
 also distinguishable in consciousness. The one class must therefore
 appear as normal and of universal validity, the other class as
 not so. But if evident and non-evident judgments alike carry with
 them the consciousness of universal validity, then the two classes
 would at first sight exactly agree in the manner in which they
 present themselves, and only as it were, afterwards (or at the same
 time, though as a mere concomitant), and by reflection upon some
 sort of criterion which is applied to them as a standard could the
 distinction be discovered. And passages are actually to be found in
 Sigwart where he speaks of a consciousness of agreement with the
 universal rules which accompany the fully evident judgment. (Cf.
 e.g. _Logic_, 2nd ed., 39, p. 311.) But apart from the fact that
 this contradicts experience--for long before the discovery of the
 syllogism, conclusions were reached syllogistically and with complete
 evidence--it is also to be rejected inasmuch as, seeing that the rule
 itself must be assured, it would lead either to an infinite regress,
 or to a _circulus vitiosus_.

 4. Another contradiction with which I have to charge Sigwart (though
 in my opinion it might have been avoided even after his erroneous
 view as to the nature of the judgment and as to the nature of
 self-evidence), we meet with in his doctrine of self-consciousness.
 The knowledge that I am contains _only_ self-evidence, and this exists
 independent of any consciousness of an obligation so to think and of
 a necessity which is common to all alike. (At least I am not able
 otherwise to understand the passage, _Logic_, 2nd ed., p. 310: “The
 certainty that I am and think is the absolutely last and fundamental
 one--the condition of all thinking and certainty at all; here, only
 immediate evidence can be given; one cannot even say that this thought
 is necessary, since it is previous to all necessity, and just as
 immediate and evident is the conscious certainty that I think this
 or that; it is inextricably interwoven with my self-consciousness;
 the one is given with the other.”) After Sigwart’s doctrine already
 examined, this would appear to be a _contradictio in adjecto_ and, as
 such, quite indefensible.

 5. Further contradictions appear in Sigwart’s very peculiar and
 doubtful doctrine concerning the postulates, which he opposes to the
 axioms. The latter are to be regarded as certain on the ground of
 their real intellectual necessity; the former, not on the ground of
 purely intellectual motives, but on psychological motives of another
 kind, on the ground of practical needs. (_Logic_, 2nd ed. p. 412 seq.)
 The law of causality: e.g. is, according to him, not an axiom, but a
 mere postulate; we regard it as certain, since we find that without
 affirming it we should not be able to investigate nature. Sigwart,
 by this mode of accepting the law of causality, that is, affirming,
 out of mere good-will, that in nature under like conditions, the same
 results would constantly be forthcoming, manifestly takes it for
 granted without being conscious of its intellectual necessity. But, if
 all “taking-as-true” (Fürwahrhalten) is an act of judgment, this is
 quite incompatible with his views as to the nature of the judgment.
 Sigwart has here, as far as I can see, but one way of escape, i.e. to
 confess that he does not believe in what, as a postulate, he accepts
 as certain (as e.g. the law of causality); then, however, he will be
 hardly serious in hoping for it.

 6. This point becomes still more doubtful on reflection upon what
 (2) has been previously discussed. The consciousness of a universal
 necessity of thought does not, according to Sigwart, belong to the
 postulates, but rather to the axioms. (Cf. 5.) But Sigwart could only
 with any plausibility exhibit the consciousness of this universal
 necessity of thinking as operating in the consciousness of one’s
 personal necessity of thinking by making use of the universal law
 of causation. But this causal law is itself merely a postulate; it
 is destitute of self-evidence. It is therefore obvious that the
 universal thought-necessity in the case of the axioms is also a
 postulate, and consequently they lose what, according to Sigwart, is
 their most essential distinction from the postulates. It may perhaps
 be in accordance with this that Sigwart calls the belief in the
 trustworthiness of “self-evidence” a postulate. But how the statement
 so interpreted, can be brought into harmony with the remaining parts
 of his doctrine I am at a loss to conceive.

 7. Sigwart denies (31) the distinction between assertorical and
 apodictic judgments, since in every judgment the sense of necessity
 in respect of its function is essential. Consequently this assertion
 likewise hangs together with his erroneous fundamental view of
 the judgment; he would appear to identify the feeling which he
 sometimes calls the feeling of evidence with the apodictic character
 of a judgment. But it would be quite unjustifiable to overlook the
 modal peculiarity of certain judgments, as for example, the law of
 contradiction in distinction from other forms of judgment like that of
 the consciousness that I am. In the first instance, we have to do with
 what is “necessarily true or false,” in the second instance only with
 what is “true or false as a matter of fact,” though both are in the
 same sense evident and do not differ in respect of their certainty.
 Only in the case of judgments like the former, not, however, from such
 as the latter do we draw the notions of impossibility and necessity.

 That Sigwart, in opposing the view which regards the apodictic
 judgment as a special class, also occasionally bears witness against
 himself is clear from what has been already said (4). The knowledge
 that I am, he calls, in opposition to the knowledge of an axiom, the
 knowledge of a simple actual truth (p. 312). Here he speaks more
 soundly than his general statements would really allow.

 Sigwart’s theory of self-evidence is, therefore, essentially false.
 As in the case of Descartes, so here it cannot be said that Sigwart
 was not conscious of the phenomenon; indeed, we must rather say in
 his praise, that with the greatest zeal he has sought to analyze it,
 but as is the case with many in psychological analysis, it would seem
 that in the eagerness of analyzing he did not stop at the right point,
 and has sought to resolve into one another phenomena very distinct in
 nature.

 It is obvious that an error respecting the nature of evidence is
 fraught with the gravest consequence for the logician. It might well
 be said that we have here touched upon the deep-seated organic disease
 in Sigwart’s logic, if this may not rather be said to consist in a
 misunderstanding of the nature of the judgment in general. Again and
 again its evil results become manifest, as for example, in Sigwart’s
 inability to understand the most essential causes of our errors, Cf.
 _Logic_, vol. i. 2nd ed. p. 103, note, where, with strange partiality
 he assigns the chief blame to the defective development of our
 language.

 For the rest, many another celebrated logician in recent times can
 claim no superiority over Sigwart here. As a further example we need
 only observe how the doctrine of evidence fares at the hands of the
 admirable J. S. Mill. Cf. note 69, p. 99.

 Owing to the great unclearness as to the nature of evidence, almost
 universal, it becomes conceivable why, as often happens, we meet
 with the expression “more or less self-evident.” Even Descartes and
 Pascal use such expressions, although it is clearly quite unsuitable.
 Whatever is self-evident is certain, and certainty in the real sense
 knows no distinctions of degree. Even quite recently we find the
 opinion expressed in the _Vierteljahrsschrift für wissenschaftliche
 Philosophie_ (and the writer is manifestly quite serious), that
 there exist _self-evident suppositions_ which, in spite of their
 self-evidence, may quite well be false. It is unnecessary to add that
 I hold this to be opposed to reason. I may here, however, express
 regret that lectures delivered by me at a time when I still regarded
 degrees of conviction as intensities of judgment, seem to have given
 an occasion for such confusions.

 [28] (_p. 19_). Cf. Hume’s Essay, already cited: _An Enquiry
 concerning the Principles of Morals._ Other philosophers, who have
 placed the foundation of ethics in the feelings, as e.g. Beneke and
 Uberweg (who follows him) have seen further than Hume here. (Cf. the
 presentation of Beneke’s ethics in his _Grundriss der Geschichte der
 Philosophie_, iii.) Herbart comes still nearer to the truth when he
 speaks of self-evident judgments of taste (these, however, are really
 not judgments at all, but feelings, and as such are not self-evident,
 but can only be said to have something analogous to self-evident
 judgments) and when he further opposes to the merely pleasurable
 the beautiful, ascribing to the latter as distinct from the former,
 universal validity and undeniable worth. Unfortunately, there is
 always something false mixed up with his view, and Herbart loses at
 once and for ever the right path, so that his ethics in its course
 diverges much further from the truth than the doctrine of Hume.

 Those thinkers who have completely overlooked the distinction between
 pleasure with the character of rightness and pleasure which is not
 so qualified, are in danger of falling into opposite errors. The one
 class view the matter as though _all_ pleasure had the character of
 rightness, the other class as though _no_ pleasure were so qualified.
 By the one class the notion of the good as that which rightly
 pleases, is entirely given up; “worthy of desire” (begehrenswert) in
 distinction from “desirable” (begehrbar), is an unmeaning expression.
 For the other class, “worthy of desire” (begehrenswert) remains as a
 separate notion, so that there is no tautology in their saying nothing
 is in itself desirable except in so far as it is in itself worthy of
 desire, is good in itself. Manifestly they must, to be consistent,
 assert this, and this they have really taught. The extreme hedonists
 all belong to this class; but, along with them, many others; in the
 Middle Ages, for example, the teaching is found in Thomas Aquinas,
 whose greatness receives fresh appreciation from Ihering (cf. Summ.
 theol. I.a. qu. 80, qu. 82, art. 2 ad. 1, etc.).

 But even then such a view cannot be maintained in the light of the
 facts without exposing the nature of good and bad to a falsification
 which involves a form of subjectivism similar to that formerly
 committed by Protagoras respecting the notions of truth and falsehood.
 Just as, according to this subjectivist in the sphere of the judgment,
 man is the measure of all things, and often what is true for one,
 may at the same time be false for another--so the advocates of the
 view that only the good can be loved, only the bad hated, are really
 compelled to assume that, in this sphere, each is himself the measure
 of all things; for the good, in that it is good; for the bad, that it
 is bad; so that often something is, in itself and at the same time,
 both good and bad: good in itself, in the case of all who love it for
 its own sake; bad in itself, in the case of all who hate it for its
 own sake. This is absurd, and the subjectivistic falsification of the
 notion of the good is to be rejected equally with the subjectivistic
 falsification of the notions of truth and existence by Protagoras,
 but with this difference: that the subjectivistic error in the sphere
 of what is rightly pleasing and displeasing takes root more easily
 and infects most ethical systems even to-day. Some, as recently,
 Sigwart (_Vorfragen der Ethik_, p. 6), confess it openly; others fall
 into this error without themselves becoming clearly conscious of the
 subjectivistic character of their view.[A]

  [A] Those especially who teach that generally speaking the knowledge,
 pleasure, and perfection of each individual is, for him, good, their
 opposites bad, and that all else is in itself indifferent, will
 perhaps protest against my classing them among the subjectivists.
 It might even seem on a superficial survey, that they have set up a
 doctrine of the good equally valid for all. But on a more careful
 examination we find that this teaching does not even in a single
 instance, hold one and the same object to be good universally.
 For example, my own knowledge is, according to this view, for me
 worthy of love; for every one else indifferent in itself, while the
 knowledge of another individual is in itself for me indifferent. It
 is curious to observe theistic thinkers, as often happens, setting
 up a subjectivistic view respecting the good, valid of all mortal
 loving and willing, while, at the same time assuming that God, without
 respect of person, estimates every perfection by a kind of objective
 standard. This exception with regard to the loving and willing of
 God and the notion of Him as eternal Judge is then meant to render
 harmless in respect of its practical consequences, the egoism which
 such a principle implies.

 elebrated controversy between Bossuet and Fenelon it may be said that
 the great bishop of Meaux advocated a kind of subjectivism. Fenelon’s
 theses, though he advocated a system of morality neither ignoble nor
 unchristian, were finally condemned by the Church of Rome, though it
 did not go so far as to reject his teaching as heretical. Otherwise
 one would really be compelled to condemn also those fine glowing lines
 attributed by many to St. Theresa, that in a very imperfect Latin
 translation have found their way into many Catholic prayer-books which
 is much more than their escaping the ecclesiastical censor. I give
 them translated directly from the Spanish

    Nicht Hoffnung auf des Himmels sel’ge Freuden
    Hat Dir, mein Gott, zum Dienste mich verbunden.
    Nicht Furcht, die ich vor ew’gem Graus empfunden,
    Hat mich bewegt der Sünder Pfad zu meiden.

    Du Herr bewegst mich, mich bewegt Dein Leiden.
    Dein Anblick in den letzten, bangen Stunden.
    Der Geisseln Wuth. Dein Haupt von Dorn umwunden.
    Dein schweres Kreuz und--ach!--Dein bittres Scheiden.

    _Herr, Du bewegest mich mit solchem Triebe,_
    _Das ich Dich liebte, wär’ kein Himmel offen._
    _Dich fürchtete, wenn auch kein Abgrund schreckte;_
    _Nichts kannst Du geben, was mir Liebe weckte;_
    _Denn würd’ ich auch nicht, wie ich hoffe, hoffen,_
    _Ich würde dennoch lieben, wie ich liebe.”_

 The teaching of Thomas Aquinas has often been so represented as though
 it were pure subjectivism. It is true that much of his teaching
 sounds quite subjectivistic (cf. e.g. Summ. theol. 1a. q. 80, art.
 1, especially the objections and replies as well as the passages in
 which he declares that the happiness of each is the highest and final
 end, asserting even of the saints in heaven that each rightly desires
 more his own blessedness than the blessedness of all others). Along
 with these, however, are to be found statements in which he soars
 above this subjectivistic view as, for example, when he declares (as
 Plato and Aristotle before him and Descartes and Leibnitz after) that
 everything which exists is good as such, not good merely as a means
 but also--a point which pure subjectivists (as recently Sigwart,
 _Vorfr. d. Ethik_, p. 6) expressly deny--good in itself, and again,
 when he affirms that in case any one--an impossible case--had at any
 time to choose between his own eternal ruin and an injury to the
 Divine love, the right course would be to prefer his own eternal
 unhappiness.

 There the moral feeling of western Christendom touches the feeling of
 the heathen Hindu, as is shown in a somewhat strange story of a maiden
 who renounces her own everlasting blessedness for the salvation of the
 rest of the world; as also that of a positivist thinker like Mill when
 he declares sooner than bow in prayer before a being not truly good,
 “to hell he will go.” I knew a Catholic priest who, on account of this
 utterance of Mill’s, voted for him at the parliamentary election.]
Whoever, as I have said, has once accepted the view that nothing can
 please except in so far as it is really good, nothing displease,
 except in so far as it is really bad, is on a way which, if
 consistently followed, must lead him to subjectivism. This is
 evident as soon as it is admitted (and at first sight, it is true,
 it may be denied) that opposite tastes, here desire, there dislike,
 may be associated with the same sense phenomenon. One might, in
 defence, argue that here, in spite of the similarity of the external
 stimulus the corresponding subjective idea may have an essentially
 different content. But such a view refutes itself in those cases
 where we ourselves repeatedly experience the same phenomenon, and, in
 consequence of a further development in age or by reason of a changed
 habit (cf. text 25, p. 16) thereby experience a different feeling,
 dislike for desire, or desire for dislike. There remains, then, no
 doubt, that as a fact the feelings may take an opposed attitude
 towards the same phenomenon: and again, in the case where ideas
 instinctively repel us, while at the same time arousing within us a
 pleasure of a higher kind (cf. note 32, p. 92), what has been said is
 also clearly evident.

 Finally, we should expect from one who thinks that every act of simple
 pleasure is right, and that one act never contradicts another, a
 similar doctrine in respect of the act of choosing. But the reverse
 is here so obvious that the advocates of this view have in striking
 contrast always asserted in the most definite manner that different
 individuals have preferences opposite in character, and that one is
 right, the other wrong.

 Glancing back from the disciples of Aristotle in the Middle Ages to
 the master himself, we find his teaching appears to be a different
 one. Aristotle recognizes a right and a wrong kind of desire (Ὄρεξις
 ὀρθᾐ καἰ οὐκ οὐκ ὀρθή) and that what is desired (ὀρεκτόν) is not
 always the good. (_De Anima_, iii. 10.) In the same way he affirms in
 respect of pleasure (ἡδονή) in the _Nicomachian Ethics_ that not every
 pleasure is good; there is a pleasure in the bad, which is itself bad
 (_Nic. Eth._ x. 2). In his _Metaphysics_ he distinguishes between a
 lower and a higher kind of desire (ἐπιθμία and βούλησις); whatever is
 desired by the higher kind for its own sake is truly good (_Metaph._ Δ
 7, p. 1072 a. 28). A certain approach to the right view seems already
 to have been reached here. It is of special interest (a point I have
 only discovered later) that Aristotle has suggested an analogy between
 ethical subjectivism and the logical subjectivism of Protagoras, and
 equally repudiates both (_Metaph._ Κ 6, p. 1062 b. 16, and 1063 a. 5).
 On the other hand it would appear from the lines immediately following
 as though Aristotle had fallen into the very obvious temptation of
 believing that we can know the good as good, independent of the
 excitation of the emotions. (_Metaph._ 29; cf. _De Anima_, iii. 9 and
 10.)

 In close connection with this appears to be the passage (_Nic. Eth._
 i. 4) where he denies that there is any uniform notion of the good
 (understanding, of course, the good in itself, cf. respecting this,
 note 26, p. 77), thinking rather that only by way of analogy does
 there exist a unity in the case of the good of rational thinking
 and seeing, joy, etc., and when, in another passage (_Metaph._ Ε 4,
 p. 1027 b. 25), he says that the true and the false are not in the
 things, where the good and the bad are, i.e. the former predicates
 (e.g. true God, false friend) are ascribed to the things only in
 respect of certain mental acts, the true and false judgments, while
 the latter, on the other hand, are not in a similar way ascribed to
 them merely in respect of a certain class of mental activities:--all
 of which, incorrect as it is, is still connected as a necessary result
 with the aforesaid error. He is more in agreement with the true
 doctrine of the origin of our notion and knowledge of the good, when
 (_Nic. Ethics_, x. 2) he adduces as an argument against the assumption
 that joy does not belong to the good, the fact that all desire it,
 and adds: “For if only irrational beings desired it, the opposition
 to this argument would still contain a certain justification; but if
 every rational being also does so, how can anything be said against
 it?” Yet even this utterance is reconcilable with his erroneous view.

 Considered in this aspect, the moralist of sentiment
 (Gefühls-moralist), Hume, has here the advantage of him, for Hume
 rightly urges, how is any one to recognize that anything is to be
 loved without experiencing the love?

 I have said that the temptation into which Aristotle has fallen
 appears quite conceivable. It arises from the fact that, along with
 the experience of an emotion qualified as right there is given at the
 same time the knowledge that the object itself is good. Thus it may
 easily happen that the relation is then perverted and the love is
 thought to follow as a consequence of the knowledge, and recognized as
 right by reason of its agreement with this its rule.

 It is not without interest to compare the error here made by Aristotle
 in respect of emotion qualified as right with that which we have seen
 was committed by Descartes in respect of the similarly qualified
 judgment (cf. note 27, p. 78). The cases are essentially analogous; in
 both cases the distinguishing mark is sought in the special character
 of the idea which forms the basis of the act rather than in the act
 itself qualified as right. In fact it seems to me evident from various
 passages in his treatise _Des Passions_, that Descartes himself has
 treated the matter in a way quite similar to that of Aristotle, and in
 a manner essentially analogous to his doctrine of the self-evident
 judgment.

 At the present time many approach very near to Descartes’ error in
 respect of the marks of self-evidence (if we are not rather to say
 that the error is really implicitly contained in their statements)
 when they regard the matter as though in the case of every
 self-evident judgment a criterion were referred to. In this case it
 must have been previously given somewhere, either as recognized--and
 this would lead to infinity--or (and this is the only alternative),
 it is given in the idea. It may be said that here also the temptation
 to such a misconception lies ready to hand and this may well have
 exercised a misleading influence upon Descartes. Aristotle’s error
 is less general, though only because the phenomenon of the emotion
 qualified as right has, generally speaking, come less frequently under
 consideration than that of the similarly qualified judgment.

 If the nature of the former has been misunderstood, the latter has
 often been so overlooked as not even to admit of its essential nature
 being misinterpreted.

 [29] (_p. 19_). When I affirmed that the language of common life
 offers no suitable terms for activities of feeling qualified as right,
 I did not mean thereby to deny that certain expressions are, in
 themselves, well suited, indeed they would seem to have been created
 for this purpose, particularly, for example, the expressions “_to be
 well pleasing_,” and “_to be ill pleasing_” (gut gefallen and schlecht
 gefallen), as distinct from the simple “to be pleasing” and “to be
 mis-pleasing.” Though, however, it might seem advisable to limit these
 terms in this way and so to make them serve as scientific terms,
 scarcely any trace of such a limitation is to be found in ordinary
 language. One does not, of course, care to say: “the good pleases him
 ill,” “the bad pleases him well,” though one still says that to one
 this tastes good, to another that, and so on, i.e. the expression
 “_to be well pleasing_” is applied unhesitatingly even in the case
 where pleasure is given in the lowest instinctive form. Indeed the
 term-“impression” (Wahrnehmung) has degenerated in an almost similar
 way. Only really appropriate in respect of knowledge, it came to be
 applied in the case of the so-called external impression (äussere
 Wahrnehmung), i.e. in cases of a belief, blind, and in its essential
 relations, erroneous, and consequently would require, in order, as a
 terminus technicus to have scientific application, an important reform
 of the usual terminology and one which would essentially narrow the
 range of the term.

 [30] (_p. 19_). _Metaph._, Α 1, p. 980 a. 22.

 [31] (_p. 20_) i.e., “Als richtig characterisiert.” This phrase, which
 occurs frequently, I have translated sometimes as above, sometimes by
 “qualified as right.” By this phrase and its equivalents is meant that
 the act (sc. of loving, hating, or preferring,) is at once perceived
 by us to be a right one, bears the mark or character of rightness.

 [32] (_p. 20_). In order to exclude a misunderstanding and the
 doubts necessarily connected therewith, I add the following remark
 to what has been suggested shortly in the text. In order that an
 act of feeling may be called purely good in itself it is requisite:
 (1) that it be right; (2) that it be an act of pleasing and not an
 act of displeasing. If either condition be absent, it is already,
 in a certain respect, bad in itself; pleasure at the misfortunes of
 others (Schadenfreude) is bad on the first ground; pain at the sight
 of injustice, on the second ground. If both conditions are lacking,
 the act is still worse, in accordance with the principle of summation
 of which we shall speak later in the lecture. According to this same
 principle, where a feeling is good, its increase increases also the
 goodness of the act, while, similarly, where an act is purely bad, or
 at least participates in any respect in the bad, with the intensity
 of the feeling increases the badness of the act. When the act is a
 mixed one, good and bad manifestly increase, or diminish, in simple
 proportion to one another. The “plus” belonging to the one or the
 other side, must therefore, with the increase in intensity of the
 act become ever greater, with its decrease ever smaller. And so the
 surplus of good in the act may, under certain circumstances in spite
 of its impurity, be described as a very great good, while conversely,
 the surplus of the bad may, despite the admixture of the good, be
 described as something very bad (cf. note 36).

 [33] (_p. 20_). It may happen that, at the same time, one and the
 same thing is both pleasing and displeasing. First, something in
 itself displeasing may yet be pleasing as a means to something else,
 and vice versa; then a case may arise where something instinctively
 repels us, while at the same time it is loved by us with a higher
 love. We may thus have an instinctive repugnance to a sensation, which
 is yet at the same time (and every idea, qua idea, is good), a welcome
 enrichment of our world of ideas. Aristotle has said: “It happens
 that desires enter into conflict with each other. This happens when
 the reason (λὁγος) and the lower desires (ἐπιθυμα) are in opposition
 (_De Anima_ iii. 10). And again: “Now the lower desires (ἐπιθυμία)
 gain a victory over the higher, now the higher over the lower, and as”
 (according to the ancient astronomy) “one celestial sphere the other,
 so one desire draws off the other with it when the individual has lost
 the firm rule over himself” (_De Anima_ ii.).

 [34] (_p. 21_). Just as love and hate may be directed towards single
 individuals, so also they may be directed to whole classes. This
 Aristotle has already observed. We are, he thinks, “not only angry
 with the individual thief who has robbed us, and with the individual
 sycophant who deceives our confiding nature, but we hate thieves and
 sycophants in general” (_Rhet._ ii. 4). Acts of loving and hating,
 where in this way there is an underlying general conception, also
 possess frequently the character of rightness. And so quite naturally
 along with the experience of this given act of love or hate, the
 goodness or badness of the entire class becomes manifest at one
 stroke, and apart from every induction from special cases. In this
 way, for example, we attain to the general knowledge that insight as
 such is good. It is easy to understand how near the temptation lies,
 in the case of such knowledge of a general truth without any induction
 from single cases otherwise demanded in truths of experience,
 entirely to overlook the preparatory experience of a feeling having
 the character of rightness, and to regard the universal judgment
 as an immediate synthetic _à priori_ form of knowledge. Herbart’s
 very remarkable doctrine of a sudden elevation to general ethical
 principles seems to me to point to the fact that he had observed
 something of this peculiar process without at the same time becoming
 quite clear about it.

 [35] (_p. 21_). It is easy to see how important this proposition may
 become for a theodicy. As regards ethics it might be feared that
 its security becomes thereby seriously endangered, perhaps, indeed,
 completely destroyed. To see how unfounded such a fear is, cf. note
 43, p. 99.

 [36] (_p. 22_). It seems to me evident even from analysis of the
 notion of choice (1) that everything which is good is to be preferred,
 i.e. that in an act of choice it shall fall as a reasonable moment
 into the balance; (2) that everything bad forms a reasonable
 anti-moment, and therefore also that (3) in such cases--partly by
 direct means, partly by an addition in which the good and the bad
 are to be taken into account as quantities with opposite signs--the
 preponderance in which right choice is to be grounded may become
 evident, i.e. the preferability or superiority of the one as opposed
 to the other. According to this view, it does not, closely examined,
 require the special experience of an act of preference having the
 character of rightness, but only the experience of simple similarly
 qualified acts of pleasing and displeasing, in order to attain in the
 above-mentioned cases to the knowledge of the better. And therefore
 I have said that we derived our knowledge of preferability, not from
 the fact that our experience has the character of rightness, but
 that the said preferences possess the character of rightness because
 the knowledge of preferability has here been made the determining
 standard. I do not, however, mean to say that the same distinguishing
 character which was previously insisted upon in the case of certain
 simple acts of pleasing is not also here really present.

 [37] (_p. 24_). In order that the procedure here might have been
 rendered quite exact and really exhaustive, two other very important
 cases would still need to have been mentioned in the lecture. The one
 case is that of pleasure in the bad, the other that of displeasure
 in the bad. If we enquire: Is pleasure in the bad good? the answer
 has already been given in a measure quite rightly by Aristotle: No.
 “No one,” he says in the _Nicomachian Ethics_ (x. 2, p. 1174 a. 1),
 “would wish to feel joy in what is shameful even if it were made
 certain to him that no harm would result therefrom.” The hedonists,
 to which class belonged such noble men as Fechner (cf. his work on
 _The Highest Good_) contradicted this view. Their teaching is to be
 rejected; in practice as Hume has observed, they fortunately proved
 much better than in theory. There is still, however, a grain of truth
 in their view. The pleasure in the bad is, qua pleasure, good, and
 only at the same time bad as a wrong activity of feeling, and though,
 by reason of this perversion, it may be described as a preponderance
 of the bad, it cannot be regarded as something purely bad. While,
 therefore, abhorring it as bad, we are really making an act of choice
 in which freedom from what in the object is bad is preferred to the
 possession of what is good. And when we recognize the aversion as
 right, this is possible only because the preference has the character
 of rightness.

 The case is similar when we inquire if a similarly qualified
 displeasure in the bad is good, as e.g. where a noble heart feels pain
 on seeing the innocent oppressed, or where some one, looking back upon
 his past life, feels remorse at the consciousness of a bad action.
 Here the case is in every respect the reverse of the one preceding.
 Such a feeling arouses a state in which pleasure preponderates, but
 this pleasure is not pure; it cannot be called a pure good like the
 joy which would have arisen were the opposite of that over which we
 now mourn a fact, hence Descartes’ advice (cf. 24, p. 75)--to turn the
 attention and feeling in an equal degree rather to the good--would
 really not lose its significance. We recognize all this clearly, and
 have therefore, once more a preference with the character of rightness
 as the source of our knowledge of what is worthy of preference.

 In order not to introduce too many complications, I omitted in my
 lecture when discussing preferences to mention these cases. And this
 seemed to me the more admissible, because it would practically lead
 to the same result, if (like Aristotle in the case of disgraceful
 pleasure) one were to treat hate qualified as right on the one hand
 and love qualified as right on the other, as phenomena of simple
 disinclination and inclination.

 It may be easily seen that from these special cases of a possible
 determination of a quantitative relation between good and bad pleasure
 and displeasure, on the one hand, and of rightness and unrightness on
 the other hand (cf. for these also Note 31, p. 91) there is no hope of
 filling in the great gaps referred to in the lecture in a way valid
 for all cases.

 [38] (_p. 26_). Cf. my _Psych. from the Empirical Standpoint_, book
 ii. chap. iv.

 [39] (_p. 26_). E. Dumont. _Traités de législation civile et pénale,
 extraits des manuscrits de J. Bentham_; espec. in the section bearing
 the title: “Principes des législation,” chap. iii. section 1 towards
 the end; chap. vi. section 2 towards the end; and chaps. viii. and ix.

 [40] (_p. 27_). S. Rudolph Wagner. _Der Kampf um die Seele, vom
 Standpunkt der Wissenschaft._ (Sendschreiben an Herrn Leibarzt Dr.
 Beneke in Oldenburg.) Göttingen, 1857, p. 94 note. “Gauss said, the
 author (of a certain psychological work) spoke of a want of exact
 measurements in the case of psychical phenomena, but it would be good
 if we only had clumsy ones, one could then make a beginning; but we
 have none. There is here wanting the _conditio sine quâ non_ of all
 mathematical treatment, i.e. whether and how far the changing of an
 intensive into an extensive quantity is possible. Yet this is the
 first and indispensable condition; then there were also others. On
 this occasion Gauss spoke also about the usual incorrect definition
 of quantity as an ‘ens’ which is capable of being increased or
 diminished; one ought rather to say, an ‘ens’ that admits of being
 divided into equal parts....”

 [41] (_p. 27_). Fechner’s psycho-physical law, even were it assured,
 whereas it awakens continually increasing doubt and opposition, could
 only be used as a means of measuring the intensity of the content
 of certain concrete perceptions, not, however, for measuring the
 strength of the emotions like joy and sorrow. Attempts have been made
 at determining the measure of feelings by means of the involuntary
 movements and other externally visible changes accompanying them. To
 me, this seems very much as if one were to seek to reckon the exact
 date of the day of the month by means of the weather. The direct inner
 consciousness, however imperfect its testimony may be, nevertheless
 offers here far more. At least one draws from the spring itself,
 whereas in the other case one has to do with water rendered impure by
 a variety of influences.

 42
: (_p. 27_). Sigwart, in his _Vorfragen der Ethik_ (p. 42),
emphasizes the fact that no more must be required from the human will
than what it is able to perform. This utterance, which coming from the
lips of so decided an indeterminist (cf. _Logic_, ii. p. 592) may
especially excite surprise, hangs together with his subjective view of
the good, from which view, in my opinion, there is offered no logical,
normal path to the peace of all who possess a good will. (Cf. e.g. the
way in which Sigwart, p. 15, passes over from egoism to regard for the
general good.)

But similar expressions are also heard from others. And it might really
appear doubtful whether the sublime command which bids us to subordinate
all our actions to the highest practical good is really the right
ethical principle. For, putting aside cases of want of reflection, which
do not, of course, enter here into consideration, the demand for such
complete self-devotion still seems too stringent, since there is no one,
however carefully he may conduct himself, who, looking sincerely into
his heart, will not frequently be compelled to say with Horace:--

    “Nunc in Aristippi furtim praecepta relabor,
     Et mihi res, non me rebus subjungere conor.”

And yet the doubt is unfounded, and a comparison may serve to make this
clear. It is certain that no one can entirely avoid error; still,
avoidable or unavoidable, every error remains a judgment, which is what
it should not be, and is opposed to the indispensable demands of logic.
What applies to logic in respect of weakness of thought applies to
ethics on the ground of weakness of will. Ethics cannot cease to demand
from a man that he should love the acknowledged good and prefer that
which is recognized to be better, not putting anything else before the
highest practical good. Even were it proved (which is not the case),
that in a definite class of cases all men without exception in respect
of these were never able to remain true to the highest practical good,
this would still not afford the slightest justification for setting
aside the fundamental ethical demand. Even then it would still remain an
evident and unchangeable truth, the sole and only right rule, here as
everywhere, to give the preference to the better over what is less good.

J. S. Mill fears that this would lead to endless self-reproaches and
that these constant reproaches would embitter the life of each
individual. This, however, is so little implied by the rule that it is
easily demonstrable that such a result is excluded. Goethe well
understood this,--

    “Nichts taugt Ungeduld”

i.e. impatience in respect of one’s own imperfections, he says in one of
his by no means lax sayings,--

    “Noch weniger Reue,”

--giving way to the stings of conscience, when fresh joyous resolve is
alone available,--

    “Jene vermehrt die Schuld,
     Diese schafft neue.”[A]

 [A]

    “Impatience naught avails
     Nor more availeth rue,
     One addeth to the fault,
     The other maketh new.”--Tr.


In an album I once found in the hand of the pious Abbot Haneberg,
afterwards Bishop of Spires, the following lines, written to the same
effect:--

    “Sonne dich mit Lust an Gottes Huld,
     Hab’ mit allen--auch mit dir, Geduld.”[B]

 [B]

    “Bathe thyself with delight in the sunshine of heavenly grace,
     Let patience toward all men abound--e’en with thyself find a place.”--Tr.


 [43] (_p. 28_). It is necessary to be on one’s guard against drawing
 from the principle of love of our neighbour the conclusion that each
 has to _care for_ every other individual in the same degree as for
 himself, which, far from conducing towards the universal good, would
 rather essentially prejudice it. This is seen by reflecting on the
 circumstance that to ourselves we stand in a position different from
 that in which we stand to everybody else, while again in respect of
 these others we are in a position to help, or to injure, one more,
 the other less. If there are human beings in Mars the inhabitants of
 the earth can and ought to wish them good also, not however to strive
 after their good in the same manner as for himself and his fellow-men.

 It is in this connexion that the injunction to take thought in the
 first instance for oneself, a precept to be found in every system
 of morality, is justifiable: “γνῷθι σαυτόν,” “Sweep before your own
 doorstep,” etc. The demand to seek first of all the welfare of wife
 and child, home and fatherland, is also universal. The command: “Take
 no thought for the morrow,” in the sense in which it really offers
 wise counsel, also flows as a result from the same source. That
 my future happiness ought not to be so _dear_ to me as my present
 happiness is not here implied.

 So regarded, the communistic doctrines which illogical impetuosity
 would seek to derive from the lofty principle of universal brotherhood
 are shown to be unjustifiable.

 [44] (_p. 29_). The fact that we are often unable to measure the more
 remote results of our actions offers a more serious difficulty.

 But even this thought will not discourage us if we love the universal
 good. It may be said of all results which are unrecognizable in an
 exactly equal degree, that one has just as many chances in its favour
 as the others. According to the law of great numbers a compensation
 will on the whole result, and so whatever calculable good we create
 will stand as a plus on the one side and, just as though it stood
 alone, will justify our choice.

 From the same point of view, as I have already suggested in the
 lecture (p. 22), the doubt is removed which in a similar manner might
 arise through uncertainty as to whether everything that is good draws
 from us a love having the qualification of rightness, and whether,
 therefore, we are able to recognize it as good and to take due account
 of it.

 [45] (_p. 29_). That in the case of the limits of right
 (Rechtsgrenzen) we have essentially to do with spheres which lie at
 the disposal of the individual will has been frequently emphasized
 both by philosophers (cf. in this respect e.g. Herbart’s Idea of
 Right) and by able jurists. Ihering in his _Geist des römischen
 Rechts_, iii. 1 (p. 320 note), demonstrates this with numerous
 citations. Arndt e.g. in his _Handbuch der Pandekten_ defines law as
 “supremacy of the will regarding an object”; for Sintenis it is, “the
 will of one person raised to the universal will.” Windscheid defines
 it as “a certain volition (Willensinhalt) of which the legal code in
 a concrete case affirms that it may be made valid as against every
 other will.” Puchta, who has perhaps expressed the thought in the
 most manifold ways, says in his digest of Roman law, section 22, “as
 the subjects of such a _will_ thought of potentially men are called
 persons, ... personality is therefore the subjective possibility of
 the legalized will, of a legal power.” In the same work (section 118,
 note b) he observes in regard to a want of personality: “The principle
 of modern law is inability to dispose of property”; many other of his
 expressions convey the same meaning.

 As however these legal authorities have concentrated their attention
 exclusively upon legal duties, and do not touch upon the problem as to
 the way in which the individual will has to rule in its legal sphere,
 Ihering has interpreted them as meaning that they considered the
 true and highest good, and the most intrinsic and final end, towards
 which the legal code strives, to be the exercise of the will as will,
 the joy of the individual in his volitional activity; “the final end
 of all law is, for them, willing” (pp. 320, 325); “the end of law
 (according to them) consists once for all in the power of the will,
 in its supremacy” (p. 326). One can well understand how he comes to
 condemn a theory so interpreted (p. 327), and even that he succeeds
 in making it appear ridiculous. “According to this view,” he says,
 (p. 320) “all private right is nothing less than an arena in which
 the will moves and exercises itself; the will is the organ by which
 the individual enjoys his right, the profit obtained from legal right
 consists in feeling the joy and glory of power, in the satisfaction of
 having realized an act of will, e.g. of having effected a mortgage,
 transferred a title, and so proved oneself to be a legal personality.
 What a poor thing would the will be if the bare and low regions of law
 were the proper “sphere of its activity!”

 Certainly the heaviest charges of absurdity and ridiculousness would
 be well deserved if those scholars who regard the _immediate_ aim of
 law as consisting in a limitation of the spheres at the disposal of
 the will had intended in so doing to disavow all regard for the _final
 ethical end_, i.e. the advancement of the highest practical good.
 There is, however, absolutely nothing to justify this insinuation,
 and therefore one could perhaps with more right smile at the zeal
 of an attack which is really levelled merely against windmills.
 Moreover, what Ihering proposes to set in its place is certainly a
 bad substitute. For, in regarding the sphere ascribed by the legal
 authority to the individual simply as a sphere consigned to their
 egoism (a view which, as the author of _Der Zweck im Recht_, he
 perhaps no longer holds), he is thus led to his definition: “Law
 (Recht) is legal security for enjoyment,” whereas he would have been
 more correct in saying: “Law is legal security for the undisturbed
 disposal of individual power in the advancement of the highest good.”
 Is then injustice something which exhausts bad conduct? By no means;
 legal duties have limits; duty in general governs all our actions,
 and this our popular religion expressly emphasizes, as, for instance,
 when it asserts that for every idle word the individual must render an
 account.

 Besides this first objection, which rests upon a simple
 misunderstanding of the intention, Ihering has also raised several
 others which are essentially due to imperfections in the use of
 language. If the legal code essentially consists in setting certain
 limits to the activity of the individual will in order that one person
 may not disturb the other in striving after the good, it follows that
 he who has, or had, or will have no will has also no legal sphere. I
 say, “has, or had, or will have,” for obviously regard must be paid to
 the past and to the future. A dead man often exercises an influence
 extending into the far distant future, so that Comte well says: the
 living are more and more dominated by the dead. In like manner, the
 situation will entail that, in respect of many problems, we leave
 the decision to the future, i.e. renounce the sovereignty in favour
 of a future will. This consideration resolves many a paradox urged
 by Ihering (pp. 320-325); not however, all. In the case of one who
 from birth has been an incurable imbecile, it is obvious that no
 power of will whatever can be found, to which regard for the highest
 practical good might allow a sphere; there remains therefore to him,
 according to our view, really no legal sphere, and yet on every hand
 we hear of a right which he possesses in his own life; even under
 some circumstances, we refer to him as the owner of a great estate,
 or ascribe to him the right of a crown or kingly rule. On examining
 the relations closely, we find that we are never concerned here with
 a true legal sphere respecting a subject incapable of being held
 responsible, but rather with the legal spheres of other individuals,
 as, for example, that of a father who, in providing for his imbecile
 child, gives instructions in his will concerning his property, the
 dominion of whose will is safeguarded after his death by the law of
 the land; or (as, for example, the case where the imbecile’s life is
 held to be sacred), quite apart from the injury done to the simple
 duty of affection which this would involve, there is also in question
 the State’s legal sphere, which permits no one else to commit a fatal
 attack, and accordingly often imposes a punishment, even in the case
 of an attempt at suicide.

 A third objection of Ihering’s, i.e. that by a limitation of rights
 as affecting spheres of will, even the most senseless dispositions of
 will must be allowed legal validity (p. 325), this offers, after what
 has been said, hardly any further difficulty. Certainly many a foolish
 disposition of will must be allowed. Were the State not to admit
 this, then it alone would possess a definitive right of disposal; all
 private right would be at an end. So long as not merely subjects, but
 also governments, are liable to commit acts of foolishness, such an
 extension of the power of the State cannot be recommended. For the
 rest, just as secondary ethical rules in general suffer exceptions,
 and in particular expropriations in the case of private owners are
 frequently necessary, so also it is clear and to be admitted without
 contradiction, that senseless dispositions or dispositions which have
 evidently lost all meaning and reference to the highest practical good
 can be annulled by the State. Regard for the highest practical good
 is here, as is the case of every other so-called collision of duties,
 decisive.

 [46] (_p. 29_). That a law, which in and for itself is bad and
 contrary to nature, however condemnable from an ethical point of view,
 and its modification urgently necessary, may yet in many cases receive
 a provisional sanction from the reason, this has long been recognized
 and made clear, as e.g. by Bentham in his _Traités de Législation
 civ. et pén._ In antiquity Socrates, who deemed himself worthy to be
 feasted in the Prytaneum, died for the sake of this conviction. The
 positive legal code, despite all its defects, creates a condition
 of things which is better than anarchy, and since each act of
 insubordination to the law threatens to injure its force in general,
 so in those circumstances brought about by the law itself, it may be
 that provisionally and for the individual a mode of action even from
 the rational standpoint is right, which, apart from this, would be in
 no way justifiable. All this results without doubt from the relativity
 of the secondary ethical rules, which will be treated later.

 It may be added that errors respecting the laws of positive morality
 (a point shortly to be discussed in the lecture) in a similar way
 demand, under certain circumstances, to be taken into account.

 It dare not, on the other hand, be overlooked that there are here
 limits, and that the saying: “We ought to obey God rather than man,”
 may not, in its free and sublime range, be allowed to suffer injury.

 [47] (_p. 29_). Heraclitus of Ephesus (B.C. 500), the
 oldest of the Greek philosophers, of whose philosophy we possess
 rather extensive fragments.

 [48] (_p. 31_). Ihering, _Der Zweck im Recht_, vol. ii. p. 119, and
 other passages.

 [49] (_p. 31_). _Politics_, vol. i. chap. 5.

 [50] (_p. 31_). _Nic. Ethics_, v. 14, p. 1137 b. 13. _Politics_, iii.
 and iv.

 [51] (_p. 31_). Cf. Discours préliminaire to the _Traités de
 Législation_, also the section “De l’influence des temps et des lieux
 en matière de législation” of that work.

 [52] (_p. 31_). _Philos. Versuch über die Wahrscheinlichkeiten von
 Laplace_, translated from the sixth edition of the original text by N.
 Schwaiger, Leipzig, 1886, p. 93 seq. (Application of the calculation
 of probabilities to moral science.)

 [53] (_p. 32_). Cf. _Allg. Juristenzeitung_, vii. p. 171; _Zweck im
 Recht_, vol. ii. p. 118; 122 seq.

 [54] (_p. 33_). _Grundlegung zur Physik der Sitten._ Cf. above note
 14, p. 49.

 [55] (_p. 34_). Cf. e.g. the Meno dialogue.

 [56] (_p. 34_). Friedr. Alb. Lange, _Logische Studien, ein Beitrag zur
 Neubegründung der formalen Logik und der Erkenntnislehre_. Iserlohn,
 1877.

 [57] (_p. 34_). Alex. Bain, _Logic_, pt. 1. Deduction. London, 1870,
 p. 159 seq.

 [58] (_p. 35_). e.g. Bentham, also, in antiquity, Epicurus.

 [59] (_p. 35_). e.g. Plato and Aristotle, and following them Thomas
 Aquinas.

 [60] (_p. 35_). The Stoics, and in the Middle Ages, the followers of
 Scotus.

 [61] (_p. 36_). This even Epicurus did not deny (little in harmony as
 it is with his utterance quoted p. 54).

 [62] (_p. 36_). _Nic. Ethics_, I. i.

 [63] (_p. 36_). _Metaph._ Δ 10.

 [64] (_p. 36_). _Metaph._ Δ 10.

 [65] (_p. 36_). They made the relation to the greater whole serve as
 an argument in favour of the view that the practical life (of the
 politician) stands higher than that of the theorist.

 [66] (_p. 36_). This testimony to the principle of summation likewise
 reappears as often as in a theory based upon egoistic and utilitarian
 grounds, the notion of God is employed in the construction of ethics
 (e.g. Locke; Fechner in his work on the highest good; cf. also for
 Leibnitz, Trendelenburg, _Histor. Beiträge_, vol. ii. p. 245). God,
 so runs their argument, loves each of His creatures, and therefore
 their totality more than the single individual; He therefore approves
 and rewards the sacrifice of the individual to the whole, while
 disapproving and punishing self-seeking injury.

 In the desire after immortality also, the influence of the principle
 of summation is manifest. Thus Helmholtz, (_über die Entstehung des
 Planetensystems_, lecture delivered at Heidelberg and Cologne, 1871),
 in seeking to offer a hopeful prospect to those who cherish this
 desire, says: “The individual (if that which we achieve can ennoble
 the lives of those who succeed us) may face fearlessly the thought
 that the thread of his own consciousness will one day be broken. But
 to the thought of a final annihilation of the race of living mortals,
 and with them, the fruits of the striving of all past generations,
 even men of minds so unfettered and great as Lessing and David Strauss
 could scarcely reconcile themselves.” When it is scientifically shown
 that the earth will one day be incapable of supporting living beings,
 then, he thinks, the need of immortality will irresistibly return, and
 we shall feel bound to cast about for something which will afford us
 the possibility of assuming it.

 [67] (_p. 34_). _Metaph._ Δ 10.

 [68] (_p. 37_). This is the standing doctrine of the great
 theologians, as e.g. Thomas Aquinas in his _Summa Theologica_.
 Only certain nominalists, like Robert Holcot, teach the complete
 arbitrariness of the divine commands. Cf. my essay on the _Geschichte
 der kirchlichen Wissenschaften im Mittelalter_, in Möhler’s _Church
 History_ (published by Gams, 1867) vol. ii. 526 seq., respecting
 which, however, the reader is asked not to overlook the revision of
 the printer’s errors in the “errata,” p. 103 seq., at the end of that
 work.

 [69] (_p. 39_). At a time when psychology was far less advanced
 and inquiries into the province of the calculation of probability
 had not brought sufficient clearness into the process of rational
 induction, it was possible even for a Hume to fall a victim to this
 gross confusion. Cf. his _Enq. concern. Hum. Underst._, chaps. v.
 and vi. More striking is it that James Mill and Herbert Spencer have
 still not advanced in the slightest degree beyond Hume; (Cf. _Anal.
 of the Phen. of the Hum. Mind_, vol. ii. chap. ix. and note 108), and
 that even the acute thinker, J. S. Mill, although Laplace’s _Essai
 Philosophique sur les Probabilités_ lay at his disposal, never arrived
 at a clear distinction of the essential difference between these two
 forms of procedure. This hangs together with his failure to appreciate
 the purely analytic character of mathematics and the import of the
 deductive procedure in general. Indeed he has absolutely denied that
 the syllogism leads to new knowledge. Whoever bases the whole of
 mathematics upon induction cannot possibly justify mathematically the
 inductive procedure. It would be for him a _circulus vitiosus_. It is
 here beyond question that Jevon’s _Logic_ takes a truer view.

 Even in the case of Mill, it sometimes appears as if an inkling of
 the immense difference had begun to dawn upon him, as when, in a note
 to his _Analysis of the Phenomena of the Human Mind_ (vol. i., chap.
 xi. p. 407), in criticizing his father’s theory, he says: “If belief
 is only an inseparable association, belief is a matter of _habit_
 and accident and not of reason. Assuredly an association, however
 close, between two ideas is not a sufficient _ground_ (the italics
 are his own) of belief; it is not evidence that the corresponding
 facts are united in external nature. The theory seems to annihilate
 all distinction between the belief of the wise, _which is regulated
 by evidence_ and conforms to the real successions and co-existences
 of the facts of the universe, and the belief of fools _which is
 mechanically produced_ by any accidental association that suggests
 the idea of a succession or co-existence to the mind; a belief aptly
 characterized by the popular expression, believing a thing because
 they have taken it into their heads.” This is all excellent. But it
 is robbed of its most essential worth, when, in a later note (vol.
 i. p. 438. note 110) we hear J. S. Mill say: “It must be conceded to
 him (the author of the _Analysis_) that an association sufficiently
 strong to exclude all ideas that would exclude itself, _produces
 a kind of mechanical belief_, and that the processes by which the
 belief is corrected, or reduced to rational bounds, _all consist in
 the growth of a counter-association_ tending to raise the idea of a
 disappointment of the first expectation, and as the one or the other
 prevails in the particular case, the belief or expectation exists or
 does not exist exactly as if the belief were the same thing with the
 association,” and so on.

 There is much here that calls for criticism. When ideas are mentioned
 which mutually exclude one another it may well be asked what kind
 of ideas these are? According to another utterance of Mill’s (vol.
 i. p. 98 seq. note 30 and elsewhere), he knows “no case of absolute
 incompatibility of thought except between the thought of the
 presence of something and that of its absence.” But are even these
 incompatible? Mill himself teaches elsewhere the very opposite when he
 thinks that along with the idea of existence there is always given at
 the same time the idea of non-existence (p. 126, note 39; “we are only
 conscious,” he says, “of the presence of an object by comparison with
 its absence”). Apart, however, from all this, how strange is it that
 Mill here overlooks the fact that he abandons entirely the distinctive
 character of self-evidence, and retains only that blind and mechanical
 formation of judgment, which he rightly treats with contempt. The
 sceptic Hume stands in this respect far higher, since he at least sees
 that such an empirical (empiristisch) view of the process of induction
 does not satisfy the requirements of our reason. Sigwart’s criticism
 of Mill’s theory of Induction (_Logic_, vol. ii. p. 371) contains
 here much that is true, though in appealing to his postulates he has
 certainly not substituted anything truly satisfactory in the place of
 what is defective in Mill.

 [70] (_p. 40_). Cf. Hume, _Enquiry concerning Human Understanding_,
 vol. ii. towards the end.

 [71] (_p. 40_). _Nic. Ethics_, iii. 10. Cf. the subtle discussions in
 the subsequent chapter on the five kinds of false courage.

 [72] (_p. 41_). _Nic. Ethics_, i. 2.



APPENDIX I



I

“Subjectless propositions” so the celebrated philologer has entitled a
little work which, on its first appearance, bore the title, _The Verba
Impersonalia in the Slav Languages_.

The change of name may well be connected with considerable additions in
the second edition. The new designation would, however, even in the
earlier form, have been the more suitable title. For, far from treating
the special nature of merely _one_ family of languages, the author sets
up a theory of wide-reaching significance, which, while contradicting
the prevailing view, only deserves all the more on this account general
attention. Not only philology, but also psychology and metaphysics have
an interest in the problem. Moreover, the new doctrine promised to bring
profit not only to the inquirer in these lofty spheres but also to the
schoolboy at present tortured by the school-master with impossible and
incomprehensible theories (cf. p. 23 seq.).

Such an influence, however, the treatise has not exercised. The earlier
views still hold unbroken sway even to-day, and although the appearance
of the monograph in a new edition bears testimony to a certain interest
in wider circles, this is manifestly not due to the circumstance that
the work was believed to have thrown light upon old doubts and errors.
Darwin’s epoch-making work, quite apart from the truth of its
hypothesis, had, even for its opponents, an indisputable worth; the
wealth of important observations and ingenious combinations every one
had to acknowledge with admiration. So also in the case of Miklosich,
who has compressed into a few pages a rich store of learning and
interspersed the most subtle observations. Many who have withheld their
assent to his principal thesis may still feel indebted to him for many
points of detail.

Here, however, we wish chiefly to consider the main problem and, very
briefly, to make ourselves clear respecting that with which it really
deals.

It is an old assertion of logic that the judgment consists essentially
in a binding or separating, in a relation of ideas to one another. This
view, almost unanimously maintained for two thousand years, has
exercised an influence upon other disciplines. And so we find
grammarians from very early times teaching that no more simple form of
expression in the case of the judgment exists, or can exist, than the
categorical, which combines a subject with a predicate.

That the carrying out of this doctrine brings with it difficulties could
not, of course, be permanently concealed. Propositions like: it rains,
it lightens, appear as though they had no wish to conform to this view.
Yet none the less the majority of inquirers were so firmly convinced,
that in such cases they felt compelled, not so much to doubt the
universal validity of their theory as rather to search for the subjects,
which in their view were only apparently missing. Many really believed
themselves to be in possession of the same. Now, however, in marked
contrast to the unity which had hitherto prevailed, they branched off in
the most varied directions. And if we examine somewhat closely and in
detail the various attempts at an explanation, we shall easily be able
to understand, why none of these were able to give permanent
satisfaction, or even for a time to bring about unanimity.

Science explains by reason of its comprehending a multiplicity as a
unity. Here also, of course, every effort has been made to accomplish
this, but every attempt has proved futile. When we say: it rains, many
have supposed that the unnamed subject denoted by the indefinite “it” is
“Zeus”: Zeus rains. But when we say: “es rauscht,” it is obvious that
Zeus cannot be the subject. Others again have thought that the subject
is here “das Rauschen”; consequently the meaning of the proposition
would be: “das Rauschen rauscht.” The previous example they also
completed in the same manner: “Raining, (or the rain) rains.”

When, however, we now say: “es fehlt an Geld,” the meaning must
therefore be: “das Fehlen an Geld fehlt an Geld.” But this is absurd. It
was therefore explained that the subject here is “Geld,” and the meaning
of the proposition is: “Geld fehlt an Geld.” Closely examined, this
would seem to strike a blow at the wished-for unity of explanation. If,
however, by closing one eye, the failure here may be partially ignored,
even this is useless when we stumble upon propositions like: “es giebt
einen Gott,” respecting which we arrive at no satisfactory meaning
either in the proposition: “das einen Gott geben giebt einen Gott; das
Geben giebt einen Gott,” or in the proposition, “Gott giebt einen Gott.”

It was therefore necessary to look for an explanation of an entirely
different character. But where was such an explanation to be found? And
even if ingenuity were here able to hit upon some expedient, what
availed such leaping from case to case, which could only be called the
caricature of a truly scientific explanation? Not a single designation
of the subject which has been so far suggested, can be termed suitable,
unless indeed it be a saying of Schleiermacher’s. For if this
philosopher (cf. p. 16) has really asserted that the subject in such
cases is _chaos_, this utterance must be regarded, not so much as an
attempt at explanation as rather a satire upon the hypotheses hitherto
set up by philologists.

Many inquirers are therefore of opinion that the real subjects of such
propositions as: it rains, it lightens, have, up to the present time,
not been discovered, and that even at the present time it is the
business of science to find them. But, would it not be strange if the
tracing of a subject, which is thought of by everyone, and which, though
unexpressed, forms the basis of the judgment, should yet offer such
extraordinary difficulties?

Steinthal seeks to explain this by saying that by the grammatical
subject something is suggested, which is yet unthinkable. But many will
reply with Miklosich (p. 23): “We would not, I think, be going too far
in asserting that grammar is not concerned with the unthinkable.”

The totality of the phenomena and the absolutely grotesque failure of
every attempt to determine the nature of the subject, however often and
however ingeniously this has been attempted, are the chief grounds on
which Miklosich bases his assertion that, generally speaking, the
supposed subject in the case of such propositions is a delusion, that
the proposition is no combination of subject and predicate, that, as
Miklosich expresses it, the proposition is subjectless.

Further reflections go to confirm this view, and among these one
consideration as to the nature of the judgment requires to be emphasized
on account of its special importance. Miklosich combats those who, like
Steinthal, deny that there is any reciprocal relation between grammar
and logic, at the same time repelling the attacks which, on the ground
of such a reciprocal relation, might be made against his doctrine by
psychologists and logicians. Indeed he arrives at the result that, in
consequence of the special peculiarity of certain judgments, subjectless
propositions must from the very first be expected in language. According
to his view it is wrong to suppose that every judgment is a relation
existing between ideas. It often happens that in a proposition only one
fact is affirmed or denied. In such cases a mode of expression is also
necessary, and it is obvious that this cannot well consist in a
combination of subject and predicate. Miklosich shows how philosophers
have been repeatedly led to this knowledge, though, as a rule, they have
not appreciated sufficiently the significance of their discovery. Not
sufficiently clear themselves as to the new truth to which they gave
expression, and, at the same time, clinging with strange indecision to
certain residues of the older view, it came about that what at first
they affirmed they at last essentially deny. Thus Trendelenburg chose to
find expressed in the proposition, “it lightens,” in the last resort, no
real judgment, but only the rudiments of a judgment which precedes the
notion of lightning and settles down into it, thereby forming the basis
for the complete judgment, “lightning is conducted by iron.” Herbart
finally declared such judgments as “es rauscht,” to be no judgments in
the ordinary sense, not, he thought, what in logic is, strictly
speaking, termed a judgment. The passage in which our author censures
the inconsistency of these philosophers, and shows that the source of
their confusion lies in their misunderstanding of the nature of judgment
and in their erroneous definition of it (p. 21 seq.), is excellent.

From all this Miklosich draws the conclusion that his subjectless
propositions are completely assured. And not only does he consider their
existence beyond doubt, he further shows that their appearance is by no
means so rare as might be supposed from the controversy into which it
has been necessary to enter concerning them. Their great variety had led
him, in the second part of his treatise (pp. 33-72) to set forth their
chief classes, and there we find subjectless propositions with the
Active Verb, the Reflexive Verb, the Passive Verb and the verb “to be,”
each of these four classes being illustrated by means of numerous
examples from the most various languages. This is especially the case
with the first class, where he makes an eightfold division with the
object of grouping the propositions according to the difference in their
content. He mentions as universally true (p. 6) that the finite verb of
the subjectless propositions always stands in the third person singular,
and, where the form admits a difference of gender, in the neuter.

In other directions also he traces the matter further. He shows how
these propositions did not arise later than those which predicate
something of a subject, but appear from the very outset among the
various forms of propositions (p. 13 seq., p. 19), and how, in the
course of time, they have disappeared from several languages (p. 26). He
proves that the languages in which they are preserved enjoy an
advantage, inasmuch as their application lends to the language a special
liveliness (26), and he shows how in other respects also it is not
always possible to substitute for the subjectless proposition the
categorical form, with which it is supposed to be identical. “Ich
friere” is, for instance, not fully identical with “mich friert.”
Instead of, was frierst du draussen? Komme doch herein! we cannot say:
was friert dich’s draussen? etc. “Mich friert” cannot be applied if I
expose myself voluntarily to the cold (p. 37).


II

This, shortly, is the substance of his book, regarding which I venture
to make a few critical observations.

I have sufficiently expressed in this summary, my approval of the
treatise in general, especially in respect of the main argument. The
proofs appear to me to be of so cogent a nature, that even the unwilling
will scarcely be able to escape from the truth. Quite independent of
these arguments, however, I had myself, long ago, arrived at the same
view, by way of a purely psychological analysis, and gave, in the most
decisive manner, public expression to it, when in 1874 I published my
_Psychology_.

Great, however, as were the pains I then took to set the teaching in a
clear light and to show every former view untenable, my success so far
has been slight. Apart from isolated individuals, I have been just as
little able to convince the philosopher, as Miklosich, in his first
edition, was able to convince philologists. Where a prejudice has,
during centuries, become ever more and more firmly rooted, where a
doctrine has penetrated even to the primary school, when a theory has
come to be regarded as fundamental upon which much else rests, and so,
as it were, by its weight rendered the foundation immovable, in such a
case, it is not to be expected that the error will immediately disappear
as soon as its refutation is established; on the contrary, it is to be
feared that distrust of the new view will be so great, as not even to
admit of a closer examination being made regarding the grounds on which
it rests. And yet when two investigators completely independent of each
other agree in their testimony, when by quite different paths they
arrive at the same goal, it may be hoped that this concurrence will not
be regarded as a mere coincidence, but that a more careful attention
will be bestowed upon the arguments on either side. I hope that this
will be so in the case of the new edition of Miklosich, in which I am
glad to see regard paid to my own work.

The agreement with regard to the main points makes subordinate points,
in respect of which we differ, of less moment. I shall, notwithstanding,
briefly touch on these.

Miklosich has termed those simple propositions, in which there is
contained no combination of subject and predicate, and in the
recognition of which I am in agreement with him, “subjectless
propositions.” I am not able entirely to approve his _use_ of the term
and the _grounds_ which he has given for its use.

Subject and predicate are correlative conceptions and stand or fall
together. A proposition which is truly without a subject must with equal
right be regarded as without a predicate. It does not therefore seem to
me quite fitting that Miklosich should always term such propositions
subjectless, and it is quite incorrect when he calls them mere
predicative propositions. (Cf. pp. 3, 25, 26, and elsewhere.) This might
suggest the view that he likewise believes a second conception (the
subject) is understood though not expressed, had he not in the most
decided manner denied this (p. 3 seq. and elsewhere); or that he
regarded such propositions as stunted forms of categorical propositions,
and the latter form as the original, had he not expressly refuted this
also (p. 13 seq.). His view rather seems to be, that the natural
development from the simple to the categorical form in thinking and
speaking is generally accomplished in such a way that the notion which
stands alone in the former proposition is combined with a second as
subject. “The subjectless propositions,” he says, p. 25, “are
propositions which consist only of a predicate, of what, in the natural
process of thought-formation must, in a great number of propositions, be
regarded as the prius, for which a subject may, but not necessarily
_must_ be sought.”

But this also can hardly be right, and the expression “subject” scarcely
seems to favour this view. That which forms the basis is, of course,
certainly that which in the construction of the judgment stands first.
The temporal succession of the words also agrees ill with such a view,
since, in the categorical proposition, we usually begin with the
subject. In opposition to such a view it may also be contended that the
emphasis usually falls upon the predicate (and Trendelenburg has made
use of this to indicate that the predicate is the main conception, and
even with exaggeration goes on to say: “We think in predicates,” cf. p.
19). If the predicative conception is what is newly added, it will,
accordingly, be the object of greater interest. On the other hand, we
would be compelled to expect exactly the opposite if the notion of the
subject contained the newly added moment.

It may just as truly be said, “a bird is black,” as, “something black is
a bird”; “Socrates is a man,” as, “a man is Socrates”; but Aristotle has
already observed that only the former predication is natural, the latter
form is opposed to the natural order. And this is really so far true,
that we naturally make _that_ term the subject to which we first pay
regard in forming a judgment, or to which the hearer must first attend
in order to understand the proposition, or to gain knowledge as to its
truth or falsity. We can be assured of the existence of a black bird by
seeking it among birds or among black objects, more easily, however,
among the former. In the same way we may be more easily assured that an
individual belongs to a particular species or genus by analysing its
nature than by running over the entire range of the corresponding
general notion. The cases of exceptions clearly confirm the rule and the
grounds on which it rests, as, for instance, when I say: “There is
something black; this something black is a bird,” in which case it is
just because I have first recognized the colour that I accordingly make
it the subject in the categorical proposition so formed.

Of the two categorical Sorites, the Aristotelian and the Goclenian, the
former in every succeeding link makes that term the subject which is
common to it and to the one preceding, the latter form makes it the
predicate. It is just on this account that the former appears the more
natural, and as such is generally regarded as the regular, the latter as
the reversed form. In like manner where, to a proposition not consisting
of a combination of ideas, we add a categorical proposition having one
term in common with the former, we usually apply this not as a predicate
but as a subject, and we should therefore prefer to say that a predicate
has been sought for a subject rather than that a subject has been
sought for a predicate. For example: es rauscht; das Rauschen kommt von
einem Bache (there is a sound of running water; the sound comes from the
brook). Es donnert; der Donner verkündet ein nahendes Gewitter (it
thunders; the thunder heralds an approaching storm). Es riecht nach
Rosen; dieser Rosengeruch kommt aus dem Nachbargarten (there is a smell
of roses; the rose-scent comes from a neighbour’s garden). Es wird
gelacht; das Gelächter gilt dem Hanswurste (there is laughter; the
laughter is due to the clown). Es fehlt an Geld; dieser Geldmangel ist
die Ursache der Stockung der Geschäfte (there is a lack of money; this
dearth of money is the cause of the depression in trade). Es giebt einen
Gott; dieser Gott ist der Schöpfer des Himmels und der Erde (there is a
God; this God is the maker of heaven and earth), etc., etc.

Only in _one_ sense, therefore, does the term “subjectless proposition”
appear to me justifiable, and even perhaps deserving of recommendation,
in so far as regard is paid to the fact, that the notion which is
contained thereby is the only, and therefore, of course, the main
conception; a preference which in the categorical proposition belongs,
as we have seen, to the predicate. Similarly also in respect of
categorical in relation to hypothetical propositions we would much
rather say that they are propositions without an antecedent, than
propositions without a consequent proposition; not as though we meant
that where there is no antecedent there may still be a consequent
proposition, but that in the hypothetical construction the consequent is
the main proposition. In this way then I might perhaps agree with the
author respecting the term “subjectless proposition.”

Another point, however, in which I am unable fully to agree with him is
the question as to what extent subjectless propositions are applicable.
Miklosich rightly emphasizes the fact that the limits are on no account
to be drawn too tightly. But he thinks such limits at any rate exist,
and this is just what is shown most clearly in his attempt to classify
and divide the varied nature of the matter capable of being expressed by
subjectless sentences. But this appears to me incorrect. The
applicability of the subjectless form may, strictly speaking, be rather
regarded as unlimited, since--as I believe I have already shown in my
_Psychology_--every judgment, whether expressed in categorical,
hypothetical or disjunctive form admits, without the slightest
alteration in the sense, of being expressed in the form of a subjectless
proposition or, as I expressed it, of an existential proposition. Thus
the proposition, “A man is ill,” is synonymous with “There is a sick
man”; and the proposition, “All men are mortal,” with the proposition,
“There is no immortal man,” and the like.[A]

 [A] Supplementary note. What is here said of the general applicability
 of the existential form holds good only with the one manifest
 limitation, in respect of judgments which are really completely
 simple. In expressing such judgment logic has always made use of
 the categorical form; in common life they are often applied as the
 expression of a plurality of judgments based upon each other. This
 is clearly the case in the proposition, “this is a man.” In the
 demonstrative “this” the belief in existence is already included; a
 second judgment then ascribes to him the predicate “man.” Similar
 cases are frequent elsewhere. In my opinion it was the original
 purpose of the categorical form to serve as a means of expressing
 such double judgments (Doppelurteile), which recognize something
 while affirming or denying something else of it. I also believe that
 the existential and impersonal forms have, by a change in function,
 proceeded from this form. This does not alter its essential nature:
 a lung is not a swim-bladder (Fisch-blase) even though it has
 developed therefrom, and the word “kraft” is none the less a merely
 syncategorematic word (Cf. Mill, _Logic_, i. 2, § 2), even though its
 origin may be traced to a substantive.

In yet another direction Miklosich appears to me to have limited too
narrowly the applicability of his subjectless propositions. We have
heard that such propositions constitute “an excellence in a language,”
“respecting which all languages are very far from being able to boast”
(p. 26). This, however, appears scarcely credible if it be true, as in
another passage he has so convincingly shown, that there are and always
have been judgments which do not consist in any combination of two ideas
with each other, and which therefore it is impossible to express by
means of a connexion of a subject with a predicate (p. 16). From this
must follow, not merely, as Miklosich _affirms_, the necessary existence
of subjectless propositions generally, but further (which he _denies_)
the existence of such propositions in all languages.

That the author has here fallen into error seems to me partly explicable
from the fact that in order to proceed with the utmost caution and lay
claim to no unwarrantable example, he has not ventured to regard certain
propositions as subjectless, which, in truth, really are so. We saw that
Miklosich expressed the view that the finite verb of subjectless
propositions always stands in the third person of the singular, and,
when the form admits a difference of gender, in the neuter. This was
certainly too narrow a limit, a limit which he himself transgresses,
though this appears in a much later passage. In the second part of his
treatise he says: “In ‘es ist ein Gott,’ the notion ‘Gott’ is affirmed
absolutely without a subject, and this is also the case in the
proposition ‘_es sind Götter_’”; and he adds: The “ist” of the
existential proposition _takes the place of the so-called copula “ist,”_
which in many, though by no means in all, languages, is indispensable to
the expression of the judgment, and has the same significance as the
termination of person in the finite verb as is clearly shown in the
proposition “es ist Sommer, es ist Nacht” alongside the propositions,
“es sommert, es nachtet.” “Ist” is accordingly not a predicate (p. 34;
cf. also p. 21 above). As a matter of fact, if the proposition, “es
giebt einen Gott,” is to be considered subjectless, so also must the
proposition, “es ist ein Gott,” and therefore also, “es sind Götter”;
and thus the rule previously laid down has proved to be too narrow. That
the existential propositions and other analogous forms, which may be
found, are all to be reckoned as subjectless propositions may serve to
confirm what we have sought to show above, i.e. that no language exists,
or can exist, which entirely dispenses with these simplest forms of
propositions. Only certain special kinds of subjectless propositions
therefore, am I able, with Miklosich, to recognize as the peculiar
advantage of certain languages.

These are the criticisms which I have thought it necessary to make. It
will be seen that, if found to be justified, they do not in the
slightest degree prejudice either the correctness or the value of the
author’s main argument, but rather lend to it a still wider
significance. And so I conclude by expressing once again the wish that
this suggestive little work, which, on its first appearance did not
meet with sufficient general recognition, may in its second
edition--where individual points have been corrected, much extended, and
particularly the critical objections of scholars like Benfey, Steinthal
and others, refuted with a laconic brevity, yet rare dialectical
power--find that interest which the importance of the inquiry and its
excellent treatment deserve.



APPENDIX II


Franz Brentano, son of Christian Brentano, and nephew of Clemens
Brentano and Bettina von Arnim, was born on January 16, 1838, at
Marienberg, near Boppard on the Rhine. He early embraced the study of
philosophy and theology, both at Berlin, under Trendelenburg, and also
at Munich. In 1864 he was ordained priest, and two years later became
_privat docent_ in the University of Würzburg. In 1873 he was appointed
professor there, but in the same year resigned his office in consequence
of his changed attitude towards the Church, and as an opponent of the
Vatican Council. Somewhat later, in response to this change in his
convictions, he separated himself definitely from the Church.

In 1874 Brentano received a call to the University of Vienna, and
continued there teaching Philosophy until 1895, first as ordinary
professor, and afterwards, having meantime renounced his professorship,
as _privat docent_. The reasons which led him to retire from this post
also, are set forth in his work, _My Last Wishes for Austria_
(Stuttgart, 1895). After withdrawing from his post as teacher he took up
his residence at Florence.

Brentano regards Aristotle as his real teacher in philosophy, and his
two earliest publications, _Von der mannigfachen Bedeutung des Seienden
nach Aristoteles_ (Freiburg, i. Br. 1862), and _Die Psychologie des
Aristoteles insbesondere seine Lehre vom_ νοῦς ποιητικός (Mainz, 1867),
are a testimony to his comprehensive study and thorough knowledge of
Aristotelian philosophy. Especially is he in agreement with the
Stagirite regarding the high position he would assign to the application
of the empirical method as the only one which, in regard alike to
scientific and philosophical problems, is able by cautious and gradual
advance, to attain to knowledge. These first principles of method,
especially in their relation to psychological research, he has set forth
and practised in his first systematic work, _Psychologie vom Empirischen
Standpunkte_ (vol. i., Leipzig, 1874). It was also his regard for this
method of inquiry which early imbued him with a special interest for the
works of the most eminent English philosophers of modern times, not only
John Locke and David Hume, but also Bentham, the two Mills, Jevons and
others. A study of these writers led Brentano to enter at length in his
Würzburg lectures into a critical and explanatory treatment of English
psychology and logic, characterizing it as a source of instruction and
inspiration at a time when other distinguished advocates of German
philosophy looked askance at this attitude towards English thought,
believing that by its contact with English writers the peculiar
character of German thought might suffer. It will be observed that only
the first volume of the _Psychology from the Empirical Standpoint_ has
hitherto appeared, and it seems hardly likely that the work in its
present form will be continued, for further reflection convinced
Brentano that _descriptive_[A] psychology, or Psychognosy, as of most
importance in the examination and presentation of psychological
problems, must be separated from _genetic psychology_,[B] a study
necessarily half physiological in character; and that the former problem
as the naturally earlier and least difficult study should first be as
far as possible completed.

 [A] i.e. the closest possible description and analysis of psychical
 _events_ and their contents, on the basis of inner observation.

 [B] i.e. the more difficult inquiry into the laws underlying the
 origin of phenomena.

Such _psychognostical inquiries_, although not yet in principle
separated from genetic inquiry, occupy by far the greater part of the
first volume of the _Psychology from the Empirical Standpoint_. Among
the subjects there treated are: 1, the fundamental revision of the
classification of psychical phenomena, and their division into the three
main classes: ideas, judgments, and phenomena of love and hate; 2, and
in particular, a new and more appropriate characterization of the
judgment.

The insufficiency of the old doctrine according to which judgment
consists essentially in a connexion of ideas, had already been shown by
Hume, and more recently was strongly emphasized by Mill, though neither
was able to arrive at perfect clearness respecting its real nature.
Notwithstanding this, the affinity of Brentano’s doctrine of the
judgment with that of Mill, led to a scientific correspondence, and
later to arrangements for a personal interview, when, at the last
moment, the plan was frustrated by the death of the great English
investigator.

The new description of the judgment and its essential qualities form the
basis for a reform of logic even in its most elementary stages, a reform
which, in its essential features, is suggested in the above-mentioned
work, and also touched upon in the Essay here translated; but this truer
description of the phenomenon of judgment also throws light upon the
description and classification of the _modes of speech from the point of
view of their function or meaning_,--a classification based upon true
and most essential distinctions. In comparison with phonetics this
branch is still little developed. What is here said, was seen by eminent
philologists like Fr. von Miklosich, the pioneer in the sphere of Slav
comparative philology. In the appendix will be found an article bearing
upon this view.

While engaged in a profound study of the descriptive peculiarities
connected with the third fundamental class of psychical states above
referred to--a study analogous to that previously undertaken by him with
regard to the judgment--Brentano was led to the discovery of the
_principles of ethical knowledge_ which form the subject of this
lecture. The author, in his lectures delivered before students of all
faculties, but especially to students in the faculty of law, during each
winter session throughout many years, presented a complete and fully
developed system of ethical teaching based upon these principles.[A]
Unfortunately, this lecture still remains unpublished. The same holds
good of many of his inquiries into “descriptive psychology,” or
psychognosie, e.g. inquiries into the nature of sense perceptions
according to their qualitative and spatial nature, the nature of the
continuum, the time phenomenon, etc., the results of which are hitherto
familiar only to those who have either attended his lectures, or have
been present during private conversations.

 [A] Since this essay was written the statements as to the principles
 here developed have been modified only in respect of two points which,
 if not practically important, are still theoretically so, and these,
 with the author’s permission, may be here shortly referred to:--

 1. In the lecture (p. 15) it is said that anything may be either
 affirmed or denied, and that if the affirmation is right its denial
 must be considered wrong, and vice versâ. It is also stated that this
 is true analogously in respect of love and hate.

 This Brentano no longer asserts, but rather observes that whereas the
 whole must be denied, if but a part is untrue, a sum of good and bad,
 on the other hand, may be of such a nature as nevertheless as a whole
 to be worthy of love. It may be also so constituted that good and bad
 remain in equilibrium.

 2. In the lecture (p. 24), and in the corresponding note 37 (p. 87),
 it is said that our preference qualified as right in the case where,
 for instance, to one good another is added, is drawn, not from our
 knowledge of the preferability of the sum as opposed to the parts,
 but that analytic judgments here yield the means of our advance in
 knowledge, and that the corresponding preferences are therefore
 qualified as right, since the knowledge (given analytically) is here
 the criterion. Here it is overlooked that without the experience of
 acts of preferring we neither have nor could have the conception,
 and therefore also our notion of preferability. And so it is also
 true that it is by no means evident from analysis that one good plus
 another is preferable to each of these goods taken singly. Here also a
 complete analogy to the sphere of the true is wanting.

 One truth added to another does not yield something more true. On
 the other hand, one good plus another good yields a better. But that
 this is so can only be understood by means of a special experience
 belonging peculiarly to this sphere, i.e. by means of the experience
 of acts of preferring which are qualified as right.

As to the other branches of philosophy, the work of Brentano already
published forms but a portion--often but the smaller portion--of
investigations, which, in the manner above described, have become known
to a larger or smaller circle of disciples. This explains the striking
fact that, in proportion to the extent of what has been published, an
unusually large number of investigators and scholars appear in a greater
or lesser degree to have been influenced by Brentano. (Überweg-Heinze,
in the eighth edition of the _Grundriss der Geschichte der Philosophie_,
reckons, as belonging to his school, six names of men at present
occupying important positions as teachers of philosophy.)

One section of Brentano’s doctrine of sense-perception forms the
substance of a lecture, _Zur Lehre von der Empfindung_, delivered at the
Third International Psychological Congress held in Munich (1896), and
published in the report of its proceedings (1897). A fragment of the
above system of ethical inquiry, _Über das Schlechte als Gegenstand
dichterischer Darstellung_ (Leipzig, 1892), treats of the worth and
preferability of the ideas employed by the artist.

With regard to psycho-genetic problems, apart from the question as to
the meaning and validity of Fechner’s psycho-physical law, a question
discussed in the first volume of his _Psychology_ and elsewhere, and
that of the spirituality and immortality of the soul, which formed
repeatedly the substance of lectures at Vienna University, Brentano has
especially occupied himself with the laws of the association of ideas.
One result of this study is his lecture, _Das Genie_, published in 1892,
which seeks to explain the artistic productions of men of genius--often
regarded as something quite unique and inexplicable--as a development of
psychical events which universally control our imaginative life.

Of Brentano’s researches in _metaphysics_ and in the _theory of
knowledge_ it must also be said that hitherto they remain still
unpublished, though they are familiar to a greater or smaller circle of
disciples. In this latter sphere are to be mentioned particularly his
inquiries respecting the nature of our insight into the law of
causality, the logical justification of induction, the _a priori_ nature
of mathematics, and the nature of analytic judgments. In ontological
questions also psychognosie has proved fruitful to the investigator in
leading him to an understanding and to an analysis based upon
experience, of the most important metaphysical notions, as, for
instance, causality, substance, necessity, impossibility, etc., notions
which some, despairing of the task rightly insisted upon by Hume, of
showing their origin to be based upon perception and experience, have
sought to explain straight away as _a priori_ categories.

For the rest, Brentano, in regard to metaphysics, is a decided theist.
He is an adherent of the theory of evolution, while denying that
accidental variations and natural selection in the struggle for
existence render explicable the phenomena of evolution and the
teleological character of the organism, basing his objections, among
other things, upon the fact that this attempt at a solution not only
leaves unexplained the first beginnings of an organism, but also takes
too little account of the fact that with the increasing perfection and
complication of the organism it becomes more and more improbable that an
accidental variation will lead to an improvement upon that which already
exists. And yet if there is to be progress, the organisms which, in the
struggle for existence, survive must not only be more perfect than those
which perish, but also more perfect than the organisms through which
they themselves are descended.

Brentano’s views on the historical development of philosophical inquiry
and the causes determining that development, the present state of
philosophy and its views regarding the future, he has set forth in
various publications: _Die Geschichte der Philosophie im Mittelalter_
(Möhler’s _Kirchengeschichte_, vol. ii. 1868); _Über die Gründe der
Entmutigung auf philosophischem Gebiete_ (Vienna, 1874), delivered as an
inaugural address on entering upon his work at Vienna University; _Was
für ein Philosoph manchmal Epoche macht_ (Vienna, 1876); _Über die
Zukunft der Philosophie_ (Vienna, 1893); and _Die vier Phasen der
Philosophie und ihr augenblicklicher Stand_ (Stuttgart, 1895).

In the last work a concise survey is made of the entire course of the
History of Philosophy, and it is there shown how in the three periods,
rightly regarded as distinct (Greek Philosophy, the Philosophy of the
Middle Ages, and Modern Philosophy), there is each time an analogous
change, a rising or blossoming period, and three periods of decadence,
of which those which succeed are always the psychologically necessary
result of the preceding. That in so doing Brentano has characterized the
latest phase of German philosophy, the so-called idealistic direction
from Kant to Hegel as the third or mystic period of decadence (howbeit
with all due recognition of the talents of these writers) has naturally
aroused violent opposition, though it has not found any real refutation.

It has been already said that Brentano’s earliest efforts were directed
to historical inquiries and especially to a presentation of the
Aristotelian psychology and to important sections of his Metaphysics.
The results of these researches, diverging as they did in many respects
from the traditional view, did not fail to awaken the attention of other
investigators. Their attitude, however (with a few exceptions like
Trendelenburg, and in part also Grote), was, on the whole, hostile and
polemic. This was especially so in the case of E. Zeller, in the later
edition of his _Greek Philosophy_, and in view of the reputation which
this work enjoys, Brentano thought it necessary to offer, as against
Zeller’s attacks, at least with regard to one point, an apology for his
own view, a point where the threads of metaphysics and psychology become
most intimately related, and where at the same time, the contrast
between the opposing views of these two writers in the psychological and
metaphysical spheres alike culminate. And so there appeared in the
_Report of the Proceedings of the Imperial Academy of Sciences in
Vienna_ (1882) Brentano’s article: “Über den Creatianismus des
Aristoteles, in regard to which E. Zeller in the same year, in the
_Report of the Proceedings of the Royal Prussian Academy of Sciences in
Berlin_, (vol. 49), published a detailed reply under the title: “Über
die Lehre des Aristoteles von der Ewigkeit des Geistes.” The charge
which is there made by Zeller against Brentano of interpreting Aristotle
without sufficient confirmation and with over-confidence, Brentano has
sufficiently repelled in his _Offener Brief an Herrn Prof. Dr. E.
Zeller_ (Leipzig, 1883), and the proofs which are here offered of the
way in which Zeller, on his part, bases his own attempts at explanation
and his charges against Brentano show distinctly that, if here one of
the two opponents is really open to the charge of over-confidence, it is
at any rate not Brentano.

       *       *       *       *       *


Dante and Giovanni del Vergilio

By PHILIP H. WICKSTEED, M.A., and
EDMUND G. GARDNER, M.A.

Demy 8vo.      12_s._



                         The Mind of Tennyson

             HIS THOUGHTS ON GOD, FREEDOM, AND IMMORTALITY

                      By E. HERSHEY SNEATH, PH.D.

              Professor of Philosophy in Yale University.

            Crown 8vo.      5_s._ net.      Third Edition.

“Admirably sums up for us Tennyson’s philosophic ideas and the creed he
had ultimately arrived at. Since Mr. Stopford Brooke’s comprehensive
survey of Tennyson, nothing so excellent has been written on the poet’s
ideas.”--_Spectator._


                        The Teachings of Dante

                       By CHARLES ALLEN DINSMORE

          With Frontispiece.      Crown 8vo.      5_s._ net.

“The author of this delightful volume takes his reader, as it were,
behind the scenes and shows him of the inner life and thought of the
master.... Mr. Dinsmore has a grip of the religious teaching of Dante
which few men have attained, and the whole volume is wondrously
suggestive of the deep truths that underlie the marvellous imagery of
the poet.”--_The Rock._


                       The Chronicle of Villani

      Translated by ROSE E. SELFE. Edited by Rev. P. H. WICKSTEED

                         Crown 8vo.      6_s._

“Perhaps no one book is so important to the student of Dante as the
chronicle of his contemporary Villani.”--_Athenæum._


                          Tiberius the Tyrant

          By J. C. TARVER, Author of “Gustave Flaubert,” etc.

           With a Portrait.      Demy 8vo.      15_s._ net.

“Mr. Tarver has drawn a lifelike portrait, amid a group of others
vigorous, real, and living; especially the women.”--_Cambridge Review._

“Not for a long time has a historical volume so deeply interested me as
Mr. Tarver’s ‘Tiberius the Tyrant,’ which has the dramatic movement of a
romance at the same time that it lights up and gives life to a story
worth telling.... His style has the transcendent virtue of clearness,
and he happily selects the modern analogies by which he illustrates the
conditions and the problems of the age of which he treats. The
comparison of ancient with modern conditions gives the work a second
interest as a criticism of contemporary ideas and movements.... The
author is to be congratulated on a volume which will attract many
readers to a subject that is just now exceptionally worthy of
attention.”--Mr. SPENSER WILKINSON in the _Morning Post_.

       *       *       *       *       *

                   Maximilian I., Holy Roman Emperor

             (Stanhope Prize Essay.) By R. W. SETON WATSON

                     Illustrated.      5_s._ net.

“A sound and well-considered piece of historical criticism.”--_Daily
News._

“A notable essay.”--_Morning Post._



       By G. S. STREET, Author of “The Trials of the Bantocks,”
        “The Autobiography of a Boy,” “A Book of Stories,” etc.

                Crown 8vo.      Cloth Gilt.      6_s._

A volume of essays divided under three headings: (1) London; (2) Books
and Men; (3) Various.


                  Studies in the Lives of the Saints

            By EDWARD HUTTON, Author of “Frederic Uvedale.”

                   Fcap. 8vo.      3_s._ 6_d._ net.


                           Ephemera Critica

                 PLAIN TRUTHS ABOUT CURRENT LITERATURE

                        By JOHN CHURTON COLLINS

           Second Edition.      Crown 8vo.      7_s._ 6_d._

“A book of uncommon interest and importance. A collection of essays
united in a common aim, and inspired by a genuine enthusiasm for
literature; it has something to say and says it without fear or
favour.”--_Literature._


                          Chalmers on Charity

A Selection of Passages and Scenes to illustrate the Social Teaching and
                Practical Work of THOMAS CHALMERS, D.D.

               Arranged and Edited by N. MASTERMAN, M.A.

   Eighteen years Member of the London Charity Organization Society,
          and some time Guardian in the Parish of Kensington.

     414 pp.      Price 7_s._ 6_d._ net.      With a Frontispiece.

“We should advise such of our readers as care to know the arguments
against public poor relief to look at a book which has just been
published by Mr. N. Masterman.... He has succeeded in making the
unpopular side of a dry subject keenly interesting.”--_Spectator._


                           Human Immortality

   By WILLIAM JAMES, Professor of Philosophy at Harvard University.

              Fourth Edition.      16mo.      2_s._ 6_d._

“Professor James is well known as one of the most suggestive and
original writers, and as certainly the most brilliant psychologist
living. Whatever, therefore, he has to say on this subject is worth
listening to; for he thinks freely, and he knows all that the scientist
knows, and more too.”--_Spectator._

       *       *       *       *       *

                         A CATALOGUE OF BOOKS

                             PUBLISHED BY

                     Archibald Constable & Co Ltd

                          2 WHITEHALL GARDENS

                              WESTMINSTER


                                     PAGE
  HISTORY, BIOGRAPHY, AND CRITICISM     3
  TRAVEL                               14
  SPORT                                17
  NAVAL AND MILITARY                   18
  FINE ART                             20
  EDUCATIONAL AND TECHNICAL            22
  RELIGIOUS                            31
  FICTION                              33
  POETRY                               42
  BOOKS FOR THE YOUNG                  47
  INDEX                                49
  BOOKS ARRANGED IN ORDER OF PRICES    53

       *       *       *       *       *

                             THE ANCESTOR

                   A Quarterly Review of County and
                       Family History, Heraldry
                            and Antiquities

                    EDITED BY OSWALD BARRON, F.S.A.

                  _Large Super Royal, in paper boards
                     with numerous Illustrations_

                          _5s. net Quarterly_

“Thoroughly original in scope and style, the publishers are to be
congratulated on its effective appearance. _The Ancestor_ intends to
apply the spirit of a new and conscientious criticism to the revived
interest in genealogy and family history.”--THE ATHENÆUM.

“Such a new departure is certainly designed to fill a want which has
long been felt, and the names of its contributors guarantee the accuracy
and importance of its contents.”--THE TIMES.

“Printed in old-faced type, and neatly bound in studious-looking boards,
the new periodical makes a very handsome appearance. The pages of _The
Ancestor_ are brightened by portraits, illustrations of old armorial
glass, and so on. It is edited carefully and with knowledge, and should
command popularity among the large number of readers to whom it
appeals.”--THE STANDARD.

“Clearly printed on good paper, and freely and excellently illustrated.
The literary contents of the number are of solid and varied interest.
Altogether _The Ancestor_ is quite admirable in its aims, which it seems
determined to achieve in scholarly and attractive fashion.”--THE GLOBE.

“The promise of a really authoritative periodical of English genealogy
and family history will be received with general satisfaction. This is
given us in the announcement of _The Ancestor_, a quarterly to be edited
by Mr. Oswald Barron and published by Archibald Constable & Co., London.
Mr. Barron’s unusual knowledge in the field to be covered is well known
to many who are interested in it. The list of contributors, including
among others Sir George Sitwell, Sir H. Maxwell-Lyte, Mr. J. Horace
Round, and Mr. St. John Hope, besides the editor, certainly supports the
promise of accuracy and authority.”--THE NATION, NEW YORK.


       *       *       *       *       *

                        History, Biography, and
                              Criticism.


     =ANITCHKOW, MICHAEL.= =War and Labour.= Demy 8vo. 18s.

     =ANON.= =Regeneration.= A Reply to Max Nordau. Demy 8vo. 14s.

     =ARNOLD, T. W., B.A.= =The Preaching of Islam.= A Work on the Spread of
     the Mohammedan Religion by Missionary Methods. Demy 8vo. 12s.

     =BAIN, R. NISBET.= =The Daughter of Peter the Great (The Empress
     Elisabeth).= A History of Russian Diplomacy and of the Russian
     Court, 1741-1762. With Photogravure Frontispiece and several
     Portraits. Demy 8vo. 15s.

     =---- = =Peter III. Emperor of Russia. The Story of a Crisis and a
     Crime.= Illustrated with Photogravure and Collotype reproductions.
     Demy 8vo. 10s. 6d. net.

     =BEATTY, WILLIAM, M.D.= (Surgeon of H.M.S. _Victory_). =An Authentic
     Narrative of the Death of Nelson.= With two Illustrations. Crown
     8vo. 2s. 6d. net. Second Edition.

     =BERTRAM, JAMES.= =Some Memories of Books, Authors and Events.=
     Recollections of Sir Walter Scott, De Quincey, John Gibson
     Lockhart, etc. With Photogravure Frontispiece. Demy 8vo. 7s. 6d.

     =BIRRELL, AUGUSTINE, Q.C.= See =Boswell.=

     =BOSWELL.= =Boswell’s Life of Johnson.= Edited by Augustine Birrell,
     Q.C. With Frontispiece in Photogravure to each volume by Alexander
     Ansted. 6 vols. Fcap. 8vo. Cloth gilt, designed by Gleeson White,
     or paper label uncut. 12s. net the set. Also half leather. 18s. net
     the set. Limited Edition. Illustrated with 100 Portraits selected
     by Ernest Radford. 6 Volumes. Crown 8vo. Bound in red buckram,
     paper label, gilt top. Sold only in sets. Price 36s. net.

     =---- = =Boswell’s Account of Dr. Johnson’s Tour to the Hebrides.= With
     Photogravure Frontispieces. Uniform with ‘Boswell’s Johnson.’ Cloth
     gilt or paper label. 4s. net the two vols. Also in half leather.
     6s. net the two vols.

     =BRADLEY, A. G.= =The Fight with France for North America.= New
     Illustrated Edition. Extra Crown 8vo. 6s.

     =BRIGHT, CHARLES, F.R.S.E.= =Science and Engineering, 1837-1897.= Large
     Crown 8vo. Paper wrapper. 1s.

     =BRIGHT, E. B.=, and =CHARLES, F.R.S.E.= =The Life of Sir Charles
     Tilston Bright.= With many Illustrations, Portraits, and Maps. 2
     vols. Demy 8vo. £3 3s. net.

     =BROWN’S LETTERS.= Edited by Sidney T. Irwin. See page 8.

     =BURROUGHS, JOHN.= =Whitman: A Study.= Crown 8vo. Cloth gilt. 6s. net.

     =CAMPBELL, LORD ARCHIBALD.= =Highland Dress, Arms, and Ornament.=
     Illustrated. Demy 8vo. 25s. net.

     ‘=CENTURION.=’ =Army Administration.= Crown 8vo. Paper. 1s.

     =CHAILLEY-BERT, J.= =The Colonisation of Indo-China.= With Maps. Crown
     8vo. 7s. 6d.

     =CHAMBERLAIN, RT. HON. JOSEPH, M.P., D.C.L., LL.D.= =Patriotism.= Bound
     in buckram. Demy 8vo. 2s.

     =COLLINS, J. CHURTON.= =Ephemera Critica=: Plain Truths about Current
     Literature. Crown 8vo. Second Edition. 7s. 6d.

     =COURTNEY, W. L.= =The Idea of Tragedy.= With a Prefatory Note by A. W.
     PINERO. Fcap. 8vo. 3s. 6d. net.

     =CURRIE, MAJOR-GENERAL FENDALL.= =Below the Surface.= Sketches of Civil
     and Native Life in India. Crown 8vo. 6s.

     =CURZON, RT. HON. GEORGE N.= (Lord Curzon of Kedleston, Viceroy of
     India). =Problems of the Far East--China, Japan, Korea.= With
     numerous Illustrations and Maps. Extra Crown 8vo. 7s. 6d.

     =DALE, T. F., M.A.= (Stoneclink). =The History of the Belvoir Hunt
     from the Year 1720.= See page 17.

     =---- = =The Eighth Duke of Beaufort and the Badminton Hunt.= See page
     17.

     =DAVIDSON, THOMAS.= =A History of Education.= Crown 8vo. 5s. net.

     =DE BURY, MLLE. BLAZE.= =French Literature of To-day.= Crown 8vo. 6s.

     =DEIGHTON, KENNETH.= =Conjectural Readings in the Old Dramatists.=
     Crown 8vo. 3s. 6d. net.

     =DINSMORE, CHARLES A.= =The Teachings of Dante.= With illustrations.
     Crown 8vo. 5s. net.

     =DUFF, C. MABEL.= =The Chronology of India.= From the Earliest Times to
     the Beginning of the Sixteenth Century. Demy 8vo. 15s. net.

     =DUTT, ROMESH CHUNDER, C.I.E.= =The Literature of Bengal.= Crown 8vo.
     6s.

     =FOX, ARTHUR W., M.A.= =A Book of Bachelors.= Essays on Ten Celebrated
     Bachelors. Fully Illustrated. Demy 8vo. 16s.

     =GAIRDNER, JAMES.= =The Paston Letters, 1422-1509.= Crown 8vo. 4 vols.
     Vol. I., Henry VI., 1422-1461. Vol. II., Edward IV., 1461-1471.
     Vol. III., 1471-1509. Vol. IV. Introductory and Supplementary.
     Edited by JAMES GAIRDNER, of the Public Record Office. Photogravure
     Frontispiece to each vol. 21s. net. Vol. IV. sold separately, 10s.
     6d. net.

     =GODKIN, E. L.= =Problems of Modern Democracy.= Large Crown 8vo. 7s.
     6d.

     =---- = =Reflections and Comments.= 1865-1895. Large Crown 8vo. 7s.
     6d.

     =GODKIN, E. L.= =Unforeseen Tendencies of Democracy.= Large Crown 8vo.
     6s. net.

     =GOMME, G. LAURENCE, F.S.A.= (Statistical Officer to the London
     County Council). =The Principles of Local Government.= Demy 8vo. 12s.

     =GRIBBLE, FRANCIS.= =Lake Geneva and its Literary Landmarks.=
     Illustrated with Photogravure and Collotype reproductions. Demy
     8vo. 18s.

     =HAILEYBURY COLLEGE, MEMORIALS OF OLD.= By BRAND SAPTE, Sir MONIER
     MONIER-WILLIAMS, FREDERICK CHARLES DANVERS, PERCY WIGRAM, Sir
     STEUART COLVIN BAYLEY, and others. With numerous Illustrations and
     Plans. Fcap. 4to. 21s. net.

     =HAKE, A. EGMONT, and WESSLAU, O. E.= =The Coming Individualism.= Demy
     8vo. 14s.

     =HANNA, COL. H. B.= =The Second Afghan War.= Demy 8vo. Vol. I. now
     ready, 10s. net.

  =Backwards or Forwards?=       }
  =Can Russia Invade India?=     } See page 18.
  =India’s Scientific Frontier.= }

     =HAYDEN, ELEANOR G.= =Travels Round our Village.= A Berkshire Book.
     (Dedicated by permission to Lady Wantage.) With numerous
     illustrations by L. LESLIE BROOKE. Demy 8vo. 7s. 6d. net.

     =HEWITT, J. F.= =The Ruling Races of Prehistoric Times in India,
     South-Western Asia, and Southern Europe.= With Diagrams and Maps.
     Demy 8vo. Vol. I., 18s.; Vol. II., 12s.

     =HOLDEN, EDWARD S.= =The Mogul Emperors of Hindustan, A.D. 1398-1707.=
     With a chapter by Sir W. W. HUNTER. With Illustrations. Crown 8vo.
     10s. 6d.

     =HOUFE, C. A.= =The Question of the Houses.= Small 16mo. 2s. 6d.

     =IRWIN, SIDNEY T.= =Letters of T. E. Brown=, Author of ‘Betsy Lee’ and
     ‘Foc’s’le Yarns.’ 2 vols. Crown 8vo. 12s.

     =JAMES, WILLIAM= (Professor of Philosophy at Harvard University).
     =Human Immortality.= Two Supposed Objections to the Doctrine. 16mo.
     2s. 6d.

     =KREHBIEL, HENRY EDWARD=, Author of ‘How to Listen to Music.’ =Music
     and Manners in the Classical Period.= Crown 8vo. 6s.

     =LANE-POOLE, STANLEY.= =The Mohammedan Dynasties.= Containing
     Chronological Tables of all the Dynasties of the Mohammedan Empire
     from the Foundation of the Caliphate to the Present Day. Crown 8vo.
     12s. net.

     =LEACH, A. F., M.A., F.S.A.= =English Schools at the
     Reformation--1546-48.= Demy 8vo. 12s. net.

     =LEGG, L. G. WICKHAM, and HOPE, W. H. ST. JOHN.= =Inventories of
     Christchurch, Canterbury.= Demy 8vo. 21s. net.

     =McCRINDLE, J. W.= =Ancient India as described in Classical
     Literature.= Crown 8vo. 7s. 6d. net.

     =MACGEORGE, G. W.= =Ways and Works in India.= Being an Account of the
     Public Works in that Country from the Earliest Times to the Present
     Day. Fully Illustrated and Five Maps. Demy 8vo. 16s.

     =McNAIR, MAJOR J. F. A.= =Prisoners their own Warders.= A Record of the
     Convict Prison at Singapore. With many Illustrations and Maps. Demy
     8vo. 10s. 6d.

     =MANCHESTER STAGE, 1880-1900.= Criticisms reprinted from _The
     Manchester Guardian_. Fcap. 8vo. 3s. 6d. net.

     =MASTERMAN, N., M.A.= =Chalmers on Charity.= A Selection of Passages
     and Scenes to Illustrate the Social Teaching and Practical Work of
     Thomas Chalmers, D.D. Arranged and Edited by N. MASTERMAN, M.A.
     Extra Crown 8vo. 7s. 6d. net.

     =MEREDITH.= =Birthday Book.= Compiled and arranged by D. M. Cloth gilt.
     4s. 6d.

     =METCALFE, CHARLES THEOPHILUS, C.S.I.= =Two Native Narratives of the
     Mutiny in Delhi.= Translated from the Originals by the late C. T.
     METCALFE, C.S.I. With Map and Two Illustrations. 12s.

     =MITCHELL, PROF. H. G.= =The World before Abraham=, according to
     Genesis i.-xi. Crown 8vo. 5s. net.

     =MORISON, M.= =Time Table of Modern History, A.D. 400-1870.= Oblong
     Folio. Cloth. 12s. 6d. net.

     CONTENTS.--Parallel Tables, Genealogical Tables.--Ruling
     Monarchs.--General Chart of Ancient and Modern
     History.--Index.--Maps showing Europe at various Periods.

     =MORISON, THEODORE, M.A.= =Imperial Rule in India.= Crown 8vo. 3s. 6d.

     =MÜNSTERBERG, PROFESSOR HUGO.= =Psychology and Life.= Demy 8vo. 6s.
     net.

     =NATIONAL WORTHIES.= See page 21.

     =NEWBERRY, PERCY E.= =The Life of Rekhmara=, Vézir of Upper Egypt under
     Thothmes III. and Amenhetep II. (_circa_ B.C. 1471-1448). With 22
     Plates. 21s. net. Only 250 printed.

     =---- = =The Gardens of the Ancient World.= Fully Illustrated. Demy
     8vo. [In preparation.]

     =NISBET, JOHN.= =Burma Under British Rule.= 2 Volumes. Demy 8vo, with
     Frontispiece to each volume. Maps and Plans. Price 32s. net.

     =OPPERT, GUSTAV, Ph.D.= (Professor of Sanscrit in the University of
     Madras). =The Original Inhabitants of India.= Demy 8vo. 20s.

     =PALMER, WALTER, M.P.= =Poultry Management on a Farm.= An account of
     three years’ work with practical results and balance sheets.
     Illustrated. Demy 8vo. 1s.

     =POPOWSKI, JOSEPH.= Translated by ARTHUR BARING BRABANT, and edited
     by CHAS. E. D. BLACK. =The Rival Powers in Central Asia.= With a
     large Map of the Pamir Region. Demy 8vo. 12s. 6d.

     =RAIT, ROBERT S.= =Five Stuart Princesses.= With Photogravure and
     full-page Portraits. Demy 8vo. 12s. 6d. net.

     =---- = =Lusus Regius.= A Volume of hitherto unpublished autograph
     works by King James I. Edited by ROBERT S. RAIT, Fellow of New
     College, Oxford. Illustrated by Photogravure and Collotype
     reproductions. Only 275 copies of this work have been printed, 250
     numbered copies being for sale. Price 42s. net.

     =RICE, LOUIS.= =The Mysore Gazetteer.= 2 vols. Demy 8vo. 30s. net.

     =ROOSEVELT, THEODORE.= =Oliver Cromwell.= Fully Illustrated. Demy 8vo.
     10s. 6d. net.

     =ROUND, J. HORACE, M.A.= =The Commune of London, and other Studies.=
     With a Prefatory Letter by Sir WALTER BESANT. Demy 8vo. 12s. 6d.
     net.

     =RYLEY, G. BUCHANAN, and J. M. M’CANDLISH.= =Scotland’s Free Church.=
     With an Etched Portrait and a Photogravure and numerous other
     Illustrations. Fcap. 4to. 10s. 6d.

     =SCHWEITZER, GEORG.= =Emin Pasha: His Life and Work.= With an
     Introduction by R. W. FELKIN, M.D. With Portrait, Facsimiles, and
     Map. 2 vols. Demy 8vo. 32s.

     =SCOTT, EVA= (late Scholar of Somerville College, Oxford). =Rupert,
     Prince Palatine.= With Photogravure Frontispiece. Large Crown 8vo.
     6s. Second Edition.

     =SETON-WATSON, R. W.= =Maximilian.= Stanhope Essay. Illustrated. Crown
     8vo. 5s. net.

     =SIBORNE, CAPTAIN WILLIAM.= =The Waterloo Campaign, 1815.= With 13
     Portraits of Generals, and 15 Maps and Plans. Crown 8vo. 832 pages.
     New Edition. 6s.

     =SICHEL, EDITH.= =The Household of the Lafayettes.= With Photogravure
     Frontispiece. Large Crown 8vo. 6s. Second Edition.

     =SICHEL, EDITH.= =Women and Men of the French Renaissance.=
     Illustrated. Demy 8vo. Price 16s. net.

     =SMITH, EDWARD.= =England and America.= A Short Examination of their
     International Intercourse. 1783-1872. Demy 8vo. 14s.

     =SMYTHE, A. J.= =The Life of William Terriss, Actor.= Illustrated. Demy
     8vo. 12s. 6d.

     =SNEATH, E. HERSHEY= (Ph.D., Professor of Philosophy in Yale
     University). =The Mind of Tennyson.= His Thoughts on God, Freedom,
     and Immortality. Crown 8vo. 5s. net.

     =SPALDING, THOMAS ALFRED.= =The Life and Times of Richard Badiley,
     Vice-Admiral of the Fleet.= Demy 8vo. 15s.

     =STEIN, M. A.= =Kalhana’s Rajatarangini.= A Chronicle of the Kings of
     Kashmir, with 3 Maps. Translated, with an Introduction, Commentary
     and Appendices. 2 Volumes. £3 3s. net.

     =STREET, G. S.= =A Book of Essays.= Crown 8vo. 6s.

     =STUART, JOHN.= =Pictures of War.= Illustrated with Maps and Plans.
     Crown 8vo. 7s. 6d.

     =THORNTON, SURGEON-GENERAL, C.B.= =Memories of Seven Campaigns.= With
     numerous Illustrations by George and Kate Thornton. Large Demy 8vo.
     17s. 6d. net.

     =TOWNSEND, MEREDITH.= =Asia and Europe.= Being Studies presenting the
     conclusions formed by the Author in a long life devoted to the
     subject of the relations between Asia and Europe. Demy 8vo. 10s.
     6d. net.

     =TRAILL, H. D.= =England, Egypt, and the Sudan.= With Maps. Demy 8vo.
     12s.

     =VALLERY-RADOT, RENÈ.= =The Life of Pasteur.= Translated from the
     French by Mrs. R. L. DEVONSHIRE. 2 Volumes. Demy 8vo. With
     Frontispiece Portrait of Pasteur. Price 32s.

     =VIBART, COLONEL HENRY M.= =Addiscombe: Its Heroes and Men of Note.=
     With a Preface by LORD ROBERTS of Kandahar. Fully Illustrated.
     Fcap. 4to. 21s. net.

     =WHITEWAY, R. S.= (Bengal Civil Service, retired). =The Rise of
     Portuguese Power in India, 1497-1550.= Demy 8vo. 15s. net.

     =WICKSTEED, REV. P. H.= =The Chronicle of Villani.= Translated by ROSE
     E. SELFE and edited by the Rev. P. H. WICKSTEED. Crown 8vo. 6s.

     =WICKSTEED, PHILIP H., M.A., and GARDNER, EDMUND G., M.A.= =Dante and
     Giovanni del Virgilio.= Including a Critical Edition of the text of
     Dante’s ‘Eclogae Latinae,’ and of the Poetic Remains of Giovanni
     del Virgilio. Demy 8vo. Price 12s.

     =WILKINSON, SPENSER.= =War and Policy.= Demy 8vo. 15s.

     =---- = =The Nation’s Awakening. Essays Towards a British Policy.=
     Crown 8vo. 5s.

     =WINSLOW, ANNA GREEN.= =Diary of a Boston School Girl.= Edited by ALICE
     MORSE EARLE. With 7 Illustrations. Crown 8vo. 6s.

     =WOOD, WALTER.= =With the Flag at Sea.= Illustrated with numerous
     full-page plates by H. C. SEPPINGS WRIGHT. Cloth gilt. Extra Crown
     8vo. Price 6s.

       *       *       *       *       *

Travel.


     =BATTYE, AUBYN TREVOR-, F.L.S., F.Z.S.= =Author of ‘Icebound on
     Kolguev.’=

     =A Northern Highway of the Czar.= Fully Illustrated. Crown 8vo. 6s.

     =CONSTABLE’S Hand Atlas of India.= A new series of Sixty Maps and
     Plans prepared from Ordnance and other Surveys under the direction
     of J. G. BARTHOLOMEW, F.R.G.S., F.R.S.E., etc. Crown 8vo. Strongly
     bound in Half Morocco. Price 14s.

     This Atlas will be found of great use not only to tourists and
     travellers, but also to readers of Indian history; it contains
     twenty-two plans of the principal towns of our Indian Empire, based
     on the most recent surveys and officially revised to date in India.

=Constable’s Hand Gazetteer of India.= Compiled under the direction of J.
G. BARTHOLOMEW, F.R.G.S., and Edited with Additions by JAS. BURGESS,
C.I.E., LL.D., etc. Crown 8vo. Half Morocco. Price 10s. 6d.

     The Hand Gazetteer of India is based on the Index to Constable’s
     Hand Atlas of India, which contains nearly 12,000 place-names. To
     these have been added very largely from various sources, bringing
     the number of entries to close upon 20,000. The populations of
     districts, towns, and villages, and the position of each place are
     clearly indicated, thus forming within a small compass a general
     reference book to the topography of India, and a companion volume
     to the Hand Atlas of India.

=CONWAY, SIR WILLIAM MARTIN.= =The Alps from End to End.= With over 50 full
page Illustrations by A. D. M’CORMICK. Large Crown 8vo. 6s. New Edition.

=DURAND, LAD.= =An Autumn Tour in Western Persia.= Demy 8vo. Illustrated.

=ELLIOTT, ROBERT H.= =Gold, Sport, and Coffee Planting in Mysore.= Being the
Thirty-eight Years’ Experience of a Mysore Planter. Crown 8vo. 7s. 6d.

=ENGELHARDT, ALEXANDER PLATONOVICH=, Governor of the Province of
Archangel. =A Russian Province of the North (Archangel).= Translated from
the Russian by HENRY COOKE. With 90 Illustrations and 3 Maps. Royal 8vo.
18s.

=FILIPPI, FILIPPO De.= =The Ascent of Mount St. Elias (Alaska).= By H.R.H.
Prince LUIGI AMEDEO DI SAVOIA, Duke of the Abruzzi. Narrated by FILIPPO
DE FILIPPI. Illustrated by VITTORIA SELLA, and Translated by SIGNORA
LINDA VILLARI. 4to. 31s. 6d. net. Edition de Luxe, £3 3s. net.

=HODGSON, RANDOLPH LLEWELLYN.= =On Plain and Peak. Sport in Bohemia and
Tyrol.= Illustrated by H.S.H. PRINCESS MARY OF THURN AND TAXIS, and from
Photographs. Demy 8vo. 7s. 6d.

=LACHAMBRE, HENRI, and MACHURON, ALEXIS.= =Andrée and His Balloon.= With a
Coloured Frontispiece and 40 Full-page Plates after Photographs taken by
the Authors during the time of preparation and at the time of start.
Crown 8vo. 6s.

=MEAKIN, ANNETTE M. B.= =A Ribbon of Iron.= Fully Illustrated. Crown 8vo.
Price 6s.

     This is an account of a journey over the Great Siberian Railway and
     down to the lower part of the Amur River to Blagovestchensk and
     thence to Vladivostok. The author relates her adventures in a novel
     field (which just at present has a special interest) in plain and
     natural language. The account of the outbreak of hostilities at
     Blagovestchensk will be found particularly interesting.

=NANSEN, FRIDTJOF.= =Farthest North.= A New Edition. With 20 full-page
Illustrations and 2 Maps. Crown 8vo. 6s.

=OOKHTOMSKY, PRINCE E.= =Travels in the East of His Imperial Majesty Czar
Nicholas II of Russia: when Cesarewitch.= Written by order of His
Imperial Majesty and translated by ROBERT GOODLET. In 2 vols., with
about 500 Illustrations engraved on wood and numerous Heliogravure
Plates. Edited by SIR GEORGE BIRDWOOD, M.D., K.C.I.E. Imperial 4to. £5
5s. net.

     Also a =Hand-made Paper Edition.= Limited to 30 copies for England
     and America. 25 guineas net.

     =PRICHARD, HESKETH.= =Where Black Rules White.= Across and about the
     Black Republic of Hayti. Fully Illustrated. Demy 8vo. 12s.

     =ROBERTS, MORLEY.= =The Western Avernus.= A new edition, with
     Illustrations by A. D. M’CORMICK, and from Photographs. Crown 8vo.
     7s. 6d. net.

     =SANGERMANO, FATHER.= =Burma a Hundred Years Ago.= Edited with Notes
     and Introduction by the HON. MR. JUSTICE JARDINE. With a Map. Demy
     8vo. 10s. 6d.

     =STADLING, J.= =Through Siberia.= Edited by Dr. F. H. H. GUILLEMARD.
     Fully Illustrated. Demy 8vo. 15s.

     =WADDELL, Surg.-Maj. L. A.= =Among the Himalayas.= With numerous
     Illustrations by A. D. M’CORMICK, the Author, and from Photographs.
     Large Crown 8vo. 6s. Second Edition.

     =YOUNG, ERNEST= (Late of the Education Department, Siam). =The Kingdom
     of the Yellow Robe.= Being Sketches of the Domestic and Religious
     Rites and Ceremonies of the Siamese. With numerous Illustrations by
     E. A. NORBURY, R.C.A., and from Photographs. Large Crown 8vo. 6s.
     Second Edition.



Sport.


     =DALE, T. F.= (=Stoneclink.=) =History of the Belvoir Hunt.= With Map and
     many Illustrations. Demy 8vo. 21s. net.

     =---- = =The Eighth Duke of Beaufort and the Badminton Hunt.=
     Illustrated. Demy 8vo. Price 21s.

     =ELLIOTT, ROBERT H.= =Gold, Sport, and Coffee Planting in Mysore.=
     Being the Thirty Years’ Experience of a Mysore Planter. Crown 8vo.
     7s. 6d.

     =HODGSON, RANDOLPH LLEWELLYN.= =On Plain and Peak. Sport in Bohemia
     and Tyrol.= Illustrated by H.S.H. PRINCESS MARY OF THURN AND TAXIS,
     and from Photographs. Demy 8vo. 7s. 6d.

     =KENNEDY, ADMIRAL.= =Sport in the Navy.=

     =WALKER, CHARLES.= =Shooting on a Small Income.= Illustrated. Crown
     8vo. 5s.

     =---- = =Amateur Fish Culture.= Cr. 8vo. 2s. 6d. net.

       *       *       *       *       *

Naval and Military.


     =ANITCHKOW, MICHAEL.= =War and Labour.= Demy 8vo. 18s.

     ‘=CENTURION.=’ =Army Administration.= Crown 8vo. Paper, 1s.

     =HANNA, COL. H. B.= =Can Russia Invade India?= (Indian Problems No. 1.)
     Crown 8vo. 2s. 6d.

     =---- = =India’s Scientific Frontier. Where is it? What is it?= (Indian
     Problems No. 2.) Crown 8vo. 2s. 6d.

     =---- = =Backwards or Forwards?= (Indian Problems No. 3.) Crown 8vo.
     2s. 6d.

     =---- = =The Second Afghan War. 1878-80.= Vol. I. Demy 8vo. 10s. net.

     =MAYO, JOHN HORSLEY.= =Medals and Decorations of the British Army and
     Navy.= With numerous Coloured Plates and other Illustrations. 2
     vols. Demy 8vo. £3 3s. net.

     =SIBORNE, CAPTAIN WILLIAM.= =The Waterloo Campaign, 1815.= With 13
     Portraits of Generals, and 15 Maps and Plans. Large Crown 8vo. 832
     pages. 6s.

     =SPALDING, THOMAS ALFRED.= =The Life and Times of Richard Badiley,
     Vice-Admiral of the Fleet.= Demy 8vo. 15s.

     =VIBART, COLONEL H. M.= =Addiscombe.= See page 13.

     =WILKINSON, SPENSER.= =The Brain of an Army.= A Popular Account of the
     German General Staff. With Letters from Count Moltke and Lord
     Roberts, and 3 Plans. Crown 8vo. 2s. 6d.

     =---- = =The Command of the Sea, and The Brain of the Navy.= Crown 8vo.
     Cloth, 2s. 6d.

     =---- = =Lessons of the War.= A Weekly Comment to the Relief of
     Ladysmith. Crown 8vo. 2s. 6d.

     =---- = =The Nation’s Awakening.= Essays towards a British Policy.
     Crown 8vo. 5s.


                               CONTENTS.

  Our Past Apathy.
  The Aims of the Great Powers.
  The Defence of British Interests.
  The Organization of Government for the Defence of British Interests.
  The Idea of the Nation.

=---- = =The Volunteers and the National Defence.= Crown 8vo. Cloth, 2s. 6d.

=---- = =War and Policy.= Essays. Demy 8vo. 15s.

       *       *       *       *       *

                               Fine Art.


     =BROWNELL, W. C.= =French Art. Classic and Contemporary Painting and
     Sculpture.= With 48 Illustrations. Small Imperial 8vo.

     =COLE, ALAN S.= =Ornament in European Silks.= With 167 Illustrations.
     Bound in half vellum. Crown 4to. 32s. net.

     =CUNYNGHAME, HENRY.= =Art-Enamelling upon Metals.= Containing both a
     History of the Art and an Account of the Manufacture of the same. 2
     Coloured Plates and 20 Illustrations. Crown 8vo. 6s. net. Second
     Edition.

     =DANIELL, A. E.= =London City Churches.= With numerous Illustrations by
     LEONARD MARTIN, and a Map. Imperial 16mo. 6s. Second Edition.

     =---- = =London Riverside Churches.= With 84 Illustrations and a
     Photogravure Frontispiece by ALEXANDER ANSTED. Imperial 16mo. 6s.

     =GRANBY, MARCHIONESS OF.= =Portraits of Men and Women.= A series of 51
     reproductions of the Marchioness of Granby’s Pencil Portraits of
     well-known Men and Women of the Day. Half vellum. Royal Quarto. £2
     2_s._ net.

     =HOPE, W. H. ST. JOHN, F.S.A.= =The Stall Plates of the Knights of the
     Order of the Garter, 1348-1485.= Imperial 8vo. With 90 full-page
     coloured plates printed upon Japan vellum. Edition limited to 500
     copies. Complete in One Volume. Bound in half leather gilt, price
     £6 net; plates and sheets loose in a portfolio, £5 10s. net;
     without binding or portfolio, £5 net.

     =HYDE, WILLIAM.= =The Nature Poems of George Meredith.= With 20
     Full-page Pictures in Photogravure by WILLIAM HYDE. Edition limited
     to 350 copies. Bound in cloth. £2 12s. 6d. net. Also a large paper
     edition of 150 copies, £5 5s. net.

     =HYDE, WILLIAM, and MEYNELL, ALICE.= =London Impressions.= Pictures in
     Photogravure and Etchings by WILLIAM HYDE, and Essays by ALICE
     MEYNELL. Royal Quarto. Edition limited to 250 copies on hand-made
     paper, bound in vellum gilt. £8 8s. net.

     =LEGG= (=LEOPOLD G. WICKHAM, B.A.=) =English Coronation Records.=
     Illustrated Edition limited to 500 copies. Imp. 8vo. 31s. 6d. net.

     =MAYO, JOHN HORSLEY.= =Medals and Decorations of the British Army and
     Navy.= With a large number of Coloured Plates and other
     Illustrations. 2 vols. Demy 8vo. £3 3s. net.

     =NATIONAL WORTHIES.= =A selection of Portraits from the National
     Portrait Gallery of London.= 140 Illustrations and Biographical
     Notes to each. Bound in full leather gilt, tooled. Crown 4to. £2
     2s. net.

     =NEWBERRY, PERCY E.= =The Life of Rekhmara.= See page 10.

     =---- = =The Gardens of the Ancient World.= See page 10.

     =THE ST. GEORGE’S CALENDAR for 1902.= Illustrated, with 12 Coloured
     Plates of the Arms of a Family of Distinction, with a short note of
     its origin. Price 1s. net.

       *       *       *       *       *

                      Educational and Technical.

     =ARBER, PROF. EDWARD, F.S.A.= =Works Edited by.=

     English Reprints. Edited by Prof. EDWARD ARBER, F.S.A., Fellow of
     King’s College, London, late English Examiner at the London
     University, and also at the Victoria University, Manchester. Cloth,
     gilt.

   1. =MILTON--Areopagitica.= 1644. 1s. net.
   2. =LATIMER--The Ploughers.= 1549. 1s. net.
   3. =GOSSON--The School of Abuse.= 1579. 1s. net.
   4. =SIDNEY--An Apology for Poetry.= ?1580. 1s. net.
   5. =WEBBE, E.--Travels.= 1590. 1s. net.
   6. =SELDEN--Table Talk.= 1634-54. 1s. net.
   7. =ASCHAM--Toxophilus.= 1544. 1s. net.
   8. =ADDISON--Criticism on ‘Paradise Lost.’= 1711-12. 1s. net.
   9. =LYLY--Euphues.= 1579-80. 4s. net.
  10. =VILLIERS--The Rehearsal.= 1671. 1s. net.
  11. =GASCOIGNE--The Steel Glass, etc.= 1576. 1s. net.
  12. =EARLE--Micro-cosmographie.= 1628. 1s. net.
  13. =LATIMER--7 Sermons before Edward VI.= 1549. 1s. 6d. net.
  14. =MORE--Utopia.= 1516-57. 1s. net.
  15. =PUTTENHAM--The Art of English Poesy.= 1589. 2s. 6d. net.
  16. =HOWELL--Instructions for Foreign Travel.= 1642. 1s. net.
  17. =UDALL--Roister Doister.= 1553-66. 1s. net.
  18. =MONK OF EVESHAM--The Revelation, etc.= 1186-1410. 1s. net.
  19. =JAMES I.--A Counterblast to Tobacco, etc.= 1604. 1s. net.
  20. =NAUNTON--Fragmenta Regalia.= 1653. 1s. net.
  21. =WATSON--Poems.= 1582-93. 1s. 6d. net.
  22. =HABINGTON--Castara.= 1640. 1s. net.
  23. =ASCHAM--The Schoolmaster.= 1570. 1s. net.
  24. =TOTTEL’S MISCELLANY--Songs and Sonnets.= 1557. 2s. 6d. net.
  25. =LEVER--Sermons.= 1550. 1s. net.
  26. =WEBBE, W.--A Discourse of English Poetry.= 1586. 1s. net.
  27. =LORD BACON--A Harmony of the ‘Essays.’= 1597-1626. 5s. net.
  28. =ROY, Etc.--Read me, and be not Wroth!= 1528. 1s. 6d. net.
  29. =RALEIGH, Etc.--Last Fight of the ‘Revenge.’= 1591. 1s. net.
  30. =GOOGE--Eclogues, Epitaphs, and Sonnets.= 1563. 1s. net.

     English Scholar’s Library, The.  Edited by Prof. EDWARD ARBER. 8vo,
     cloth, gilt.

   1. =WILLIAM CAXTON--Reynard the Fox.= 1s. 6d. net.
   2. =JOHN KNOX--The First Blast of the Trumpet.= 1s. 6d. net.
   3. =CLEMENT ROBINSON and Others--A Handful of Pleasant Delights.= 1s. 6d. net.
   4. =[SIMON FISH]--A Supplication for the Beggars.= 1s. 6d. net.
   5. =[REV. JOHN UDALL]--Diotrephes.= 1s. 6d. net.
   6. =[?]--The Return from Parnassus.= 1s. 6d. net.
   7. =THOMAS DECKER--The Seven Deadly Sins of London.= 1s. 6d. net.
   8. =EDWARD ARBER--An Introductory Sketch to the ‘Martin Marprelate’ Controversy.= 1588-1590. 3s. net.
   9. =[REV. JOHN UDALL]--A Demonstration of Discipline.= 1s. 6d. net.
  10. =RICHARD STANIHURST--Æneid I.-IV., in English Hexameters.= 3s. net.
  11. =MARTIN MARPRELATE--The Epistle.= 1s. 6d. net.
  12. =ROBERT GREENE--Menaphon.= 1s. 6d. net.
  13. =GEORGE JOY--An Apology to William Tyndale.= 1s. 6d. net.
  14. =RICHARD BARNFIELD---Poems.= 3s. net.
  15. =BISHOP THOMAS COOPER--An Admonition to the People of England.= 3s. net.
  16. =CAPTAIN JOHN SMITH--Works.= 1120 pp. Six Facsimile Maps. 2 vols. 12s. 6d. net.      [_Out of print._

     Garner, An English. New Edition in preparation.

     This Miscellany embodies the results of more than fifteen years’
     persistent search after the rarest and most valuable Tracts and
     Poems in our Literature that are not generally known. Only one copy
     now survives of the original edition of many of these Texts; and
     that copy is often not to be found in any Public Library.

     These volumes constitute a charming Pleasure Series of English
     Literature; full of most varied and graphic Narratives, and of most
     delightful and diversified Poetry.

     But a much higher use than that can be made of this _English
     Garner_. All History is ultimately based upon eye-witness
     testimony, or upon written documents. This Series will throw floods
     of light upon many little-known facts, or periods, of England’s
     past story.

     _An English Garner_ also contains many hundreds of Poems, many of
     them written in the Golden Age of English Song. This Poetry
     represents almost every conceivable form of English versification;
     and its topics range

    ‘From grave to gay, from lively to severe;’


     or, to put it in another way, from Sir J. DAVIES’ poem on the
     ‘Immortality of the Soul,’ down to ‘Old King Cole.’

     =BALLIN, MRS. ADA.= =From Cradle to School.= Crown 8vo. 3s. 6d.

     =BANKES, RODEN.= =A Story Book for Lesson Time.= Crown 8vo. Cloth, 1s.

     =BEAUMONT, W. WORBY, M. Inst. C.E.= =Motor Vehicles and Motors.= Their
     Design, Construction, and Working by Steam, Oil, and Electricity.
     With over 300 Illustrations and Working Drawings. 4to. 42s. net.

     =BLOUNT, BERTRAM.= =Practical Electro-Chemistry.= Fully Illustrated.
     Demy 8vo. 15s. net.

     =BONAVIA, EMMANUEL, M.D.= =The Flora of the Assyrian Monuments.= With
     numerous Illustrations. Demy 8vo. 10s. net.

     =---- = =Studies in the Evolution of Animals.= With over 100
     Illustrations. Fcap. 4to. 21s. net.

     =BRIGHT, CHARLES, F.R.S.E.= =Science and Engineering, 1837-1897.= Large
     Crown 8vo. Paper wrapper. 1s.

     =COLDSTREAM, J. P.= =The Institutions of Austria.= Fcap. 8vo. Cloth,
     2s.

     =---- = =The Institutions of Italy.= Fcap. 8vo. Cloth, 2s.

     =CONSTABLE’S HAND ATLAS OF INDIA.= See page 14.

     =CONSTABLE’S HAND GAZETTEER OF INDIA.= See page 14.

     =CUNYNGHAME, HENRY, C.B., M.A.= =Art-Enamelling upon Metals.= With many
     coloured and other Illustrations. Crown 8vo. 6s. net. Second
     Edition.

     =DAVIDSON, THOMAS= (Author of ‘Aristotle and the Ancient Educational
     Ideals,’ ‘Rousseau and Education according to Nature,’ etc.). =A
     History of Education.= Crown 8vo. 5s. net.

     =GALL, JOHN, M.A., LL.B.= (Late Professor of Mathematics and Physics,
     Canning College, Lucknow), and =ROBERTSON, DAVID, M.A., LL.B., B.Sc.=
     =Popular Readings in Science.= With many Diagrams, a Glossary of
     Technical Terms, and an Index. Crown 8vo, pp. 468. 4s. New Edition.

     =HACKEL, EDUARD.= =The True Grasses.= Authorized Translation. With over
     90 Illustrations and Diagrams, and a voluminous Glossary of
     Technical Terms. Demy 8vo. 10s. 6d. net.

     =HOLLAND, CLIVE.= =The Use of the Hand Camera.= With an Introduction by
     A. HORSLEY HINTON, and 22 Illustrations. Crown 8vo. Cloth, 2s. 6d.

     =JAMES, WILLIAM.= =Human Immortality.= 16mo. 2s. 6d. Fourth Edition.

     =LEACH, A. F., M.A., F.S.A.= =English Schools at the Reformation.=
     1546-8. Demy 8vo. 12s. net.

     =LEAF, CECIL H., M.A., F.R.C.S.= =The Surgical Anatomy of the
     Lymphatic Glands.= With numerous Coloured Plates. Demy 8vo. 10s. 6d.
     net.

     =LEAF, H. M., A.M.Inst.C.E., M.I.M.E.= =The Internal Wiring of
     Buildings.= With numerous Illustrations. New Edition in
     preparation.

     =LEWES, VIVIAN B.= =Acetylene.= A Handbook for the Student and
     Manufacturer. With over 200 Illustrations. Demy 8vo. 31s. 6d. net.

     =---- = (Professor of Chemistry, Royal Naval College), and =BRAME, J.
     S. S.= (Demonstrator in Chemistry, Royal Naval College, and
     Assistant Examiner in Chemistry, Science and Art Department).
     =Laboratory Note Book for Chemical Students.= 4s.

     =MORISON, M.= =Time Table of Modern History, A.D. 400-1870.= See page
     9.

     =MÜNSTERBERG, PROFESSOR HUGO.= =Psychology and Life.= Demy 8vo. 6s.
     net.

     =PEEL, MRS. C. S.= =The New Home.= How to Furnish on Small Incomes.
     With many Illustrations by AGNES WALKER. Crown 8vo. 3s. 6d.

     =---- = =Ten Shillings a Head per Week for House Books.= A Manual for
     the Economical Housekeeper. Containing a large number of New
     Recipes. Crown 8vo. 3s. 6d.

     =ROGERS, C. J.= =Coin Collecting in Northern India.= 10s. 6d. net.

     =SCRUTTON, PERCY E.= =Electricity in Town and Country Houses.= Fully
     illustrated. Crown 8vo. 2s. 6d. Third Edition.

     =SPENSER.= =The Faerie Queene.= Edited by KATE M. WARREN. With a
     Glossary and Notes to each volume. In 6 vols. Fcap. 8vo. Cloth, 1s.
     6d. net per vol. Cloth gilt, with Photogravure Frontispiece, 2s.
     6d. net per vol. Each vol. sold separately.

     =TARVER, J. C.= =Some Observations of a Foster Parent.= Crown 8vo. 6s.
     Second Edition.

     =---- = =Debateable Claims.= Essays on Secondary Education. Crown 8vo.
     6s.

     =---- = =Tiberius the Tyrant.= Demy 8vo. 16s. net.

     =THE PREVENTION OF DISEASE.= =Prophylaxis in Surgery Operations, The
     Treatment of Fractures and Dislocation, Wounds, Deformities and
     Tumours, Medicine and Insanity.= By DR. BING, Vienna; DR. EINHORN,
     New York; DR. FISCHL, Prague; DR. FLATAU, Berlin; DR. FUCHS,
     Ernmendingen; DR. GOLDSCHMIDT, Reichenhall; DR. GREVE, Magdeburg;
     DR. HOFFA, Würzburg; DR. MAX JOSEPH, Berlin; DR. KÖNIGSHÖFER,
     Stuttgart; DR. KOLLMANN, Leipzig; DR. LILIENFELD, Würzburg; DR.
     MARTIUS, Rostock; DR. MENDELSOHN, Berlin; DR. J. V. NOTTHEFFT,
     München; DR. ROSEN, Berlin; DR. O. SCHAEFFER, Heidelberg; DR.
     WINDSCHEID, Leipzic. With an Introduction by H. TIMBRELL BULSTRODE,
     M.A., D.P.H. Royal College of Physicians and Surgeons, M.R.C.S.
     Eng., L.R.C.P. London. Medical Inspector H.M. Local Government
     Board. Demy 8vo.

     =THOMSON, PROF. J. J., F.R.S.= =The Discharge of Electricity through
     Gases.= Illustrated. Crown 8vo. 4s. 6d. net.

     =TORREY, JOSEPH.= =Elementary Studies in Chemistry.= Crown 8vo. 6s.
     net.

     =TURNER, H. H., F.R.S.= =Modern Astronomy.= Being some Account of the
     Revolution of the Last Quarter of the Century. Crown 8vo. 6s. net.

     =WARREN, KATE M.= See =Spenser=, =Faerie Queene.=

     =WEBB, SURGEON-CAPTAIN W. W.= =The Coins of the Hindu States of
     Rajputana.= With 12 Plates, and a Map in colours. Royal 8vo. 16s.
     net.

     =ZIMMERMANN, DR. A.= =Botanical Microtechnique.= By DR. A. ZIMMERMANN.
     With Sixty Illustrations and Diagrams. Demy 8vo. 12s. net.

       *       *       *       *       *

                           Religious Books.


     =ARNOLD, T. W.= =The Preaching of Islam.= Demy 8vo. 12s.

     =BOOKS OF THE BIBLE.= =The Psalms.= =St. Matthew.= =St. Mark.= =St. Luke.=
     =St. John.= Printed in red and black by T. & A. Constable. Bound in
     cloth label, 1s. net per vol.; cloth gilt, 1s. 6d. net per vol.;
     leather gilt, 2s. 6d. net per vol. Also

     =The Four Gospels.= In one volume. Paper label, 2s. 6d. net; gilt
     cloth, 3s. net; leather, 5s. net.

     =DANIELL, A. E.= =London City Churches.= With numerous Illustrations by
     LEONARD MARTIN, and a Map. Imperial 16mo. 6s.

     =---- = =London Riverside Churches.= With numerous Illustrations by
     ALEXANDER ANSTED. Imperial 16mo. 6s.

     =FOUR GOSPELS.= See ‘Books of the Bible.’

     =HARALD, J. H.= =The Knowledge of Life.= Crown 8vo. 6s.

     =JAMES, WILLIAM= (Professor of Philosophy at Harvard University).
     =Human Immortality.= Two supposed Objections to the Doctrine. 16mo.
     2s. 6d.

     =MADGE, H. D.= =Leaves from the Golden Legend.= Chosen by H. D. MADGE,
     LL.M. With numerous Illustrations by H. M. WATTS. Pott 8vo. Half
     linen, gilt top, 3s. 6d. net. Second Edition.

     =MITCHELL, PROF. H. G.= =The World before Abraham.= According to
     Genesis i.-xi. Crown 8vo. 5s. net.

     =PSALMS.= See ‘Books of the Bible.’

     =RYLEY, G. BUCHANAN, and J. M. M’CANDLISH.= =Scotland’s Free Church.=
     See page 11.

  =ST. JOHN.=    }
  =ST. LUKE.=    } See ‘Books of the Bible.’
  =ST. MARK.=    }
  =ST. MATTHEW.= }

     =SINCLAIR, VEN. ARCHDEACON, D.D.= =Simplicity in Christ.= Sermons
     preached in St. Paul’s Cathedral and elsewhere. Crown 8vo. 3s. 6d.

     =SKRINE, J. HUNTLEY.= =A Goodly Heritage.= Sermons. Crown 8vo. Cloth,
     2s. 6d.

     =SNEATH, E. HERSHEY, Ph.D.= (Professor of Philosophy in Yale
     University). =The Mind of Tennyson.= His Thoughts on God, Freedom,
     and Immortality. Crown 8vo. 5s. net.

     =WILSON, J. M., M.A.= (Archdeacon of Manchester). =Truths New and Old.=
     Sermons. Crown 8vo. 6s.

     =WILSON, SARAH.= =The Romance of our Ancient Churches.= With about 200
     Illustrations by ALEXANDER ANSTED. Crown 8vo. 6s.

       *       *       *       *       *

                               Fiction.


     ‘=ALIEN=,’ Author of ‘Daughter of the King,’ etc., etc. =Another
     Woman’s Territory.= 2nd Edition. Crown 8vo. 6s.

     =ANDOM, R.= (Author of ‘We Three and Troddles’), =and HAREWOOD, FRED.=
     =The Fortune of a Spendthrift and other Items.= Crown 8vo. 3s. 6d.

     =ANON.= =All Expenses Paid.= Fcap. 8vo. 2s. 6d. net.

     =---- = =Muggleton College: Its Rise and Fall.= Fcap. 8vo. Paper, 1s.

     =ARGYLL, DUKE OF.= =Adventures in Legend.= Illustrated by FAIRFAX
     MUCKLEY and HARRISON MILLER. Crown 8vo. 6s.

     =BATES, ARLO.= =The Puritans.= Crown 8vo. 6s.

     =BERTHET, E.= =The Catacombs of Paris.= A Thrilling Story of Life in
     Paris during the 18th Century. Crown 8vo. 6s.

     =BIDDER, M.= =In the Shadow of the Crown.= With an Introduction by
     MAURICE HEWLETT. Crown 8vo. 6s. Second Edition.

     =BOWER, MARIAN.= =The Puppet Show.= Crown 8vo. 6s.

     =BRYDEN, H. A.=, Author of ‘Gun and Camera in South Africa.’ =Tales of
     South Africa.= 3s. 6d.

     =CAIRNES, CAPTAIN W. E.= =The Coming Waterloo.= 4th Edition. Crown 8vo.
     6s.

     Describes an imaginary campaign against a Continental Power, and
     gives an exposition of the use of modern arms and appliances in
     warfare. A sketch map of the scene of operations is included in the
     volume.

     =CAPES, BERNARD.= Author of ‘The Lake of Wine,’ etc. =Love like a
     Gipsy.= Crown 8vo. Cloth, 6s.

     =CARMICHAEL, M.= =Sketches and Stories, Grave and Gay.= Crown 8vo. 3s.
     6d.

     =CHAMBERS, R. W.=, Author of ‘Ashes of Empire,’ ‘The King in Yellow,’
     etc. =Cardigan.= Crown 8vo. Cloth, 6s.

     =CHARLES, JOSEPH F.= =A Statesman’s Chance.= Crown 8vo. 6s.

     =CHARRINGTON, CHARLES.= =A Sturdy Beggar and Lady Bramber’s Ghost.= Two
     Stories. Crown 8vo. 3s. 6d.

     =COOPER, E. H.=, Author of ‘Mr. Blake of Newmarket.’ =The Enemies.=
     Crown 8vo. 6s.

     =CORNISH, F. WARRE.= =Sunningwell.= Crown 8vo. 6s. Second Edition.

     =COXON, ETHEL.= =Within Bounds.= Cr. 8vo. 6s.

     =DALE, T. F. (Stoneclink), and SLAUGHTER, F. E. (Trant).= =Two
     Fortunes and Old Patch.= A Sporting Novel. Crown 8vo. 6s.

     =DARNLEY, THE COUNTESS OF, and R. Ll. HODGSON.= =Elma Trevor.= Crown
     8vo. 6s.

     =DENNY, CHARLES E.= =The Failure of the Wanderer.= Crown 8vo. 6s.

     =DOYLE, C. W.= =The Taming of the Jungle.= Bound in a cover specially
     designed by J. T. NETTLESHIP. Fcap. 8vo. 3s. 6d.

      =---- = =The Shadow of Quong Lung.= Crown 8vo. 3s. 6d.

     =FLOWERDEW, HERBERT=, Author of ‘The Celibate’s Wife,’ and ‘The
     Realist.’ =Retaliation.= Crown 8vo. 6s.

     =FORBES-ROBERTSON, FRANCES.= =The Potentate.= Crown 8vo. 6s.

     =---- = =Odd Stories.= Crown 8vo. 6s.

     =FORD, PAUL LEICESTER.= =Janice Meredith.= Crown 8vo. 6s.

     =---- = =The Story of an Untold Love.= Crown 8vo. 6s. Third Edition.

     =---- = =Tattle Tales of Cupid.= Crown 8vo. 6s.

     =GLASGOW, ELLEN=, Author of ‘The Voice of a People,’ etc. =The Battle
     Ground.= Crown 8vo. 6s.

     =GWYNN, PAUL.= =Marta.= A Novel. Crown 8vo. 6s.

     =HANNAN, CHARLES, F.R.G.S.= =Chin-Chin-Wa.= Crown 8vo. 3s. 6d.

     =HARRIS, JOEL CHANDLER (Uncle Remus).= =Sister Jane.= Crown 8vo. 6s.

     =HEWLETT, MAURICE.= Author of ‘The Forest Lovers,’ ‘Richard Yea or
     Nay.’ =New Canterbury Tales.= Crown 8vo. Cloth, 6s.

     =HUTTEN, BARONESS VON.= =Marr’d in Making.= Photogravure Frontispiece.
     Crown 8vo. 6s.

     =JAMES, HENRY.= =The Wings of the Dove.= Crown 8vo. 6s.

     =JOHNSTON, MARY.= =By Order of the Company.= Crown 8vo. 6s. Tenth
     Edition.

     =JOHNSTON, MARY.= =The Old Dominion.= Crown 8vo. 6s. Seventh Edition.

     =---- = =Audrey.= With Illustrations in Colour by F. C. YOHN. Crown
     8vo. 6s.

     =KINGSLEY, CHARLES.= =Westward Ho!= Fully Illustrated and Edited with
     an Introduction by G. LAURENCE GOMME, F.S.A. Crown 8vo. 3s. 6d.

     =LAFARGUE, PHILIP.= =Stephen Brent.= 2 vols. Crown 8vo. 12s.

     =---- = =The Salt of the Earth.= Crown 8vo. 2s. 6d.

     =LE GOFFIC, CHARLES.= =The Dark Way of Love.= Translated by E. WINGATE
     RINDER. Crown 8vo. 3s. 6d.

     =LOTI, PIERRE.= =Impressions.= Translated from the French. With an
     Introduction by HENRY JAMES. Fcap. 4to. Half vellum, gilt. 10s. 6d.

     =LOVE OF AN OBSOLETE WOMAN.= Chronicled by Herself. Fcap. 8vo. Cloth
     gilt, 2s. 6d.

     =LOVER, SAMUEL.= =The Stories of.= Centenary Edition. Edited with
     Introduction and Notes by J. T. O’DONOGHUE. Large Crown 8vo. 6s.
     per vol.

      Vol. 1. =Handy Andy.=
       “   2. =Rory O’More.=
       “   3. =Treasure Trove; or, ‘He would be a Gentleman.’=
       “   4. =Legends and Stories of Ireland= (1st Series).
       “   5. =Legends and Stories of Ireland= (2nd Series).
       “   6. =Further Stories of Ireland.=

The last volume includes Stories which have never been previously
collected, completing the issue.

     =LYTTON, LORD.= =Harold, the Last of the Saxons.= Fully Illustrated and
     edited with an Introduction by G. LAURENCE GOMME, F.S.A. Crown 8vo.
     3s. 6d.

     =MACFARLANE, CHARLES.= =The Camp of Refuge.= Fully Illustrated and
     edited with an Introduction by G. LAURENCE GOMME, F.S.A. Crown 8vo.
     3s. 6d.

     =---- = =Reading Abbey.= Fully Illustrated and edited with an
     Introduction by G. LAURENCE GOMME, F.S.A. Crown 8vo. 3s. 6d.

     =MACHRAY, ROBERT=, Author of ‘The Vision Splendid,’ =Sir Hector: The
     Story of a Scots Gentleman.= Crown 8vo. Cloth, 6s.

     =MACILWAINE, HERBERT C.= =Fate the Fiddler.= Crown 8vo. 6s.

     =---- = =Dinkinbar.= Crown 8vo. 6s. Second Edition.

     =MACLEOD, FIONA.= =The Dominion of Dreams.= Crown 8vo. 6s. Fourth
     Edition.

     =---- = =The Laughter of Peterkin.= Illustrated by SUNDERLAND
     ROLLINSON. Large Crown 8vo. 6s.

     =---- = =Green Fire.= Crown 8vo. 3s. 6d.

     =McILWRAITH, JEAN=, part Author of ‘The Span of Life.’ =The Curious
     Career of Robert Campbell.= Illustrated by FRANK SCHOONOVER. Crown
     8vo. 6s.

     =McLAWS, LAFAYETTE.= =When the Land was Young.= Illustrated by WILL
     CRAUFORD. Crown 8vo. Cloth, 6s.

     =MASON, A. E. W.=, Author of ‘Miranda of the Balcony,’ etc. =Ensign
     Knightley, and other Stories.= Crown 8vo. 6s.

     =MEREDITH, GEORGE.= =The Novels of. Library Edition.= Complete in 15
     vols., with Photogravure Frontispiece to each. Cr. 8vo. 6s. each.

     =MEREDITH, GEORGE.= =The Novels of.= In 15 Volumes. Pocket Edition.
     Printed on thin opaque paper, specially manufactured for this
     edition, bound in red cloth, gilt lettered on back and side, gilt
     top. 2s. 6d. net per volume, or 3s. 6d. net in full leather per
     volume.

      =THE ORDEAL OF RICHARD FEVEREL.=
      =RHODA FLEMING.=
      =SANDRA BELLONI.=
      =VITTORIA.=
      =DIANA OF THE CROSSWAYS.=
      =THE ADVENTURES OF HARRY RICHMOND.=
      =BEAUCHAMP’S CAREER.=
      =THE EGOIST.=
      =THE TRAGIC COMEDIANS.=
      =EVAN HARRINGTON.=
      =SHORT STORIES=:--=The Tale of Chloe.= =The House on the Beach.= =Farina.= =The Case of General Ople and Lady Camper.=
      =THE SHAVING OF SHAGPAT.=
      =THE AMAZING MARRIAGE.=
      =ONE OF OUR CONQUERORS.=
      =LORD ORMONT AND HIS AMINTA.=


     =AN ESSAY ON COMEDY.= Uniform with the Library Edition of the Novels
     of GEORGE MEREDITH. Crown 8vo. 6s.

     =TALE OF CHLOE.= Pocket Edition. 3s. 6d. net.

     =THE STORY OF BHANAVAR.= Pocket Edition. 3s. 6d. net.

     =MEREJKOWSKI, DMITRI.= =The Death of the Gods.= Translated by HERBERT
     TRENCH, late Fellow of All Souls. Crown 8vo. Cloth, 6s.

     =---- = =The Resurrection of the Gods.= Translated by HERBERT TRENCH.
     Crown 8vo. Cloth, 6s.

     =MONTAGUE, CHARLES.= =The Vigil.= A Romance of Zulu Life. With 14
     full-page Illustrations by A. D. M’CORMICK. Crown 8vo. 6s.

     =MOWBRAY, J. P.= =A Journey to Nature.= Coloured end papers, and
     specially designed head and tail pieces. Demy 8vo. 7s. 6d. net.

     =---- = =The Making of a Country Home.= Illustrated by CHARLES E.
     HOOPER. Demy 8vo. 6s. net.

     =NEWMAN, MRS.= =His Vindication.= Crown 8vo. 6s.

     =PARKER, NELLA.= =Dramas of To-day.= Crown 8vo. 3s. 6d.

     =PAYNE, WILL=, Author of ‘Jerry the Dreamer,’ etc. =The Story of Eva.=
     Crown 8vo. 6s.

     =PENROSE, MRS. H. H.= =The Modern Gospel.= Crown 8vo. 6s.

     =PERKS, MRS. HARTLEY=, Author of ‘From Heather Hills.’ =Among the
     Bracken.= Crown 8vo. 3s. 6d.

     =PICKERING, SIDNEY.= =The Romance of his Picture.= Crown 8vo. 2s. 6d.

     =PRICHARD, K. & HESKETH=, Joint Authors of ‘A Modern Mercenary.’
     =Karadac.= With Photogravure Frontispiece. Crown 8vo. 6s.

     =REED, MARCUS.= ‘=Pride of England.=’ Crown 8vo. 6s.

     ‘=RITA=,’ Author of ‘Peg the Rake,’ ‘Petticoat Loose,’ etc. =The Sin
     of Jasper Standish.= Crown 8vo. 6s.

     =RUSSELL, W. CLARK=, Author of ‘John Holdsworth, Chief Mate,’ ‘Wreck
     of the _Grosvenor_,’ etc. =The Ship’s Adventure.= Crown 8vo. 6s.

     =SCOTT, SIR WALTER.= =The Waverley Novels.= The favourite Edition of
     Sir Walter Scott. A Facsimile of the Edition of 1829 published by
     Cadell & Co. With all the original Plates after Sir DAVID WILKIE,
     R.A.; Sir EDWIN LANDSEER, R.A.; C. R. LESLIE, R.A.; CLARKSON
     STANFIELD, R.A., etc. (re-engraved). In 48 vols. Fcap. 8vo. Cloth,
     paper label title, 1s. 6d. net per volume, or £3 12s. net the set.
     Also cloth gilt, gilt top, 2s. net per volume, or £4 16s. net the
     set; and half leather, gilt, 2s. 6d. net per volume, or £6 net the
     set.

     =SETOUN, GABRIEL=, Author of ‘Robert Urquhart,’ ‘Barncraig,’ etc. =The
     Skipper of Barncraig.= Crown 8vo. Cloth, 6s.

     =SHARP, WILLIAM.= =Madge o’ the Pool.= Fcap. 8vo. 2s. 6d.

     =SINCLAIR, MAY=, Author of ‘Audrey Craven’ and ‘Mr. and Mrs. Nevill
     Tyson.’ =Two Sides of a Question.= Crown 8vo. 6s. 2nd Edition.

     =SMITH, F. HOPKINSON=, Author of ‘Tom Grogan,’ etc. =Caleb West,
     Master Diver.= Crown 8vo. 6s. Second Edition.

     =SOANE, JOHN.= =The Quest of Mr. East.= Crown 8vo. 6s.

     =STEEL, FLORA ANNIE.= =In the Tideway.= Crown 8vo. 3s. 6d.

     =STOKER, BRAM.= =Dracula.= Crown 8vo. 6s. Sixth Edition.

     =STOKER, BRAM.= =The Shoulder of Shasta.= Crown 8vo. Cloth, 3s. 6d.

     =STREET, G. S.=, Author of ‘The Autobiography of a Boy,’ etc. =A Book
     of Stories.= Crown 8vo. 6s.

     =STURGIS, JULIAN.= =The Folly of Pen Harrington.= Crown 8vo. 3s. 6d.

     =---- = =Stephen Calinari.= Crown 8vo. 6s.

     =THORBURN, S. S.= =His Majesty’s Greatest Subject.= Crown 8vo. 3s. 6d.

     =TYNAN, KATHARINE=, Author of ‘The Dear Irish Girl,’ etc., etc. =That
     Sweet Enemy.= Crown 8vo. 6s. 2nd Edition.

     =WHITE, PERCY.= =The West End.= Crown 8vo. 6s.

     =WHITE, STEWART E.= =The Westerners.= Crown 8vo. Cloth, 6s.

     =---- = =The Blazed Trail.= Crown 8vo. 6s.

     ‘=ZACK=,’ Author of ‘Life is Life’ and ‘On Trial.’ =The White Cottage.=
     Crown 8vo. 6s.

       *       *       *       *       *


                                Poetry.


     =ALLEN, REV. G. C.= =Tales from Tennyson.= 3s. 6d. net.

     =ARMSTRONG, ARTHUR COLES.= =A Tale from Boccaccio, and other Poems.=
     Crown 8vo. 5s. net.

     =BARMBY, BEATRICE HELEN.= =Gisli Sursson.= A Drama. =Ballads and Poems
     of the Old Norse Days, with some Translations.= With an Introduction
     by F. YORK POWELL. Cr. 8vo. 3s. 6d. net.

     =BATTERSBY, CARYL.= =The Song of the Golden Bough.= Crown 8vo. 3s. 6d.
     net.

     =BAUGHAN, B. E.= =Verses.= Crown 8vo. 5s.

     =BIDDER, GEORGE.= =By Southern Shore.= Crown 8vo. 5s.

     =---- = =Merlin’s Youth.= Paper, 1s. Also cloth, 5s.

     =BROWNING, ROBERT.= =Men and Women.= A limited Edition, printed on
     hand-made paper, and bound in half vellum. In 2 vols., 16mo, with
     Photogravure Frontispiece to each. 6s. net the 2 vols.

     =CAMPBELL, JAMES DYKES.= =Coleridge’s Poems.= A Facsimile Reproduction
     of the Proofs and MSS. of some of the Poems. Edited by JAMES DYKES
     CAMPBELL. With Preface and Notes by W. HALE WHITE. Edition limited
     to 250 copies, 6s. net. Large Paper edition of 50 copies, 12s. 6d.
     net.

     =DOUGHTY, CHARLES.= =Under Arms, 1900.= Price 1s. net.

  =DRYDEN, JOHN.= =Aureng-Zebe: A Tragedy.=       }
                                                            }
  =SOMERVILLE, WILLIAM.= =The Chace: A=           }
  =Poem.= Edited by KENNETH DEIGHTON. In one  }
  volume. Crown 8vo. 5s. net.                               }

     =GALE, NORMAN.= =A Country Muse.= First and Second Series. A new
     Edition containing additional Poems. Crown 8vo. 5s. each volume.

     =---- = =Cricket Songs.= Third Edition. Fcap. 8vo. Paper, 1s.

     =GARDNER, EDMUND.= =Dante’s Ten Heavens.= A Study in the ‘Paradiso.’
     Demy 8vo. 12s. Second Edition.

     =---- and PHILIP H. WICKSTEED, M.A.= =Dante and Giovanni del Vergilio.=
     Including a Critical Edition of the text of Dante’s ‘Eclogæ
     Latinæ,’ and of the poetic remains of Giovanni del Vergilio. Demy
     8vo.

     =GEMMER, C. M.= =Fidelis and other Poems.= Fcap. 8vo. Cloth, 3s. 6d.
     net.

     =GRAHAM, DAVID.= =Rizzio.= An Historical Tragedy. Crown 8vo. 5s. net.

     =---- = =Darnley.= Crown 8vo. 5s. net.

     =MEREDITH, GEORGE.= =A Reading of Life and other Poems.= Buckram. Crown
     8vo, 6s. net.

     =---- = =Poems.= 2 vols. Crown 8vo. 6s. each. Uniform with the Library
     Edition of the Works of GEORGE MEREDITH.

     =MEREDITH, GEORGE.= =Selected Poems.= Crown 8vo. Buckram, 6s. net.

     =---- = =Selected Poems.= Pocket Edition. Bound in half vellum. 16mo.
     3s. 6d. net.

     =---- = =Odes in Contribution to the Song of French History.= The
     Revolution, Napoléon, Alsace-Lorraine. Crown 8vo. Buckram, 6s. net.

     =---- = =The Nature Poems of.= With 20 full-page Photogravure Drawings
     by WILLIAM HYDE. Printed on handmade paper. Edition limited to 350
     copies. £2 12s. 6d. net. Also 150 copies on large paper, £5 5s.
     net.

     =MILLS, E. J.= =My Only Child.= Crown 8vo. 5s.

     =NESBIT, E.= =Songs of Love and Empire.= Cloth gilt. Crown 8vo. 5s.

     =PIATT, JOHN JAMES.= =The Ghost’s Entry, and other Poems.= Cloth gilt.
     Crown 8vo. 5s.

     =PIATT, MRS.= =Child World Ballads.= Crown 8vo. 5s.

     =PREMA-SAGARA; OR, THE OCEAN OF LOVE.= Translated from the Hindi by
     F. PINCOTT. Demy 8vo. 15s. net.

     =RAIT, ROBERT S.= =A Royal Rhetorician.= A Treatise on Scottis Poesie.
     A Counterblaste to Tobacco, etc., etc. By KING JAMES VI. and I.
     Edited with an Introduction by ROBERT S. RAIT, Fellow of New
     College, Oxford. 3s. 6d. net.

     =RAIT, ROBERT S.= =Poems of Montrose and Marvell.= Edited by ROBERT S.
     RAIT. 16mo, half parchment. 2s. 6d. net.

     =ROGERS, ALEXANDER.= =The Widowed Queen; or, The Rhani of Jhansi.= A
     Play. With an Introduction by SIR EDWIN ARNOLD. Fcap. 8vo. 5s.

     =SHAKESPEARE, WILLIAM.= =Illustrated Edition of the Works of.= In 20
     Imperial 16mo Volumes with coloured title-page and end-papers
     designed by LEWIS F. DAY, and a specially designed coloured
     illustration to each Play, the artists being: L. LESLIE BROOKE,
     BYAM SHAW, HENRY J. FORD, G. P. JACOMB HOOD, W. D. EDEN, ESTELLE
     NATHAN, ELEANOR F. BRICKDALE, PATTEN WILSON, ROBERT SAUBER, JOHN D.
     BATTEN, GERALD MOIRA, and FRANK C. COWPER. The title-page and
     illustrations printed on Japanese vellum. Cloth gilt, extra, gilt
     top, gilt back, with headband and bookmarker, 2s. 6d. net per
     volume, or £2 10s. the set. Each volume sold separately.

     =SKRINE, J. HUNTLEY.= =Songs of the Maid.= Crown 8vo. 5s.

     =SPENSER, EDMUND.= =The Faerie Queene.= Complete in Six Volumes. Fcap.
     8vo. Cloth, 9s. net. Edited by KATE M. WARREN. 1s. 6d. net each.
     Also Art Canvas, gilt extra, with Photogravure Frontispiece, 2s.
     6d. net per vol.; complete in case, 15s. net.

     =STANTON, FRANK L.= =Songs of the Soil.= With a Preface by JOEL
     CHANDLER HARRIS (UNCLE REMUS). Fcap. 8vo. 5s. net.

     =STEVENSON, WALLACE.= =Some Songs and Verses.= Crown 8vo. 5s. net.

     =THOMPSON, FRANCIS.= =New Poems.= Crown 8vo. 6s. net.

     =THOMSON, JAMES.= =Poems.= By JAMES THOMSON, Weaver of Kenleith. Demy
     8vo. 7s. 6d.

     =VIALLS, M. A.= =Music Fancies.= Crown 8vo. 5s. net.

     =WICKSTEED, PHILIP H., M.A., and EDMUND G. GARDNER, M.A.= =Dante and
     Giovanni del Vergilio.= Including a Critical Edition of the text of
     Dante’s ‘Eclogæ Latinæ,’ and of the poetic remains of Giovanni del
     Vergilio. Demy 8vo. 12s.

     =WILSON, ROBERT.= =Laurel Leaves.= Crown 8vo. 5s.

       *       *       *       *       *

                         Books for the Young.


     =ALLEN, REV. G. C., M.A.= (Head Master of Cranleigh School). =Tales
     from Tennyson.= With two Photogravures. Crown 8vo. 3s. 6d. net.

     =ARGYLL, DUKE OF.= =Adventures in Legend.= Tales of the West Highlands.
     With numerous Illustrations by HARRISON MILLER and FAIRFAX MUCKLEY.
     Crown 8vo. 6s.

     =BANKES, RODEN.= =A Story Book for Lesson Time.= Cloth, crown 8vo. 1s.

     =GALE, NORMAN.= =Cricket Songs.= Fcap. 8vo. Paper, 1s. Third Edition.

     =GOMME, G. LAURENCE.= Books edited by.

     =---- = =The King’s Story Book.= Illustrated by HARRISON MILLER.

     =---- = =The Queen’s Story Book.= Illustrated by W. H. ROBINSON.

     =---- = =The Prince’s Story Book.= Illustrated by H. S. BANKS.

     =---- = =The Princess’s Story Book.= Illustrated by HELEN STRATTON.

     Historical Stories collected out of English Romantic Literature, in
     illustration of the Reigns of English Monarchs from the Conquest to
     Queen Victoria.

     New Editions of each of these Story Books are in preparation.

     =Harold: The Last of the Saxons.= By LORD LYTTON. Crown 8vo.
     Illustrated. 3s. 6d.

     =The Camp of Refuge.= By CHARLES MACFARLANE. Crown 8vo. Illustrated.
     3s. 6d.

     =Westward Ho!= By CHARLES KINGSLEY. Crown 8vo. Illustrated. 3s. 6d.

     =Reading Abbey.= By CHARLES MACFARLANE. Crown 8vo. Illustrated. 3s.
     6d.

     =HARRIS, JOEL CHANDLER (Uncle Remus).= =Sister Jane, Her Friends and
     Acquaintances.= Crown 8vo. 6s.

     =MACLEOD, FIONA.= =The Laughter of Peterkin.= A Re-telling of Old
     Stories of the Celtic Wonder-World. Illustrated by SUNDERLAND
     ROLLINSON. Large Crown 8vo. 6s.

     =PAINE, ALBERT BIGELOW.= =The Hollow Tree.= Illustrated by J. M. CONDÉ.
     Bound in coloured boards. 4to. 3s. 6d.

     =SINGING TIME.= =A Child’s Song Book.= Music by ARTHUR SOMERVELL.
     Drawings by L. LESLIE BROOKE. Square 4to. 5s.

       *       *       *       *       *

INDEX TO AUTHORS

Addison, Joseph, 22.

‘Alien,’ 33.

Allen, Rev. G. C., 42.

Andom, R., 33.

Anitchkow, Michael, 3.

Anon., 3, 33.

Arber, Professor Edward, 22-25.

Argyll, Duke of, 33.

Armstrong, Arthur Coles, 42.

Arnold, T. W., 3.

Arnold, Sir Edwin, 45.

Ascham, Roger, 22, 23.


Bacon, Lord, 23.

Bain, R. Nisbet, 3.

Ballin, Mrs. A., 26.

Bankes, Roden, 26.

Barmby, Beatrice Helen, 42.

Barnfield, Richard, 25.

Bartholomew, J. G., F.R.G.S., 14.

Bates, Arlo, 33.

Battersby, Caryl, 42.

Battye, A. Trevor-, F.L.S., 14.

Baughan, B. E., 42.

Bayley, Sir Steuart Colvin, 7.

Beatty, William, M.D., 3.

Beaumont, Worby, 26.

Berthet, E., 33.

Bertram, James, 4.

Bidder, George, 42.

Bidder, M., 33.

Birdwood, Sir George, M.D., K.C.I.E., C.S.I., LL.D., 15.

Birrell, Augustine, Q.C., M.P., 4.

Black, C. E. D., 10.

Blount, Bertram, 26.

Bonavia, Emmanuel, M.D., 26.

Boswell, James, 4.

Bower, Marian, 33.

Brabant, Arthur Baring, 10.

Bradley, A. G., 4.

Brame, J. S. S., 28.

Bright, Charles, F.R.S.E., 4.

Bright, Edward Brailston, C.E., 4.

Brownell, W. C., 20.

Browning, Robert, 42.

Bryden, H. A., 33.

Burroughs, John, 5.


Cairnes, Capt. W. E., 33.

Campbell, James Dykes, 42.

Campbell, Lord Archibald, 5.

Capes, Bernard, 33.

Carmichael, M., 34.

Caxton, William, 24.

‘Centurion,’ 5.

Chailley-Bert, J., 5.

Chamberlain, Rt. Hon. Joseph, M.P., D.C.L., LL.D., 5.

Chambers, R. W., 34.

Charles, Joseph F., 34.

Charrington, Charles, 34.

Coldstream, J. P., 26.

Cole, Alan S., 20.

Collins, J. Churton, 5.

Conway, Sir William Martin, 14.

Cooper, Bishop Thomas, 25.

Cooper, E. H., 34.

Cornish, F. Warre, 34.

Courtney, W. L., 5.

Coxon, Ethel, 34.

Cunynghame, Henry, 20.

Currie, Maj.-Gen. Fendall, 5.

Curzon, The Right Hon. George N. (Lord Curzon of Kedleston), 5.


Dale, T. F. (Stoneclink), 17, 34.

Daniell, A. E., 20, 31.

Danvers, Fred. Charles, 7.

Darnley, Countess of, 34.

Davidson, Thomas, 6.

Decker, Thomas, 24.

Deighton, Kenneth, 6.

De Bury, Mlle. Blaze, 6.

Denny, Charles E., 34.

Dinsmore, Charles A., 6.

Doughty, Charles, 43.

Doyle, C. W., 34.

Dryden, John, 43.

Duff, C. M., 6.

Durand, Lady, 15.

Dutt, R. C., C.I.E., 6.


Earle, Alice Morse, 12.

Earle, John, 22.

Elliott, Robert H., 15.

Englehardt, A. P., 15.


Filippi, Filippo de, 15.

Fish, Simon, 24.

Flowerdew, Herbert, 35.

Forbes-Robertson, Frances, 35.

Ford, Paul Leicester, 35.

Fox, Arthur W., 6.


Gairdner, James, 6.

Gale, Norman, 43.

Gall, John, M.A., LL.B., 27.

Gardner, Edmund, 43.

Gascoigne, George, 22.

Gemmer, C. M., 43.

Glasgow, Ellen, 35.

Godkin, E. L., 6, 7.

Goffic, Charles le, 36.

Gomme, G. Laurence, 7, 36, 37, 47.

Googe, Barnabe, 23.

Gosson, Stephen, 22.

Graham, David, 43.

Granby, Marchioness of, 20.

Greene, Robert, M.A., 24.

Gribble, Francis, 7.

Guillemard, Dr. F. H. H., 16.

Gwynn, Paul, 35.


Habington, William, 23.

Hackel, Eduard, 27.

Hake, A. Egmont, 7.

Hanna, Col. H. B., 7, 18.

Hannan, Charles, F.R.G.S., 35.

Harald, J. H., 31.

Harewood, Fred., 33.

Harris, Joel Chandler (Uncle Remus), 35.

Hayden, E. G., 7.

Hewitt, J. F., 7.

Hewlett, Maurice, 35.

Hodgson, R. Ll., 15, 34.

Holden, Ed. S., LL.D., 8.

Holland, Clive, 27.

Hope, W. H. St. John, 8, 20.

Houfe, C. A., 8.

Howell, James, 23.

Hunter, Sir W. W., 8.

Hutten, Baroness von, 35.

Hyde, William, 21.


Irwin, Sidney T., 8.


James, Henry, 35, 36.

James, King, the First, 23.

James, William, 8.

Jardine, Hon. Mr. Justice, 16.

Johnston, Mary, 35, 36.

Joy, George, 25.


Kennedy, Admiral, 17.

Kingsley, Charles, 36.

Knox, John, 24.

Krehbiel, Henry E., 8.


Lachambre, Henri, 15.

Lafargue, Philip, 36.

Lane-Poole, Stanley, 8.

Latimer, Hugh, 22.

Leach, A. F., M.A., 8, 27.

Leaf, Cecil H., M.A., 27.

Leaf, H. M., M.I.E.E., 27.

Legg, L. G. Wickham, 8, 21.

Lever, Rev. Thomas, 23.

Lewes, Vivian B., 28.

Loti, Pierre, 36.

Lover, Samuel, 36.

Lyly, John, 22.

Lytton, Lord, 36.


Macfarlane, Charles, 37.

MacGeorge, G. W., 8.

Machuron, Alexis, 15.

MacIlwaine, Herbert C., 37.

Macleod, Fiona, 37, 48.

MacNair, Major J. F. A., 9.

Machray, Robert, 37.

Madge, H. D., Rev., 31.

Marprelate, Martin, 24.

Mason, A. E. W., 37.

Masterman, N., 9.

Mayo, John Horsley, 18.

M’Candlish, J. M., 10.

McIlwraith, Jean, 37.

McLaws, Lafayette, 37.

Meakin, A. M. B., 16.

Meredith, George, 9, 21, 37, 38, 43.

Merejkowski, Dmitri, 38.

Metcalfe, Charles Theophilus, C.S.I., 9.

Meynell, Alice, 21.

Mills, E. J., 44.

Milton, John, 22.

Mitchell, H. G., 32.

Monier-Williams, Sir M., K.C.I.E., 7.

Monk of Evesham, A, 23.

Montague, Charles, 39.

More, Sir Thomas, 22.

Morison, M., 9, 28.

Morison, Theodore, 9.

Mowbray, J. P., 39.

Münsterberg, Hugo, 9.


Nansen, Fridtjof, 16.

Naunton, Sir Robert, 23.

Nesbit, E., 44.

Newberry, Percy E., 10, 21.

Newman, Mrs., 39.

Nisbet, John, 10.


O’Donoghue, J. T., 56.

Ookhtomsky, Prince E., 16.

Oppert, Gustav, 10.


Paine, Albert Bigelow, 48.

Palmer, Walter, M.P., 10.

Parker, Nella, 39.

Payne, Will, 39.

Peel, Mrs., 28.

Penrose, Mrs. H. H., 39.

Perks, Mrs. Hartley, 39.

Piatt, John James, 44.

Piatt, Mrs., 44.

Pickering, Sidney, 39.

Pincott, F., 44.

Popowski, Joseph, 10.

Powell, F. York, 42.

Prichard, Hesketh, 16.

Prichard, K. & Hesketh, 39.

Puttenham, George, 23.


Rait, R. S., 10, 44, 45.

Raleigh, Sir Walter, 23.

Reed, Marcus, 39, 58.

Rice, Louis, 10.

Rinder, E. Wingate, 36.

‘Rita,’ 39.

Roberts, Morley, 16.

Robertson, David, 27.

Robinson, Clement, 24.

Rogers, Alexander, 45.

Rogers, C. J., 28.

Roosevelt, Theodore, 11.

Round, J. Horace, M.A., 11.

Roy, W., 23.

Russell, W. Clark, 40.

Ryley, Rev. J. Buchanan, 11, 32.


Sangermano, Father, 16.

Sapte, Brand, 7.

Schweitzer, Georg, 11.

Scott, Eva, 11.

Scott, Sir Walter, 40.

Scrutton, Percy E., 28.

Selden, John, 22.

Selfe, Rose E., 12.

Setoun, Gabriel, 40.

Shakespeare, William, 45.

Sharp, William, 40.

Siborne, Captain William, 11, 18.

Sichel, Edith, 12.

Sidney, Sir Philip, 22.

Sinclair, May, 40.

Sinclair, Ven. Archdeacon, D.D., 52.

Skrine, J. Huntley, 32, 45.

Slaughter, Frances, 34.

Smith, Edward, 12.

Smith, F. Hopkinson, 40.

Smith, Captain John, 25.

Smythe, A. J., 12.

Sneath, E. Hershey, 12, 32.

Soane, John, 40.

Somervell, Arthur, 48.

Somerville, William, 43.

Spalding, Thomas Alfred, 12, 18.

Spenser, Edmund, 45.

Stadling, J., 16.

Stanihurst, Richard, 24.

Stanton, Frank L., 45.

Steel, Flora Annie, 40.

Stein, M. A., 12.

Stevenson, Wallace, 45.

Stoker, Bram, 40, 41.

Stoneclink (T. F. Dale), 6, 17, 34.

Street, G. S., 12, 41.

Stuart, John, 12.

Sturgis, Julian, 41.


Tarver, J. C., 29.

Thompson, Francis, 46.

Thomson, J. J., F.R.S., 29.

Thomson, James, 46.

Thorburn, S. S., 41.

Thornton, Surg.-General, C.B., 13.

Torrey, Joseph, 29.

Tottel, R., 23.

Townsend, Meredith, 12.

Traill, H. D., 13.

Trench, Herbert, 38.

Turner, H. H., F.R.S., 29.

Tynan, Katharine, 41.


Udall, Rev. John, 24.

Udall, Nicholas, 23.


Vallery-Radot, R., 13.

Vibart, Colonel Henry M., 13, 19.

Villiers, George, 22.


Waddell, Surg.-Maj. J. A., 16.

Walker, Charles, 17.

Warren, Kate M., 28, 30.

Watson, Thomas. 23.

Webb, Surgeon-Captain, W. W., 30.

Webbe, E., 22.

Webbe, William, 23.

Wesslau, O. E., 7.

White, W. Hale, 42.

White, Percy, 41.

White, Stewart E., 41.

Whiteway, R. S., 13.

Wicksteed, Rev. P. H., 13, 43.

Wigram, Percy, 7.

Wilkinson, Spenser, 13, 18, 19.

Wilson, A. J., 17.

Wilson, J. M., M.A., 32.

Wilson, Robert, 46.

Wilson, Sarah, 32.

Winslow, Anna Green, 13.

Wood, Walter, 13.


Young, Ernest, 16.


‘Zack,’ 41.

Zimmermann, Dr. A., 50.


       *       *       *       *       *


                         A CATALOGUE OF BOOKS

                             PUBLISHED BY

                     Archibald Constable & Co. Ltd


Arranged in Order of Prices


***=Waverley Novels.= See page 64.


[Sidenote: =1s.=]

     =Anon. Muggleton College.=

     =Bankes (Roden) A Story Book for Lesson Time.=

     =Bidder (George) Merlin’s Youth.= Paper.

     =Bright (Charles) Science and Engineering, 1837-97.=

     =Gale (Norman) Cricket Songs.=

     =Palmer (Walter, M.P.) Poultry Management on a Farm.=


[Sidenote: =1s. Net.=]

     =Philips (F. C.) A Full Confession.=

     =The Books of the Bible--Psalms, St. Matthew, St. Mark, St. Luke,
     St. John.= Cloth. Paper label.

     =The St. George’s Kalendar, 1902.=


[Sidenote: =1s. 6d. Net.=]

=Doughty (Charles) Under Arms, 1900.=

=Scott (Sir Walter) The Waverley Novels.= 48 Volumes. Label. Per vol.

=The Books of the Bible--Psalms, St. Matthew, St. Mark, St. Luke, St.
John.= Cloth gilt.

=Warren (Kate M.) Spenser’s Faerie Queene.= 6 vols. Each.


[Sidenote: =2s.=]

     =Chamberlain (Rt. Hon. Joseph, M.P.) Patriotism.= Buckram.

     =Coldstream (John P.) Institutions of Austria.=

=----                       “      “  Italy.=



[Sidenote: =2s. Net.=]

     =Scott (Sir Walter) The Waverley Novels.= 48 vols. Cloth gilt. Per
     Vol.


[Sidenote: =2s.6d.=]

     =Anon. The Love of an Obsolete Woman.=

     =Hanna (Col. H. B.) Backwards or Forwards.=

     =---- Can Russia Invade India?=

      =---- India’s Scientific Frontier.=

     =Holland (Clive) The Use of the Hand Camera.=

     =Houfe (C. A.) The Question of the Houses.=

     =James (William) Human Immortality.=

     =Lafargue (Philip) The Salt of the Earth.=

     =Pickering (Sidney) The Romance of his Picture.=

     =Scrutton (Percy E.) Electricity in Town and Country Houses.=

     =Sharp (William) Madge o’ the Pool.=

     =Skrine (J. Huntley) A Goodly Heritage.=

     =Stoker (Bram) The Shoulder of Shasta.=

     =Wilkinson (Spenser) The Brain of an Army.=

     =---- Lessons of the War.=----

     =---- The Volunteers and the National Defence.=

     =---- The Command of the Sea and the Brain of the Navy.=


[Sidenote: =2s. 6d. Net.=]

     =Anon. All Expenses Paid.=

     =Beatty (William, M.D.) An Authentic Narrative of the Death of
     Nelson.=

     =Four Gospels.= Cloth. Paper label.

     =Meredith (George) The Novels of.= Pocket Edition. 15 vols. Each.

     =Rait (R. S.) Poems of Montrose and Marvell.=

     =Scott (Sir Walter) The Waverley Novels.= 48 vols. Leather. Per vol.

     =Shakespeare. The Works of.= Illustrated. 20 vols. Each.

     =The Books of the Bible--Psalms, St. Matthew, St. Mark, St. Luke,
     St. John.= Leather gilt.

     =Walker (C.) Amateur Fish Culture.=

     =Warren (Kate M.) Spenser’s Faerie Queene.= Cloth gilt. 6 vols. Each.


[Sidenote: =3s. Net.=]

     =Four Gospels.= Cloth gilt.


[Sidenote: =3s. 6d.=]

     =Andom (R.) and Harewood (F.) The Fortune of a Spendthrift.=

     =Anon. Muggleton College.= Cloth.

     =Ballin (Mrs. Ada) From Cradle to School.=

     =Bryden (H. A.) Tales of South Africa.=

     =Carmichael (Montgomery) Sketches and Stories, Grave and Gay.=

     =Charrington (Charles) A Sturdy Beggar, and Lady Bramber’s Ghost.=
     Two Stories.

     =Doyle (C. W.) The Shadow of Quong Lung.=

     =---- The Taming of the Jungle.=

     =Goffic (C. Le) The Dark Way of Love.=

     =Hannan (Charles, F.R.G.S.) Chin-Chin-Wa.=

     =Kingsley (Charles) Westward Ho!=

     =Lytton (Lord) Harold.=

     =Macfarlane (Charles) The Camp of Refuge.=

     =---- Reading Abbey.=

     =Macleod (Fiona) Green Fire.=

     =Morison (Theodore) Imperial Rule in India.=

     =Parker (Nella) Dramas of To-Day.=

     =Peel (Mrs. C. S.) The New Home.=

     =---- Ten Shillings a Head per Week for House-books.=

     =Perks (Mrs. Hartley) Among the Bracken.=

     =Sinclair (Ven. Archdeacon, D.D.) Simplicity in Christ.=

     =Steele (F. A.) In the Tideway.=

     =Stoker (Bram) The Shoulder of Shasta.=

     =Sturgis (Julian) The Folly of Pen Harrington.=

     =Thorburn (S. S.) His Majesty’s Greatest Subject.=

     =Ward (Prof. A. W.) Sir Henry Wotton.=


[Sidenote: =3s. 6d. Net=]

     =Allen (G. C.) Tales from Tennyson.=

     =Barmby (B. H.) Gisli Sursson. A Drama.=

     =Battersby (Caryl) The Song of the Golden Bough.=

     =Courtney (W. L.) The Idea of Tragedy.=

     =Deighton (Kenneth) Conjectural Readings in the Old Dramatists.=

     =Gemmer (C. M.) Fidelis and other Poems.=

     =Madge (H. D.) Leaves from the Golden Legend.=

     =Meredith (George) Selected Poems.= Pocket Edition.

     =---- Tale of Chloe.= Pocket Edition.

     =---- The Story of Bhanavar.= Pocket Edn.

     =Rait (R. S.) A Royal Rhetorician.=

     =The Manchester Stage, 1880-1900.=


[Sidenote: =4s.=]

     =Gall (John, M.A., LL.B.) and Robertson (David, B.Sc.) Popular
     Readings in Science.=

     =Lewes (Vivian B.) and Brame (J. S. S.) Laboratory Note Book for
     Chemical Students.=


[Sidenote: =4s. Net.=]

     =Boswell’s Account of Dr. Johnson’s Tour in the Hebrides.= 2 volumes.
     Cloth.


[Sidenote: =4s. 6d.=]

     =Meredith Birthday Book.=


[Sidenote: =4s. 6d. Net.=]

     =Thomson (J. J.) The Discharge of Electricity through Gases.=


[Sidenote: =5s.=]

     =Baughan (B. E.) Verses.=

     =Bidder (George) By Southern Shore.=

     =---- Merlin’s Youth.= Cloth.

     =Four Gospels.= Leather.

     =Gale (Norman) A Country Muse.= 1st Series.

     =---- = 2nd Series.

     =Mills (E. J.) My Only Child.=

     =Nesbit (E.) Songs of Love and Empire.=

     =Piatt (J. J.) The Ghost’s Entry.=

     =Piatt (Mrs.) Child World Ballads.=

     =Rogers (Alexander) The Widowed Queen.=

     =Skrine (J. H.) Songs of the Maid.=

     =Somervell (A.) and Brooke (Leslie) Singing Time.= A Child’s Song
     Book.

     =Walker (Charles) Shooting on a Small Income.=

     =Wilkinson (Spenser) The Nation’s Awakening.=

     =Wilson (Robert) Laurel Leaves.=


[Sidenote: =5s. Net.=]

     =Armstrong (Arthur Coles) A Tale from Boccaccio.=

     =Davidson (Thomas) A History of Education.=

     =Dinsmore (Charles A.) The Teachings of Dante.=

     =Dryden (John) Aureng-Zebe, Somerville (William) The Chace.= Edited
     by Kenneth Deighton.

     =Graham (David) Rizzio.=

     =---- Darnley.=

     =Mitchell (H. G.) The World Before Abraham.=

     =Seton-Watson (R. W.) Maximilian.=

     =Sneath (E. Hershey) The Mind of Tennyson.=

     =Stanton (Frank L.) Songs of the Soil.=


[Sidenote: =6s.=]

     =‘Alien’ Another Woman’s Territory.=

     =Argyll (Duke of) Adventures in Legend.=

     =Bates (Arlo) The Puritans.=

     =Berthet (E.) The Catacombs of Paris.=

     =Bidder (M.) In the Shadow of the Crown.=

     =Bower (Marian) The Puppet Show.=

     =Bradley (A. G.) The Fight with France for North America.=

     =Cairnes (Captain W. E.) The Coming Waterloo.=

     =Capes (Bernard) Love Like a Gipsy.=

     =Chambers (R. W.) Cardigan.=

     =Charles (Joseph F.) A Statesman’s Chance.=

     =Conway (Sir William Martin) The Alps from End to End.=

     =Cooper (E. H.) The Enemies.=

     =Cornish (F. Warre) Sunningwell.=

     =Coxon (Ethel) Within Bounds.=

     =Currie (Major-Gen. Fendall) Below the Surface.=

     =Dale (T. F.) and Slaughter (F. E.) Two Fortunes and Old Patch.=

     =Daniell (A. E.) London City Churches.=

     =---- London Riverside Churches.=

     =Darnley (Countess of) and Hodgson (R. Ll.) Elma Trevor.=

     =De Bury (Yetta Blaze) French Literature of To-day.=

     =Denny (Charles E.) The Failure of the Wanderer.=

     =Dutt (R. C.) The Literature of Bengal.=

     =Flowerdew (H.) Retaliation.=

     =Forbes-Robertson (Francis) Odd Stories.=

     =---- The Potentate.=

     =Ford (Paul Leicester) The Story of an Untold Love.=

     =---- Tattle Tales of Cupid.=

     =---- Janice Meredith.=

     =Gallon (Tom) The Man who Knew Better.=

     =Glasgow (Ellen) The Battle Ground.=

     =Gwynn (Paul) Marta.=

     =Harald (H. J.) The Knowledge of Life.=

     =Harris (Joel Chandler) Sister Jane.=

     =Hewlett (Maurice) New Canterbury Tales.=

     =Hutten (Baroness von) Marr’d in Making.=

     =James (Henry) The Wings of the Dove.=

     =Johnston (Mary) The Old Dominion.=

     =---- By Order of the Company.=

     =---- Audrey.=

     =Krehbiel (Henry E.) Music and Manners in the Classical Period.=

     =Lachambre and Machuron. Andrée and his Balloon.=

     =Lover (Samuel) Handy Andy.=

     =---- Treasure Trove.=

     =---- Rory O’More.=

     =---- Legends and Stories of Ireland.= Vol. I.

     =-------- = Vol. II.

     =----Further Stories.=

     =Machray (Robert) Sir Hector.=

     =MacIlwaine (Herbert C.) Dinkinbar.=

     =----Fate the Fiddler.=

     =McIlwraith (Jean N.) Curious Career of Robert Campbell.=

     =McLaws (Lafayette) When the Land was Young.=

     =Macleod (Fiona) The Laughter of Peterkin.=

     =---- The Dominion of Dreams.=

     =Mason (A. E. W.) Ensign Knightley, and other Stories.=

     =Meakin (A. M. B.) A Ribbon of Iron.=

     =Meredith (George) The Ordeal of Richard Feverel.=

     =---- Rhoda Fleming.=

     =---- Sandra Belloni.=

     =---- Vittoria.=

     =---- Diana of the Crossways.=

     =---- Beauchamp’s Career.=

      =---- The Adventures of Harry Richmond.=

     =Meredith (George) The Egoist.=

     =---- The Tragic Comedians.=

     =---- Evan Harrington.=

     =---- The Tale of Chloe and other Stories.=

     =---- The Shaving of Shagpat.=

     =---- The Amazing Marriage.=

     =---- One of Our Conquerors.=

     =---- Poems.= 2 vols. Each.

     =---- Lord Ormont and his Aminta.=

     =---- An Essay on Comedy.=

     =Merejkowski (Dmitri) The Death of the Gods.=

     =---- The Resurrection of the Gods.=

     =Montague (Charles) The Vigil.=

     =Nansen (Fridtjof) Farthest North.=

     =Newman (Mrs.) His Vindication.=

     =Payne (Will) The Story of Eva.=

     =Penrose (Mrs. H. H.) The Modern Gospel.=

     =Prichard (K. & H.) Karadac.=

     =Reed (Marcus) ‘Pride of England.’=

     =‘Rita’ The Sin of Jasper Standish.=

     =Russell (W. Clark) The Ship’s Adventure.=

     =Scott (Eva) Rupert, Prince Palatine.=

     =Setoun (Gabriel) The Skipper of Barncraig.=

     =Siborne (Captain William) The Waterloo Campaign, 1815.=

     =Sichel (Edith) The Household of the Lafayettes.=

     =Sinclair (May) Two Sides of a Question.=

     =Smith (F. Hopkinson) Caleb West: Master Diver.=

     =Soane (John) The Quest of Mr. East.=

     =Stoker (Bram) Dracula.=

     =Street (G. S.) A Book of Stories.=

     =Sturgis (Julian) Stephen Calinari.=

     =Tarver (J. C.) Some Observations of a Foster Parent.=

     =---- Debateable Claims.=

     =Trevor-Battye (Aubyn) A Northern Highway of the Czar.=

     =Tynan (Katharine) That Sweet Enemy.=

     =Waddell (Major L. A.) Among the Himalayas.=

     =White (Stewart E.) The Westerners.=

     =---- The Blazed Trail.=

     =Wicksteed (Rev. P. H.) The Chronicle of Villani.=

     =Wilson (Archdeacon J. M.) Truths New and Old.=

     =Wilson (Sarah) The Romance of our Ancient Churches.=

     =Winslow (Mrs. Anna Green) Diary of a Boston School Girl.=

     =Young (Ernest) The Kingdom of the Yellow Robe.=

     =‘Zack’ The White Cottage.=


[Sidenote: =6s. Net.=]

     =Boswell’s Account of Dr. Johnson’s Tour in the Hebrides.= Half
     leather. 2 vols. The set.

     =Browning (Robert) Men and Women.= 2 vols. The set.

     =Burroughs (John) Whitman.=

     =Campbell (James Dykes) Coleridge’s Poems.=

     =Cunynghame (H. H.) Art Enamelling on Metals.= Illustrated. Second
     Edition.

     =Godkin (E. L.) Unforeseen Tendencies of Democracy.=

     =Meredith (George) Odes in Contribution to the Song of French
     History.=

     =---- Selected Poems.=

     =---- A Reading of Life.=

     =Mowbray (J. P.) The Making of a Country Home.=

     =Münsterberg (Hugo) Psychology and Life.=

     =Thompson (Francis) New Poems.=

     =Torrey (Joseph) Elementary Studies in Chemistry.=

     =Turner (H. H., F.R.S.) Modern Astronomy.=


[Sidenote: =7s. 6d.=]

     =Bertram (James) Some Memories of Books, Authors and Events.=

     =Chailley-Bert (J.) Colonisation of Indo-China.=

     =Collins (Churton) Ephemera Critica.=

     =Curzon (Lord, of Kedleston) Problems of the Far East.=

     =Elliott (Robert) Gold, Sport, and Coffee-Planting in Mysore.=

     =Godkin (E. L.) Reflections and Comments.=

     =---- Problems of Modern Democracy.=

     =Hodgson (R. Ll.) On Plain and Peak.=

     =Stuart (John) Pictures of War.=

     =Thomson (James) Poems.=


[Sidenote: =7s. 6d. Net.=]

     =Hayden (E. G.) Travels Round our Village.=

     =Masterman (N.) Chalmers on Charity.=

     =McCrindle (J. W.) Ancient India as described in Classical
     Literature.=

     =Mowbray (J. P.) A Journey to Nature.=

     =Roberts (Morley) The Western Avernus.=


[Sidenote: =9s. Net.=]

     =Spenser (Edmund) The Faerie Queene.= 6 vols. Cloth.


[Sidenote: =10s. Net.=]

     =Bonavia (Emmanuel) Flora of the Assyrian Monuments.=

     =Hanna (Col. H. B.) The Second Afghan War.= Vol. I.


[Sidenote: =10s. 6d.=]

     =Constable’s Hand Gazetteer of India.=

     =Holden (Ed. S.) Mogul Emperors of Hindustan.=

     =Jardine (Hon. Justice) Burma a Hundred Years Ago.=

     =Loti (Pierre) Impressions.=

     =McNair (Major J. F. A.) Prisoners their Own Warders.=

     =Ryley and M’Candlish, Scotland’s Free Church.=


[Sidenote: =10s. 6d. Net.=]

     =Bain (R. Nisbet) Peter III.=

     =Gairdner (James) The Paston Letters.= Supplementary Volume.

     =Hackel (Eduard) The True Grasses.=

     =Leaf (Cecil H.) The Surgical Anatomy of the Lymphatic Glands.=

     =List of 837 London Publishers.=

     =Rogers (C. J.) Coin Collecting in Northern India.=

     =Roosevelt (Theodore) Oliver Cromwell.=

     =Townsend (Meredith) Asia and Europe.=


[Sidenote: =12s.=]

     =Arnold (T. W.) The Preaching of Islam.=

     =Gardner (E. G.) Dante’s Ten Heavens.=

     =Gardner (E. G.) and Wicksteed (P. H.) Dante and Giovanni del
     Virgilio.=

     =Gomme (G. Laurence) The Principles of Local Government.=

     =Hewitt (J. F.) Ruling Races of Prehistoric Times.= Second Series.

     =Irwin (S. T.) Letters of T. E. Brown.= 2 vols.

     =Lafargue (Philip) Stephen Brent.= 2 vols.

     =Metcalfe (C. T.) Two Native Narratives of the Mutiny in Delhi.=

     =Prichard (Hesketh) Where Black Rules White.=

     =Traill (H. D.) England, Egypt and the Sudan.=


[Sidenote: =12s. Net.=]

     =Boswell’s Life of Johnson.= Edited by Augustine Birrell. 6 vols.,
     fcap. 8vo.

     =Lane Poole (Stanley) Mohammedan Dynasties.=

     =Leach (A. F., M.A., F.S.A.) English Schools at the Reformation,
     1546-48.=

     =Zimmermann (Dr. A.) Botanical Microtechnique.=


[Sidenote: =12s. 6d.=]

     =Popowski (Joseph) The Rival Powers in Central Asia.=

     =Smythe (A. J.) William Terriss, Actor.=


[Sidenote: =12s. 6d. Net.=]

     =Campbell (James Dykes) Coleridge’s Poems.= Large paper.

     =Morison (M.) Time Table of Modern History.=

     =Rait (Robert S.) Five Stuart Princesses.=

     =Round (J. Horace) The Commune of London.=


[Sidenote: =14s.=]

     =Anon. Regeneration.=

     =Constable’s Hand Atlas of India.=

     =Hake (A. E.) and Wesslau (O. E.) The Coming Individualism.=

     =Smith (Edward) England and America after Independence.=


[Sidenote: =15s.=]

     =Bain (R. Nisbet) The Daughter of Peter the Great.=

     =Spalding (T. A.) The Life and Times of Richard Badiley,
     Vice-Admiral of the Fleet.=

     =Wilkinson (Spenser) War and Policy.=


[Sidenote: =15s. Net.=]

     =Blount (Bertram) Practical Electro-Chemistry.=

     =Duff (C. M.) The Chronology of India.=

     =Pincott (F.) The Prema Sagara.=

     =Spenser (Edmund) The Faerie Queene.= 6 volumes. Canvas gilt.

     =Whiteway (R. S.) The Rise of Portuguese Power in India.=


[Sidenote: =16s.=]

     =Fox (Arthur W.) A Book of Bachelors.=

     =MacGeorge (G. W.) Ways and Works in India.=


[Sidenote: =16s. Net.=]

     =Sichel (Edith) Women and Men of the French Renaissance.=

     =Webb (W. W.) Coins of the Hindu States of Rajputana.=


[Sidenote: =17s. 6d. Net.=]

     =Thornton (Surgeon-General) Memories of Seven Campaigns.=


[Sidenote: =18s.=]

     =Anitchkow (Michael) War and Labour.=

     =Engelhardt (H.) A Russian Province of the North.=

     =Gribble (Francis) Lake Geneva, and its Literary Landmarks.=

     =Hewitt (J. F.) Ruling Races of Prehistoric Times.= First Series.

     =Stadling (J.) Through Siberia.= Edited by Dr. F. H. H. Guillemard.


[Sidenote: =18s. Net.=]

     =Boswell’s Life of Johnson.= Edited by A. Birrell, K.C. 6 vols.,
     fcap. 8vo, half leather.


[Sidenote: =20s.=]

     =Oppert (Gustav) The Original Inhabitants of India.=


[Sidenote: =21s.=]

     =Dale (T. F.) The Eighth Duke of Beaufort and the Badminton Hunt.=


[Sidenote: =21s. Net.=]

     =Bonavia (E.) The Evolution of Animals.=

     =Dale (T. F.) The History of the Belvoir Hunt.=

     =Gairdner (James) The Paston Letters.= 4 vols.

     =Legg (L. G. Wickham), and Hope (W. H. St. John) Inventories of
     Christchurch, Canterbury.=

     =Newberry (Percy E.) The Life of Rekhmara.=

     =Sapte (Brand) Memorials of Haileybury College.=

     =Vibart (Col. H. M.) Addiscombe.=


[Sidenote: =25s. Net.=]

     =Campbell (Lord Archibald) Highland Dress, Arms, and Ornament.=


[Sidenote: =30s. Net.=]

     =Rice (Louis) The Mysore Gazetteer.=


[Sidenote: =31s. 6d. Net.=]

     =Filippi (Dr.) The Ascent of Mount St. Elias.=

     =Legg (Wickham) English Coronation Records.=

     =Lewes (Vivian B.) Acetylene.=


[Sidenote: =32s.=]

     =Schweitzer (Georg) Emin Pasha: His Life and Work.=

     =Vallery-Radot (Rene) The Life of Pasteur.= 2 vols.


[Sidenote: =32s. Net.=]

     =Cole (Alan) Ornament in European Silks.=

     =Nisbet (John) Burma under British Rule.= 2 vols.


[Sidenote: =36s. Net.=]

     =Boswell’s Life of Johnson.= 6 vols. Limited Edition. Illustrated.


[Sidenote: =£2.=]

     =Oppert (Gustav) The Original Inhabitants of India.= Large paper.


[Sidenote: =£2 Net.=]

     =Garner, An English.= 8 vols. Cloth or Buckram.


[Sidenote: =£2 2s. Net.=]

     =Beaumont (Worby) Motor Vehicles and Motors.=

     =Granby (Marchioness of) Portraits of Men and Women.=

     =National Worthies.=

     =Rait (R. S.) Lusus Regius.=


[Sidenote: =£2 12s. 6d. Net.=]

     =Meredith (George) Nature Poems.=


[Sidenote: =£3 3s. Net.=]

     =Bright (E. B. and C.) Life of Sir Charles Tilston Bright.=

     =Filippi (Dr.) The Ascent of Mount St. Elias.= Edition de Luxe.

     =Mayo (J. H.) Medals and Decorations of the British Army and Navy.=

     =Stein (M. A.) Kalhana’s Rajatarangini.=


[Sidenote: =£3 12s. Net.=]

     =The Waverley Novels.= The Author’s Favourite Edition. Reprint, 48
     vols., fcap. 8vo. Cloth, paper label.


[Sidenote: =£4 16s. Net.=]

     =The Waverley Novels.= The Author’s Favourite Edition. Reprint, 48
     vols., fcap. 8vo. Cloth, gilt extra, gilt top.


[Sidenote: =£5 5s. Net.=]

     =Meredith (George) Nature Poems.= Large paper.

     =Travels of H.I.M. Czar Nicholas II. (when Cesarewitch) in the East.=
     2 vols.


[Sidenote: =£6 Net.=]

     =The Waverley Novels.= The Author’s Favourite Edition. Reprint, 48
     vols., fcap. 8vo. Half leather, gilt top.

     =W. H. St. John Hope. The Stall Plates of the Knights of the Order
     of the Garter, 1348-1485.=


[Sidenote: =£8 8s. Net.=]

     =Hyde (William) and Meynell (Alice) London Impressions.=


[Sidenote: =£26 5s.=]

     =Travels of H.I.M. Czar Nicholas II. (when Cesarewitch) in the East.=
     Large paper.

       *       *       *       *       *

                         THE WAVERLEY NOVELS.

           Facsimile Reprint of the Favourite Edition of SIR
              WALTER SCOTT. With all the Original Plates
                            and Vignettes.


     Red cloth, paper back title. Price 1s. 6d. per vol. net.

     Cloth gilt, gilt top. Price 2s. per vol. net.

     Quarter leather, gilt top. Price 2s. 6d. per vol. net.


  Vols. 1, 2.        =Waverley.=
  Vols. 3, 4.        =Guy Mannering.=
  Vols. 5, 6.        =The Antiquary.=
  Vols. 7, 8.        =Rob Roy.=
  Vol. 9.            =The Black Dwarf.=
  Vols. 10, 11.      =Old Mortality.=
  Vols. 12, 13.      =Heart of Midlothian.=
  Vol. 14.           =Bride of Lammermoor.=
  Vol. 15.           =Legend of Montrose.=
  Vols. 16, 17.      =Ivanhoe.=
  Vols. 18, 19.      =The Monastery.=
  Vols. 20, 21.      =The Abbot.=
  Vols. 22, 23.      =Kenilworth.=
  Vols. 24, 25.      =The Pirate.=
  Vols. 26, 27.      =Fortunes of Nigel.=
  Vols. 28, 29, 30.  =Peveril of the Peak.=
  Vols. 31, 32.      =Quentin Durward.=
  Vols. 33, 34.      =St. Ronan’s Well.=
  Vols. 35, 36.      =Redgauntlet.=
  Vol. 37.           =The Betrothed.=
  Vol. 38.           =The Talisman.=
  Vols. 39, 40.      =Woodstock.=
  Vol. 41.           =Highland Widow, etc.=
  Vols. 42, 43.      =Fair Maid of Perth.=
  Vols. 44, 45.      =Anne of Geierstein.=
  Vols. 46, 47.      =Count Robert of Paris.= =Castle Dangerous.=
  Vol. 48.           =The Surgeon’s Daughter.= =Glossary.=

Typographical errors corrected by the etext transcriber: natually desire
knowledge=> naturally desire knowledge {pg 19}

“ber Üdie Entstehung des Rechtsgefühls.”=> “Über die Entstehung des
Rechtsgefühls.” {pg 43}

is is obvious that Zeus=> it is obvious that Zeus {pg 106}





*** End of this LibraryBlog Digital Book "The Origin of the Knowledge of Right and Wrong" ***

Copyright 2023 LibraryBlog. All rights reserved.



Home