Home
  By Author [ A  B  C  D  E  F  G  H  I  J  K  L  M  N  O  P  Q  R  S  T  U  V  W  X  Y  Z |  Other Symbols ]
  By Title [ A  B  C  D  E  F  G  H  I  J  K  L  M  N  O  P  Q  R  S  T  U  V  W  X  Y  Z |  Other Symbols ]
  By Language
all Classics books content using ISYS

Download this book: [ ASCII | HTML | PDF ]

Look for this book on Amazon


We have new books nearly every day.
If you would like a news letter once a week or once a month
fill out this form and we will give you a summary of the books for that week or month by email.

Title: The Foundations of Science: Science and Hypothesis, The Value of Science, Science and Method
Author: Poincaré, Henri, 1854-1912
Language: English
As this book started as an ASCII text book there are no pictures available.


*** Start of this LibraryBlog Digital Book "The Foundations of Science: Science and Hypothesis, The Value of Science, Science and Method" ***


produced from scanned images of public domain material


  SCIENCE AND EDUCATION

  A SERIES OF VOLUMES FOR THE PROMOTION OF
  SCIENTIFIC RESEARCH AND EDUCATIONAL PROGRESS

  EDITED BY J. MCKEEN CATTELL


  VOLUME I--THE FOUNDATIONS OF SCIENCE



  UNDER THE SAME EDITORSHIP


    SCIENCE AND EDUCATION. A series of volumes for the promotion of
      scientific research and educational progress.

      Volume I. The Foundations of Science. By H. POINCARÉ. Containing
      the authorised English translation by George Bruce Halsted of
      "Science and Hypothesis," "The Value of Science," and "Science
      and Method."

      Volume II. Medical Research and Education. By Richard Mills
      Pearce, William H. Welch, W. H. Howell, Franklin P. Mall,
      Lewellys F. Barker, Charles S. Minot, W. B. Cannon, W. T.
      Councilman Theobald Smith, G. N. Stewart, C. M. Jackson,
      E. P. Lyon, James B. Herrick, John M. Dodson, C. R. Bardeen,
      W. Ophuls, S. J. Meltzer, James Ewing, W. W. Keen, Henry H.
      Donaldson, Christian A. Herter, and Henry P. Bowditch.

      Volume III. University Control. By J. MCKEEN CATTELL and other
      authors.

    AMERICAN MEN OF SCIENCE. A Biographical Directory.

    SCIENCE. A weekly journal devoted to the advancement of science.
      The official organ of the American Association for the
      Advancement of Science.

    THE POPULAR SCIENCE MONTHLY. A monthly magazine devoted to the
      diffusion of science.

    THE AMERICAN NATURALIST. A monthly journal devoted to the
      biological sciences, with special reference to the factors
      of evolution.

  THE SCIENCE PRESS

  NEW YORK      GARRISON, N. Y.



  THE FOUNDATIONS
  OF SCIENCE

  SCIENCE AND HYPOTHESIS
  THE VALUE OF SCIENCE
  SCIENCE AND METHOD


  BY
  H. POINCARÉ


  AUTHORIZED TRANSLATION BY
  GEORGE BRUCE HALSTED


  WITH A SPECIAL PREFACE BY POINCARÉ, AND AN INTRODUCTION
  BY JOSIAH ROYCE, HARVARD UNIVERSITY


  THE SCIENCE PRESS
  NEW YORK AND GARRISON, N. Y.
  1913



  Copyright, 1913
  BY THE SCIENCE PRESS


  PRESS OF
  THE NEW ERA PRINTING COMPANY
  LANCASTER, PA.



CONTENTS


                                                          PAGE
    Henri Poincaré                                          ix
    Author's Preface to the Translation                      3


SCIENCE AND HYPOTHESIS

    Introduction by Royce                                    9
    Introduction                                            27

  PART I. _Number and Magnitude_

    CHAPTER I.--On the Nature of Mathematical Reasoning     31
      Syllogistic Deduction                                 31
      Verification and Proof                                32
      Elements of Arithmetic                                33
      Reasoning by Recurrence                               37
      Induction                                             40
      Mathematical Construction                             41

    CHAPTER II.--Mathematical Magnitude and Experience      43
      Definition of Incommensurables                        44
      The Physical Continuum                                46
      Creation of the Mathematical Continuum                46
      Measurable Magnitude                                  49
      Various Remarks (Curves without Tangents)             50
      The Physical Continuum of Several Dimensions          52
      The Mathematical Continuum of Several Dimensions      53

  PART II. _Space_

    CHAPTER III.--The Non-Euclidean Geometries              55
      The Bolyai-Lobachevski Geometry                       56
      Riemann's Geometry                                    57
      The Surfaces of Constant Curvature                    58
      Interpretation of Non-Euclidean Geometries            59
      The Implicit Axioms                                   60
      The Fourth Geometry                                   62
      Lie's Theorem                                         62
      Riemann's Geometries                                  63
      On the Nature of Axioms                               63

    CHAPTER IV.--Space and Geometry                         66
      Geometric Space and Perceptual Space                  66
      Visual Space                                          67
      Tactile Space and Motor Space                         68
      Characteristics of Perceptual Space                   69
      Change of State and Change of Position                70
      Conditions of Compensation                            72
      Solid Bodies and Geometry                             72
      Law of Homogeneity                                    74
      The Non-Euclidean World                               75
      The World of Four Dimensions                          78
      Conclusions                                           79

    CHAPTER V.--Experience and Geometry                     81
      Geometry and Astronomy                                81
      The Law of Relativity                                 83
      Bearing of Experiments                                86
      Supplement (What is a Point?)                         89
      Ancestral Experience                                  91

  PART III. _Force_

    CHAPTER VI.--The Classic Mechanics                      92
      The Principle of Inertia                              93
      The Law of Acceleration                               97
      Anthropomorphic Mechanics                            103
      The School of the Thread                             104

    CHAPTER VII.--Relative Motion and Absolute Motion      107
      The Principle of Relative Motion                     107
      Newton's Argument                                    108

    CHAPTER VIII.--Energy and Thermodynamics               115
      Energetics                                           115
      Thermodynamics                                       119
      General Conclusions on Part III                      123

  PART IV. _Nature_

    CHAPTER IX.--Hypotheses in Physics                     127
      The Rôle of Experiment and Generalization            127
      The Unity of Nature                                  130
      The Rôle of Hypothesis                               133
      Origin of Mathematical Physics                       136

    CHAPTER X.--The Theories of Modern Physics             140
      Meaning of Physical Theories                         140
      Physics and Mechanism                                144
      Present State of the Science                         148

    CHAPTER XI.--The Calculus of Probabilities             155
      Classification of the Problems of Probability        158
      Probability in Mathematics                           161
      Probability in the Physical Sciences                 164
      Rouge et noir                                        167
      The Probability of Causes                            169
      The Theory of Errors                                 170
      Conclusions                                          172

    CHAPTER XII.--Optics and Electricity                   174
      Fresnel's Theory                                     174
      Maxwell's Theory                                     175
      The Mechanical Explanation of Physical Phenomena     177

    CHAPTER XIII.--Electrodynamics                         184
      Ampère's Theory                                      184
      Closed Currents                                      185
      Action of a Closed Current on a Portion of Current   186
      Continuous Rotations                                 187
      Mutual Action of Two Open Currents                   189
      Induction                                            190
      Theory of Helmholtz                                  191
      Difficulties Raised by these Theories                193
      Maxwell's Theory                                     193
      Rowland's Experiment                                 194
      The Theory of Lorentz                                196


THE VALUE OF SCIENCE

    Translator's Introduction                              201
    Does the Scientist Create Science?                     201
    The Mind Dispelling Optical Illusions                  202
    Euclid not Necessary                                   202
    Without Hypotheses, no Science                         203
    What Outcome?                                          203
    Introduction                                           205

  PART I. _The Mathematical Sciences_

    CHAPTER I.--Intuition and Logic in Mathematics         210

    CHAPTER II.--The Measure of Time                       223

    CHAPTER III.--The Notion of Space                      235
      Qualitative Geometry                                 238
      The Physical Continuum of Several Dimensions         240
      The Notion of Point                                  244
      The Notion of Displacement                           247
      Visual Space                                         252

    CHAPTER IV.--Space and its Three Dimensions            256
      The Group of Displacements                           256
      Identity of Two Points                               259
      Tactile Space                                        264
      Identity of the Different Spaces                     268
      Space and Empiricism                                 271
      Rôle of the Semicircular Canals                      276

  PART II. _The Physical Sciences_

    CHAPTER V.--Analysis and Physics                       279

    CHAPTER VI.--Astronomy                                 289

    CHAPTER VII.--The History of Mathematical Physics      297
      The Physics of Central Forces                        297
      The Physics of the Principles                        299

    CHAPTER VIII.--The Present Crisis in Physics           303
      The New Crisis                                       303
      Carnot's Principle                                   303
      The Principle of Relativity                          305
      Newton's Principle                                   308
      Lavoisier's Principle                                310
      Mayer's Principle                                    312

    CHAPTER IX.--The Future of Mathematical Physics        314
      The Principles and Experiment                        314
      The Rôle of the Analyst                              314
      Aberration and Astronomy                             315
      Electrons and Spectra                                316
      Conventions preceding Experiment                     317
      Future Mathematical Physics                          319

  PART III. _The Objective Value of Science_

    CHAPTER X.--Is Science Artificial?                     321
      The Philosophy of LeRoy                              321
      Science, Rule of Action                              323
      The Crude Fact and the Scientific Fact               325
      Nominalism and the Universal Invariant               333

    CHAPTER XI.--Science and Reality                       340
      Contingence and Determinism                          340
      Objectivity of Science                               347
      The Rotation of the Earth                            353
      Science for Its Own Sake                             354


SCIENCE AND METHOD

    Introduction                                           359

  BOOK I. _Science and the Scientist_

    CHAPTER I.--The Choice of Facts                        362

    CHAPTER II.--The Future of Mathematics                 369

    CHAPTER III.--Mathematical Creation                    383

    CHAPTER IV.--Chance                                    395

  BOOK II. _Mathematical Reasoning_

    CHAPTER I.--The Relativity of Space                    413

    CHAPTER II.--Mathematical Definitions and Teaching     430

    CHAPTER III.--Mathematics and Logic                    448

    CHAPTER IV.--The New Logics                            460

    CHAPTER V.--The Latest Efforts of the Logisticians     472

  BOOK III. _The New Mechanics_

    CHAPTER I.--Mechanics and Radium                       486

    CHAPTER II.--Mechanics and Optics                      496

    CHAPTER III.--The New Mechanics and Astronomy          512

  BOOK IV. _Astronomic Science_

    CHAPTER I.--The Milky Way and the Theory of Gases      523

    CHAPTER II.--French Geodesy                            535

    General Conclusions                                    544

    Index                                                  547



HENRI POINCARÉ


SIR GEORGE DARWIN, worthy son of an immortal father, said, referring to
what Poincaré was to him and to his work: "He must be regarded as the
presiding genius--or, shall I say, my patron saint?"

Henri Poincaré was born April 29, 1854, at Nancy, where his father was a
physician highly respected. His schooling was broken into by the war of
1870-71, to get news of which he learned to read the German newspapers.
He outclassed the other boys of his age in all subjects and in 1873
passed highest into the École Polytechnique, where, like John Bolyai at
Maros Vásárhely, he followed the courses in mathematics without taking a
note and without the syllabus. He proceeded in 1875 to the School of
Mines, and was _Nommé_, March 26, 1879. But he won his doctorate in the
University of Paris, August 1, 1879, and was appointed to teach in the
Faculté des Sciences de Caen, December 1, 1879, whence he was quickly
called to the University of Paris, teaching there from October 21, 1881,
until his death, July 17, 1912. So it is an error to say he started as
an engineer. At the early age of thirty-two he became a member of
l'Académie des Sciences, and, March 5, 1908, was chosen Membre de
l'Académie Française. July 1, 1909, the number of his writings was 436.

His earliest publication was in 1878, and was not important. Afterward
came an essay submitted in competition for the Grand Prix offered in
1880, but it did not win. Suddenly there came a change, a striking fire,
a bursting forth, in February, 1881, and Poincaré tells us the very
minute it happened. Mounting an omnibus, "at the moment when I put my
foot upon the step, the idea came to me, without anything in my previous
thoughts seeming to foreshadow it, that the transformations I had used
to define the Fuchsian functions were identical with those of
non-Euclidean geometry." Thereby was opened a perspective new and
immense. Moreover, the magic wand of his whole life-work had been
grasped, the Aladdin's lamp had been rubbed, non-Euclidean geometry,
whose necromancy was to open up a new theory of our universe, whose
brilliant exposition was commenced in his book _Science and Hypothesis_,
which has been translated into six languages and has already had a
circulation of over 20,000. The non-Euclidean notion is that of the
possibility of alternative laws of nature, which in the Introduction to
the _Électricité et Optique_, 1901, is thus put: "If therefore a
phenomenon admits of a complete mechanical explanation, it will admit of
an infinity of Others which will account equally well for all the
peculiarities disclosed by experiment."

The scheme of laws of nature so largely due to Newton is merely one of
an infinite number of conceivable rational schemes for helping us master
and make experience; it is _commode_, convenient; but perhaps another
may be vastly more advantageous. The old conception of _true_ has been
revised. The first expression of the new idea occurs on the title page
of John Bolyai's marvelous _Science Absolute of Space_, in the phrase
"haud unquam a priori decidenda."

With bearing on the history of the earth and moon system and the origin
of double stars, in formulating the geometric criterion of stability,
Poincaré proved the existence of a previously unknown pear-shaped
figure, with the possibility that the progressive deformation of this
figure with increasing angular velocity might result in the breaking up
of the rotating body into two detached masses. Of his treatise _Les
Méthodes nouvelles de la Méchanique céleste_, Sir George Darwin says:
"It is probable that for half a century to come it will be the mine from
which humbler investigators will excavate their materials." Brilliant
was his appreciation of Poincaré in presenting the gold medal of the
Royal Astronomical Society. The three others most akin in genius are
linked with him by the Sylvester medal of the Royal Society, the
Lobachevski medal of the Physico-Mathematical Society of Kazan, and the
Bolyai prize of the Hungarian Academy of Sciences. His work must be
reckoned with the greatest mathematical achievements of mankind.

The kernel of Poincaré's power lies in an oracle Sylvester often quoted
to me as from Hesiod: The whole is less than its part.

He penetrates at once the divine simplicity of the perfectly general
case, and thence descends, as from Olympus, to the special concrete
earthly particulars.

A combination of seemingly extremely simple analytic and geometric
concepts gave necessary general conclusions of immense scope from which
sprang a disconcerting wilderness of possible deductions. And so he
leaves a noble, fruitful heritage.

Says Love: "His right is recognized now, and it is not likely that
future generations will revise the judgment, to rank among the greatest
mathematicians of all time."

  GEORGE BRUCE HALSTED.


       *       *       *       *       *



SCIENCE AND HYPOTHESIS



       *       *       *       *       *



AUTHOR'S PREFACE TO THE TRANSLATION


I am exceedingly grateful to Dr. Halsted, who has been so good as to
present my book to American readers in a translation, clear and
faithful.

Every one knows that this savant has already taken the trouble to
translate many European treatises and thus has powerfully contributed to
make the new continent understand the thought of the old.

Some people love to repeat that Anglo-Saxons have not the same way of
thinking as the Latins or as the Germans; that they have quite another
way of understanding mathematics or of understanding physics; that this
way seems to them superior to all others; that they feel no need of
changing it, nor even of knowing the ways of other peoples.

In that they would beyond question be wrong, but I do not believe that
is true, or, at least, that is true no longer. For some time the English
and Americans have been devoting themselves much more than formerly to
the better understanding of what is thought and said on the continent of
Europe.

To be sure, each people will preserve its characteristic genius, and it
would be a pity if it were otherwise, supposing such a thing possible.
If the Anglo-Saxons wished to become Latins, they would never be more
than bad Latins; just as the French, in seeking to imitate them, could
turn out only pretty poor Anglo-Saxons.

And then the English and Americans have made scientific conquests they
alone could have made; they will make still more of which others would
be incapable. It would therefore be deplorable if there were no longer
Anglo-Saxons.

But continentals have on their part done things an Englishman could not
have done, so that there is no need either for wishing all the world
Anglo-Saxon.

Each has his characteristic aptitudes, and these aptitudes should be
diverse, else would the scientific concert resemble a quartet where
every one wanted to play the violin.

And yet it is not bad for the violin to know what the violon-cello is
playing, and _vice versa_.

This it is that the English and Americans are comprehending more and
more; and from this point of view the translations undertaken by Dr.
Halsted are most opportune and timely.

Consider first what concerns the mathematical sciences. It is frequently
said the English cultivate them only in view of their applications and
even that they despise those who have other aims; that speculations too
abstract repel them as savoring of metaphysic.

The English, even in mathematics, are to proceed always from the
particular to the general, so that they would never have an idea of
entering mathematics, as do many Germans, by the gate of the theory of
aggregates. They are always to hold, so to speak, one foot in the world
of the senses, and never burn the bridges keeping them in communication
with reality. They thus are to be incapable of comprehending or at least
of appreciating certain theories more interesting than utilitarian, such
as the non-Euclidean geometries. According to that, the first two parts
of this book, on number and space, should seem to them void of all
substance and would only baffle them.

But that is not true. And first of all, are they such uncompromising
realists as has been said? Are they absolutely refractory, I do not say
to metaphysic, but at least to everything metaphysical?

Recall the name of Berkeley, born in Ireland doubtless, but immediately
adopted by the English, who marked a natural and necessary stage in the
development of English philosophy.

Is this not enough to show they are capable of making ascensions
otherwise than in a captive balloon?

And to return to America, is not the _Monist_ published at Chicago, that
review which even to us seems bold and yet which finds readers?

And in mathematics? Do you think American geometers are concerned only
about applications? Far from it. The part of the science they cultivate
most devotedly is the theory of groups of substitutions, and under its
most abstract form, the farthest removed from the practical.

Moreover, Dr. Halsted gives regularly each year a review of all
productions relative to the non-Euclidean geometry, and he has about him
a public deeply interested in his work. He has initiated this public
into the ideas of Hilbert, and he has even written an elementary
treatise on 'Rational Geometry,' based on the principles of the renowned
German savant.

To introduce this principle into teaching is surely this time to burn
all bridges of reliance upon sensory intuition, and this is, I confess,
a boldness which seems to me almost rashness.

The American public is therefore much better prepared than has been
thought for investigating the origin of the notion of space.

Moreover, to analyze this concept is not to sacrifice reality to I know
not what phantom. The geometric language is after all only a language.
Space is only a word that we have believed a thing. What is the origin
of this word and of other words also? What things do they hide? To ask
this is permissible; to forbid it would be, on the contrary, to be a
dupe of words; it would be to adore a metaphysical idol, like savage
peoples who prostrate themselves before a statue of wood without daring
to take a look at what is within.

In the study of nature, the contrast between the Anglo-Saxon spirit and
the Latin spirit is still greater.

The Latins seek in general to put their thought in mathematical form;
the English prefer to express it by a material representation.

Both doubtless rely only on experience for knowing the world; when they
happen to go beyond this, they consider their foreknowledge as only
provisional, and they hasten to ask its definitive confirmation from
nature herself.

But experience is not all, and the savant is not passive; he does not
wait for the truth to come and find him, or for a chance meeting to
bring him face to face with it. He must go to meet it, and it is for his
thinking to reveal to him the way leading thither. For that there is
need of an instrument; well, just there begins the difference--the
instrument the Latins ordinarily choose is not that preferred by the
Anglo-Saxons.

For a Latin, truth can be expressed only by equations; it must obey laws
simple, logical, symmetric and fitted to satisfy minds in love with
mathematical elegance.

The Anglo-Saxon to depict a phenomenon will first be engrossed in making
a _model_, and he will make it with common materials, such as our crude,
unaided senses show us them. He also makes a hypothesis, he assumes
implicitly that nature, in her finest elements, is the same as in the
complicated aggregates which alone are within the reach of our senses.
He concludes from the body to the atom.

Both therefore make hypotheses, and this indeed is necessary, since no
scientist has ever been able to get on without them. The essential thing
is never to make them unconsciously.

From this point of view again, it would be well for these two sorts of
physicists to know something of each other; in studying the work of
minds so unlike their own, they will immediately recognize that in this
work there has been an accumulation of hypotheses.

Doubtless this will not suffice to make them comprehend that they on
their part have made just as many; each sees the mote without seeing the
beam; but by their criticisms they will warn their rivals, and it may be
supposed these will not fail to render them the same service.

The English procedure often seems to us crude, the analogies they think
they discover to us seem at times superficial; they are not sufficiently
interlocked, not precise enough; they sometimes permit incoherences,
contradictions in terms, which shock a geometric spirit and which the
employment of the mathematical method would immediately have put in
evidence. But most often it is, on the other hand, very fortunate that
they have not perceived these contradictions; else would they have
rejected their model and could not have deduced from it the brilliant
results they have often made to come out of it.

And then these very contradictions, when they end by perceiving them,
have the advantage of showing them the hypothetical character of their
conceptions, whereas the mathematical method, by its apparent rigor and
inflexible course, often inspires in us a confidence nothing warrants,
and prevents our looking about us.

From another point of view, however, the two conceptions are very
unlike, and if all must be said, they are very unlike because of a
common fault.

The English wish to make the world out of what we see. I mean what we
see with the unaided eye, not the microscope, nor that still more
subtile microscope, the human head guided by scientific induction.

The Latin wants to make it out of formulas, but these formulas are still
the quintessenced expression of what we see. In a word, both would make
the unknown out of the known, and their excuse is that there is no way
of doing otherwise.

And yet is this legitimate, if the unknown be the simple and the known
the complex?

Shall we not get of the simple a false idea, if we think it like the
complex, or worse yet if we strive to make it out of elements which are
themselves compounds?

Is not each great advance accomplished precisely the day some one has
discovered under the complex aggregate shown by our senses something far
more simple, not even resembling it--as when Newton replaced Kepler's
three laws by the single law of gravitation, which was something
simpler, equivalent, yet unlike?

One is justified in asking if we are not on the eve of just such a
revolution or one even more important. Matter seems on the point of
losing its mass, its solidest attribute, and resolving itself into
electrons. Mechanics must then give place to a broader conception which
will explain it, but which it will not explain.

So it was in vain the attempt was made in England to construct the ether
by material models, or in France to apply to it the laws of dynamic.

The ether it is, the unknown, which explains matter, the known; matter
is incapable of explaining the ether.

  POINCARÉ.



INTRODUCTION

BY PROFESSOR JOSIAH ROYCE

HARVARD UNIVERSITY


The treatise of a master needs no commendation through the words of a
mere learner. But, since my friend and former fellow student, the
translator of this volume, has joined with another of my colleagues,
Professor Cattell, in asking me to undertake the task of calling the
attention of my fellow students to the importance and to the scope of M.
Poincaré's volume, I accept the office, not as one competent to pass
judgment upon the book, but simply as a learner, desirous to increase
the number of those amongst us who are already interested in the type of
researches to which M. Poincaré has so notably contributed.


I

The branches of inquiry collectively known as the Philosophy of Science
have undergone great changes since the appearance of Herbert Spencer's
_First Principles_, that volume which a large part of the general public
in this country used to regard as the representative compend of all
modern wisdom relating to the foundations of scientific knowledge. The
summary which M. Poincaré gives, at the outset of his own introduction
to the present work, where he states the view which the 'superficial
observer' takes of scientific truth, suggests, not indeed Spencer's own
most characteristic theories, but something of the spirit in which many
disciples of Spencer interpreting their master's formulas used to
conceive the position which science occupies in dealing with experience.
It was well known to them, indeed, that experience is a constant guide,
and an inexhaustible source both of novel scientific results and of
unsolved problems; but the fundamental Spencerian principles of science,
such as 'the persistence of force,' the 'rhythm of motion' and the rest,
were treated by Spencer himself as demonstrably objective, although
indeed 'relative' truths, capable of being tested once for all by the
'inconceivability of the opposite,' and certain to hold true for the
whole 'knowable' universe. Thus, whether one dwelt upon the results of
such a mathematical procedure as that to which M. Poincaré refers in his
opening paragraphs, or whether, like Spencer himself, one applied the
'first principles' to regions of less exact science, this confidence
that a certain orthodoxy regarding the principles of science was
established forever was characteristic of the followers of the movement
in question. Experience, lighted up by reason, seemed to them to have
predetermined for all future time certain great theoretical results
regarding the real constitution of the 'knowable' cosmos. Whoever
doubted this doubted 'the verdict of science.'

Some of us well remember how, when Stallo's 'Principles and Theories of
Modern Physics' first appeared, this sense of scientific orthodoxy was
shocked amongst many of our American readers and teachers of science. I
myself can recall to mind some highly authoritative reviews of that work
in which the author was more or less sharply taken to task for his
ignorant presumption in speaking with the freedom that he there used
regarding such sacred possessions of humanity as the fundamental
concepts of physics. That very book, however, has quite lately been
translated into German as a valuable contribution to some of the most
recent efforts to reconstitute a modern 'philosophy of nature.' And
whatever may be otherwise thought of Stallo's critical methods, or of
his results, there can be no doubt that, at the present moment, if his
book were to appear for the first time, nobody would attempt to
discredit the work merely on account of its disposition to be agnostic
regarding the objective reality of the concepts of the kinetic theory of
gases, or on account of its call for a logical rearrangement of the
fundamental concepts of the theory of energy. We are no longer able so
easily to know heretics at first sight.

For we now appear to stand in this position: The control of natural
phenomena, which through the sciences men have attained, grows daily
vaster and more detailed, and in its details more assured. Phenomena men
know and predict better than ever. But regarding the most general
theories, and the most fundamental, of science, there is no longer any
notable scientific orthodoxy. Thus, as knowledge grows firmer and wider,
conceptual construction becomes less rigid. The field of the theoretical
philosophy of nature--yes, the field of the logic of science--this whole
region is to-day an open one. Whoever will work there must indeed accept
the verdict of experience regarding what happens in the natural world.
So far he is indeed bound. But he may undertake without hindrance from
mere tradition the task of trying afresh to reduce what happens to
conceptual unity. The circle-squarers and the inventors of devices for
perpetual motion are indeed still as unwelcome in scientific company as
they were in the days when scientific orthodoxy was more rigidly
defined; but that is not because the foundations of geometry are now
viewed as completely settled, beyond controversy, nor yet because the
'persistence of force' has been finally so defined as to make the
'opposite inconceivable' and the doctrine of energy beyond the reach of
novel formulations. No, the circle-squarers and the inventors of devices
for perpetual motion are to-day discredited, not because of any
unorthodoxy of their general philosophy of nature, but because their
views regarding special facts and processes stand in conflict with
certain equally special results of science which themselves admit of
very various general theoretical interpretations. Certain properties of
the irrational number [pi] are known, in sufficient multitude to justify
the mathematician in declining to listen to the arguments of the
circle-squarer; but, despite great advances, and despite the assured
results of Dedekind, of Cantor, of Weierstrass and of various others,
the general theory of the logic of the numbers, rational and irrational,
still presents several important features of great obscurity; and the
philosophy of the concepts of geometry yet remains, in several very
notable respects, unconquered territory, despite the work of Hilbert and
of Pieri, and of our author himself. The ordinary inventors of the
perpetual motion machines still stand in conflict with accepted
generalizations; but nobody knows as yet what the final form of the
theory of energy will be, nor can any one say precisely what place the
phenomena of the radioactive bodies will occupy in that theory. The
alchemists would not be welcome workers in modern laboratories; yet
some sorts of transformation and of evolution of the elements are to-day
matters which theory can find it convenient, upon occasion, to treat as
more or less exactly definable possibilities; while some newly observed
phenomena tend to indicate, not indeed that the ancient hopes of the
alchemists were well founded, but that the ultimate constitution of
matter is something more fluent, less invariant, than the theoretical
orthodoxy of a recent period supposed. Again, regarding the foundations
of biology, a theoretical orthodoxy grows less possible, less definable,
less conceivable (even as a hope) the more knowledge advances. Once
'mechanism' and 'vitalism' were mutually contradictory theories
regarding the ultimate constitution of living bodies. Now they are
obviously becoming more and more 'points of view,' diverse but not
necessarily conflicting. So far as you find it convenient to limit your
study of vital processes to those phenomena which distinguish living
matter from all other natural objects, you may assume, in the modern
'pragmatic' sense, the attitude of a 'neo-vitalist.' So far, however, as
you are able to lay stress, with good results, upon the many ways in
which the life processes can be assimilated to those studied in physics
and in chemistry, you work as if you were a partisan of 'mechanics.' In
any case, your special science prospers by reason of the empirical
discoveries that you make. And your theories, whatever they are, must
not run counter to any positive empirical results. But otherwise,
scientific orthodoxy no longer predetermines what alone it is
respectable for you to think about the nature of living substance.

This gain in the freedom of theory, coming, as it does, side by side
with a constant increase of a positive knowledge of nature, lends itself
to various interpretations, and raises various obvious questions.


II

One of the most natural of these interpretations, one of the most
obvious of these questions, may be readily stated. Is not the lesson of
all these recent discussions simply this, that general theories are
simply vain, that a philosophy of nature is an idle dream, and that the
results of science are coextensive with the range of actual empirical
observation and of successful prediction? If this is indeed the lesson,
then the decline of theoretical orthodoxy in science is--like the
eclipse of dogma in religion--merely a further lesson in pure
positivism, another proof that man does best when he limits himself to
thinking about what can be found in human experience, and in trying to
plan what can be done to make human life more controllable and more
reasonable. What we are free to do as we please--is it any longer a
serious business? What we are free to think as we please--is it of any
further interest to one who is in search of truth? If certain general
theories are mere conceptual constructions, which to-day are, and
to-morrow are cast into the oven, why dignify them by the name of
philosophy? Has science any place for such theories? Why be a
'neo-vitalist,' or an 'evolutionist,' or an 'atomist,' or an
'Energetiker'? Why not say, plainly: "Such and such phenomena, thus and
thus described, have been observed; such and such experiences are to be
expected, since the hypotheses by the terms of which we are required to
expect them have been verified too often to let us regard the agreement
with experience as due merely to chance; so much then with reasonable
assurance we know; all else is silence--or else is some matter to be
tested by another experiment?" Why not limit our philosophy of science
strictly to such a counsel of resignation? Why not substitute, for the
old scientific orthodoxy, simply a confession of ignorance, and a
resolution to devote ourselves to the business of enlarging the bounds
of actual empirical knowledge?

Such comments upon the situation just characterized are frequently made.
Unfortunately, they seem not to content the very age whose revolt from
the orthodoxy of traditional theory, whose uncertainty about all
theoretical formulations, and whose vast wealth of empirical discoveries
and of rapidly advancing special researches, would seem most to justify
these very comments. Never has there been better reason than there is
to-day to be content, if rational man could be content, with a pure
positivism. The splendid triumphs of special research in the most
various fields, the constant increase in our practical control over
nature--these, our positive and growing possessions, stand in glaring
contrast to the failure of the scientific orthodoxy of a former period
to fix the outlines of an ultimate creed about the nature of the
knowable universe. Why not 'take the cash and let the credit go'? Why
pursue the elusive theoretical 'unification' any further, when what we
daily get from our sciences is an increasing wealth of detailed
information and of practical guidance?

As a fact, however, the known answer of our own age to these very
obvious comments is a constant multiplication of new efforts towards
large and unifying theories. If theoretical orthodoxy is no longer
clearly definable, theoretical construction was never more rife. The
history of the doctrine of evolution, even in its most recent phases,
when the theoretical uncertainties regarding the 'factors of evolution'
are most insisted upon, is full of illustrations of this remarkable
union of scepticism in critical work with courage regarding the use of
the scientific imagination. The history of those controversies regarding
theoretical physics, some of whose principal phases M. Poincaré, in his
book, sketches with the hand of the master, is another illustration of
the consciousness of the time. Men have their freedom of thought in
these regions; and they feel the need of making constant and
constructive use of this freedom. And the men who most feel this need
are by no means in the majority of cases professional metaphysicians--or
students who, like myself, have to view all these controversies amongst
the scientific theoreticians from without as learners. These large
theoretical constructions are due, on the contrary, in a great many
cases to special workers, who have been driven to the freedom of
philosophy by the oppression of experience, and who have learned in the
conflict with special problems the lesson that they now teach in the
form of general ideas regarding the philosophical aspects of science.

Why, then, does science actually need general theories, despite the fact
that these theories inevitably alter and pass away? What is the service
of a philosophy of science, when it is certain that the philosophy of
science which is best suited to the needs of one generation must be
superseded by the advancing insight of the next generation? Why must
that which endlessly grows, namely, man's knowledge of the phenomenal
order of nature, be constantly united in men's minds with that which is
certain to decay, namely, the theoretical formulation of special
knowledge in more or less completely unified systems of doctrine?

I understand our author's volume to be in the main an answer to this
question. To be sure, the compact and manifold teachings which this text
contains relate to a great many different special issues. A student
interested in the problems of the philosophy of mathematics, or in the
theory of probabilities, or in the nature and office of mathematical
physics, or in still other problems belonging to the wide field here
discussed, may find what he wants here and there in the text, even in
case the general issues which give the volume its unity mean little to
him, or even if he differs from the author's views regarding the
principal issues of the book. But in the main, this volume must be
regarded as what its title indicates--a critique of the nature and place
of hypothesis in the work of science and a study of the logical
relations of theory and fact. The result of the book is a substantial
justification of the scientific utility of theoretical construction--an
abandonment of dogma, but a vindication of the rights of the
constructive reason.


III

The most notable of the results of our author's investigation of the
logic of scientific theories relates, as I understand his work, to a
topic which the present state of logical investigation, just summarized,
makes especially important, but which has thus far been very
inadequately treated in the text-books of inductive logic. The useful
hypotheses of science are of two kinds:

1. The hypotheses which are valuable _precisely_ because they are either
verifiable or else refutable through a definite appeal to the tests
furnished by experience; and

2. The hypotheses which, despite the fact that experience suggests them,
are valuable _despite_, or even _because_, of the fact that experience
can _neither_ confirm nor refute them. The contrast between these two
kinds of hypotheses is a prominent topic of our author's discussion.

Hypotheses of the general type which I have here placed first in order
are the ones which the text-books of inductive logic and those summaries
of scientific method which are customary in the course of the elementary
treatises upon physical science are already accustomed to recognize and
to characterize. The value of such hypotheses is indeed undoubted. But
hypotheses of the type which I have here named in the second place are
far less frequently recognized in a perfectly explicit way as useful
aids in the work of special science. One usually either fails to admit
their presence in scientific work, or else remains silent as to the
reasons of their usefulness. Our author's treatment of the work of
science is therefore especially marked by the fact that he explicitly
makes prominent both the existence and the scientific importance of
hypotheses of this second type. They occupy in his discussion a place
somewhat analogous to each of the two distinct positions occupied by the
'categories' and the 'forms of sensibility,' on the one hand, and by the
'regulative principles of the reason,' on the other hand, in the Kantian
theory of our knowledge of nature. That is, these hypotheses which can
neither be confirmed nor refuted by experience appear, in M. Poincaré's
account, partly (like the conception of 'continuous quantity') as
devices of the understanding whereby we give conceptual unity and an
invisible connectedness to certain types of phenomenal facts which come
to us in a discrete form and in a confused variety; and partly (like the
larger organizing concepts of science) as principles regarding the
structure of the world in its wholeness; _i. e._, as principles in the
light of which we try to interpret our experience, so as to give to it a
totality and an inclusive unity such as Euclidean space, or such as the
world of the theory of energy is conceived to possess. Thus viewed, M.
Poincaré's logical theory of this second class of hypotheses undertakes
to accomplish, with modern means and in the light of to-day's issues, a
part of what Kant endeavored to accomplish in his theory of scientific
knowledge with the limited means which were at his disposal. Those
aspects of science which are determined by the use of the hypotheses of
this second kind appear in our author's account as constituting an
essential human way of viewing nature, an interpretation rather than a
portrayal or a prediction of the objective facts of nature, an
adjustment of our conceptions of things to the internal needs of our
intelligence, rather than a grasping of things as they are in
themselves.

To be sure, M. Poincaré's view, in this portion of his work, obviously
differs, meanwhile, from that of Kant, as well as this agrees, in a
measure, with the spirit of the Kantian epistemology. I do not mean
therefore to class our author as a Kantian. For Kant, the
interpretations imposed by the 'forms of sensibility,' and by the
'categories of the understanding,' upon our doctrine of nature are
rigidly predetermined by the unalterable 'form' of our intellectual
powers. We 'must' thus view facts, whatever the data of sense must be.
This, of course, is not M. Poincaré's view. A similarly rigid
predetermination also limits the Kantian 'ideas of the reason' to a
certain set of principles whose guidance of the course of our
theoretical investigations is indeed only 'regulative,' but is 'a
priori,' and so unchangeable. For M. Poincaré, on the contrary, all this
adjustment of our interpretations of experience to the needs of our
intellect is something far less rigid and unalterable, and is constantly
subject to the suggestions of experience. We must indeed interpret in
our own way; but our way is itself only relatively determinate; it is
essentially more or less plastic; other interpretations of experience
are conceivable. Those that we use are merely the ones found to be most
convenient. But this convenience is not absolute necessity. Unverifiable
and irrefutable hypotheses in science are indeed, in general,
indispensable aids to the organization and to the guidance of our
interpretation of experience. But it is experience itself which points
out to us what lines of interpretation will prove most convenient.
Instead of Kant's rigid list of _a priori_ 'forms,' we consequently have
in M. Poincaré's account a set of conventions, neither wholly subjective
and arbitrary, nor yet imposed upon us unambiguously by the external
compulsion of experience. The organization of science, so far as this
organization is due to hypotheses of the kind here in question, thus
resembles that of a constitutional government--neither absolutely
necessary, nor yet determined apart from the will of the subjects, nor
yet accidental--a free, yet not a capricious establishment of good
order, in conformity with empirical needs.

Characteristic remains, however, for our author, as, in his decidedly
contrasting way, for Kant, the thought that _without principles which at
every stage transcend precise confirmation through such experience as is
then accessible the organization of experience is impossible_. Whether
one views these principles as conventions or as _a priori_ 'forms,' they
may therefore be described as hypotheses, but as hypotheses that, while
lying at the basis of our actual physical sciences, at once refer to
experience and help us in dealing with experience, and are yet neither
confirmed nor refuted by the experiences which we possess or which we
can hope to attain.

Three special instances or classes of instances, according to our
author's account, may be used as illustrations of this general type of
hypotheses. They are: (1) The hypothesis of the existence of continuous
extensive _quanta_ in nature; (2) The principles of geometry; (3) The
principles of mechanics and of the general theory of energy. In case of
each of these special types of hypotheses we are at first disposed,
apart from reflection, to say that we _find_ the world to be thus or
thus, so that, for instance, we can confirm the thesis according to
which nature contains continuous magnitudes; or can prove or disprove
the physical truth of the postulates of Euclidean geometry; or can
confirm by definite experience the objective validity of the principles
of mechanics. A closer examination reveals, according to our author, the
incorrectness of all such opinions. Hypotheses of these various special
types are needed; and their usefulness can be empirically shown. They
are in touch with experience; and that they are not merely arbitrary
conventions is also verifiable. They are not _a priori_ necessities; and
we can easily conceive intelligent beings whose experience could be best
interpreted without using these hypotheses. Yet these hypotheses are
_not_ subject to direct confirmation or refutation by experience. They
stand then in sharp contrast to the scientific hypotheses of the other,
and more frequently recognized, type, _i. e._, to the hypotheses which
can be tested by a definite appeal to experience. To these other
hypotheses our author attaches, of course, great importance. His
treatment of them is full of a living appreciation of the significance
of empirical investigation. But the central problem of the logic of
science thus becomes the problem of the relation between the two
fundamentally distinct types of hypotheses, _i. e._, between those which
can not be verified or refuted through experience, and those which can
be empirically tested.


IV

The detailed treatment which M. Poincaré gives to the problem thus
defined must be learned from his text. It is no part of my purpose to
expound, to defend or to traverse any of his special conclusions
regarding this matter. Yet I can not avoid observing that, while M.
Poincaré strictly confines his illustrations and his expressions of
opinion to those regions of science wherein, as special investigator, he
is himself most at home, the issues which he thus raises regarding the
logic of science are of even more critical importance and of more
impressive interest when one applies M. Poincaré's methods to the study
of the concepts and presuppositions of the organic and of the historical
and social sciences, than when one confines one's attention, as our
author here does, to the physical sciences. It belongs to the province
of an introduction like the present to point out, however briefly and
inadequately, that the significance of our author's ideas extends far
beyond the scope to which he chooses to confine their discussion.

The historical sciences, and in fact all those sciences such as geology,
and such as the evolutionary sciences in general, undertake theoretical
constructions which relate to past time. Hypotheses relating to the more
or less remote past stand, however, in a position which is very
interesting from the point of view of the logic of science. Directly
speaking, no such hypothesis is capable of confirmation or of
refutation, because we can not return into the past to verify by our own
experience what then happened. Yet indirectly, such hypotheses may lead
to predictions of coming experience. These latter will be subject to
control. Thus, Schliemann's confidence that the legend of Troy had a
definite historical foundation led to predictions regarding what certain
excavations would reveal. In a sense somewhat different from that which
filled Schliemann's enthusiastic mind, these predictions proved
verifiable. The result has been a considerable change in the attitude
of historians toward the legend of Troy. Geological investigation leads
to predictions regarding the order of the strata or the course of
mineral veins in a district, regarding the fossils which may be
discovered in given formations, and so on. These hypotheses are subject
to the control of experience. The various theories of evolutionary
doctrine include many hypotheses capable of confirmation and of
refutation by empirical tests. Yet, despite all such empirical control,
it still remains true that whenever a science is mainly concerned with
the remote past, whether this science be archeology, or geology, or
anthropology, or Old Testament history, the principal theoretical
constructions always include features which no appeal to present or to
accessible future experience can ever definitely test. Hence the
suspicion with which students of experimental science often regard the
theoretical constructions of their confrères of the sciences that deal
with the past. The origin of the races of men, of man himself, of life,
of species, of the planet; the hypotheses of anthropologists, of
archeologists, of students of 'higher criticism'--all these are matters
which the men of the laboratory often regard with a general incredulity
as belonging not at all to the domain of true science. Yet no one can
doubt the importance and the inevitableness of endeavoring to apply
scientific method to these regions also. Science needs theories
regarding the past history of the world. And no one who looks closer
into the methods of these sciences of past time can doubt that
verifiable and unverifiable hypotheses are in all these regions
inevitably interwoven; so that, while experience is always the guide,
the attitude of the investigator towards experience is determined by
interests which have to be partially due to what I should call that
'internal meaning,' that human interest in rational theoretical
construction which inspires the scientific inquiry; and the theoretical
constructions which prevail in such sciences are neither unbiased
reports of the actual constitution of an external reality, nor yet
arbitrary constructions of fancy. These constructions in fact resemble
in a measure those which M. Poincaré in this book has analyzed in the
case of geometry. They are constructions molded, but _not_ predetermined
in their details, by experience. We report facts; we let the facts
speak; but we, as we investigate, in the popular phrase, 'talk back' to
the facts. We interpret as well as report. Man is not merely made for
science, but science is made for man. It expresses his deepest
intellectual needs, as well as his careful observations. It is an effort
to bring internal meanings into harmony with external verifications. It
attempts therefore to control, as well as to submit, to conceive with
rational unity, as well as to accept data. Its arts are those directed
towards self-possession as well as towards an imitation of the outer
reality which we find. It seeks therefore a disciplined freedom of
thought. The discipline is as essential as the freedom; but the latter
has also its place. The theories of science are human, as well as
objective, internally rational, as well as (when that is possible)
subject to external tests.

In a field very different from that of the historical sciences, namely,
in a science of observation and of experiment, which is at the same time
an organic science, I have been led in the course of some study of the
history of certain researches to notice the existence of a theoretical
conception which has proved extremely fruitful in guiding research, but
which apparently resembles in a measure the type of hypotheses of which
M. Poincaré speaks when he characterizes the principles of mechanics and
of the theory of energy. I venture to call attention here to this
conception, which seems to me to illustrate M. Poincaré's view of the
functions of hypothesis in scientific work.

The modern science of pathology is usually regarded as dating from the
earlier researches of Virchow, whose 'Cellular Pathology' was the
outcome of a very careful and elaborate induction. Virchow, himself,
felt a strong aversion to mere speculation. He endeavored to keep close
to observation, and to relieve medical science from the control of
fantastic theories, such as those of the _Naturphilosophen_ had been.
Yet Virchow's researches were, as early as 1847, or still earlier,
already under the guidance of a theoretical presupposition which he
himself states as follows: "We have learned to recognize," he says,
"that diseases are not autonomous organisms, that they are no entities
that have entered into the body, that they are no parasites which take
root in the body, but _that they merely show us the course of the vital
processes under altered conditions_" ('dasz sie nur Ablauf der
Lebenserscheinungen unter veränderten Bedingungen darstellen').

The enormous importance of this theoretical presupposition for all the
early successes of modern pathological investigation is generally
recognized by the experts. I do not doubt this opinion. It appears to be
a commonplace of the history of this science. But in Virchow's later
years this very presupposition seemed to some of his contemporaries to
be called in question by the successes of recent bacteriology. The
question arose whether the theoretical foundations of Virchow's
pathology had not been set aside. And in fact the theory of the
parasitical origin of a vast number of diseased conditions has indeed
come upon an empirical basis to be generally recognized. Yet to the end
of his own career Virchow stoutly maintained that in all its essential
significance his own fundamental principle remained quite untouched by
the newer discoveries. And, as a fact, this view could indeed be
maintained. For if diseases proved to be the consequences of the
presence of parasites, the diseases themselves, so far as they belonged
to the diseased organism, were still not the parasites, but were, as
before, the reaction of the organism to the _veränderte Bedingungen_
which the presence of the parasites entailed. So Virchow could well
insist. And if the famous principle in question is only stated with
sufficient generality, it amounts simply to saying that if a disease
involves a change in an organism, and if this change is subject to law
at all, then the nature of the organism and the reaction of the organism
to whatever it is which causes the disease must be understood in case
the disease is to be understood.

For this very reason, however, Virchow's theoretical principle in its
most general form _could be neither confirmed nor refuted by
experience_. It would remain empirically irrefutable, so far as I can
see, even if we should learn that the devil was the true cause of all
diseases. For the devil himself would then simply predetermine the
_veränderte Bedingungen_ to which the diseased organism would be
reacting. Let bullets or bacteria, poisons or compressed air, or the
devil be the _Bedingungen_ to which a diseased organism reacts, the
postulate that Virchow states in the passage just quoted will remain
irrefutable, if only this postulate be interpreted to meet the case. For
the principle in question merely says that whatever entity it may be,
bullet, or poison, or devil, that affects the organism, the disease is
not that entity, but is the resulting alteration in the process of the
organism.

I insist, then, that this principle of Virchow's is no trial
supposition, no scientific hypothesis in the narrower sense--capable of
being submitted to precise empirical tests. It is, on the contrary, a
very precious _leading idea_, a theoretical interpretation of phenomena,
in the light of which observations are to be made--'a regulative
principle' of research. It is equivalent to a resolution to search for
those detailed connections which link the processes of disease to the
normal process of the organism. Such a search undertakes to find the
true unity, whatever that may prove to be, wherein the pathological and
the normal processes are linked. Now without some such leading idea, the
cellular pathology itself could never have been reached; because the
empirical facts in question would never have been observed. Hence this
principle of Virchow's was indispensable to the growth of his science.
Yet it was not a verifiable and not a refutable hypothesis. One value of
unverifiable and irrefutable hypotheses of this type lies, then, in the
sort of empirical inquiries which they initiate, inspire, organize and
guide. In these inquiries hypotheses in the narrower sense, that is,
trial propositions which are to be submitted to definite empirical
control, are indeed everywhere present. And the use of the other sort of
principles lies wholly in their application to experience. Yet without
what I have just proposed to call the 'leading ideas' of a science, that
is, its principles of an unverifiable and irrefutable character,
suggested, but not to be finally tested, by experience, the hypotheses
in the narrower sense would lack that guidance which, as M. Poincaré has
shown, the larger ideas of science give to empirical investigation.


V

I have dwelt, no doubt, at too great length upon one aspect only of our
author's varied and well-balanced discussion of the problems and
concepts of scientific theory. Of the hypotheses in the narrower sense
and of the value of direct empirical control, he has also spoken with
the authority and the originality which belong to his position. And in
dealing with the foundations of mathematics he has raised one or two
questions of great philosophical import into which I have no time, even
if I had the right, to enter here. In particular, in speaking of the
essence of mathematical reasoning, and of the difficult problem of what
makes possible novel results in the field of pure mathematics, M.
Poincaré defends a thesis regarding the office of 'demonstration by
recurrence'--a thesis which is indeed disputable, which has been
disputed and which I myself should be disposed, so far as I at present
understand the matter, to modify in some respects, even in accepting the
spirit of our author's assertion. Yet there can be no doubt of the
importance of this thesis, and of the fact that it defines a
characteristic that is indeed fundamental in a wide range of
mathematical research. The philosophical problems that lie at the basis
of recurrent proofs and processes are, as I have elsewhere argued, of
the most fundamental importance.

These, then, are a few hints relating to the significance of our
author's discussion, and a few reasons for hoping that our own students
will profit by the reading of the book as those of other nations have
already done.

Of the person and of the life-work of our author a few words are here,
in conclusion, still in place, addressed, not to the students of his own
science, to whom his position is well known, but to the general reader
who may seek guidance in these pages.

Jules Henri Poincaré was born at Nancy, in 1854, the son of a professor
in the Faculty of Medicine at Nancy. He studied at the École
Polytechnique and at the École des Mines, and later received his
doctorate in mathematics in 1879. In 1883 he began courses of
instruction in mathematics at the École Polytechnique; in 1886 received
a professorship of mathematical physics in the Faculty of Sciences at
Paris; then became member of the Academy of Sciences at Paris, in 1887,
and devoted his life to instruction and investigation in the regions of
pure mathematics, of mathematical physics and of celestial mechanics.
His list of published treatises relating to various branches of his
chosen sciences is long; and his original memoirs have included several
momentous investigations, which have gone far to transform more than one
branch of research. His presence at the International Congress of Arts
and Science in St. Louis was one of the most noticeable features of that
remarkable gathering of distinguished foreign guests. In Poincaré the
reader meets, then, not one who is primarily a speculative student of
general problems for their own sake, but an original investigator of the
highest rank in several distinct, although interrelated, branches of
modern research. The theory of functions--a highly recondite region of
pure mathematics--owes to him advances of the first importance, for
instance, the definition of a new type of functions. The 'problem of the
three bodies,' a famous and fundamental problem of celestial mechanics,
has received from his studies a treatment whose significance has been
recognized by the highest authorities. His international reputation has
been confirmed by the conferring of more than one important prize for
his researches. His membership in the most eminent learned societies of
various nations is widely extended; his volumes bearing upon various
branches of mathematics and of mathematical physics are used by special
students in all parts of the learned world; in brief, he is, as
geometer, as analyst and as a theoretical physicist, a leader of his
age.

Meanwhile, as contributor to the philosophical discussion of the bases
and methods of science, M. Poincaré has long been active. When, in 1893,
the admirable _Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale_ began to appear, M.
Poincaré was soon found amongst the most satisfactory of the
contributors to the work of that journal, whose office it has especially
been to bring philosophy and the various special sciences (both natural
and moral) into a closer mutual understanding. The discussions brought
together in the present volume are in large part the outcome of M.
Poincaré's contributions to the _Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale_.
The reader of M. Poincaré's book is in presence, then, of a great
special investigator who is also a philosopher.



SCIENCE AND HYPOTHESIS

INTRODUCTION


For a superficial observer, scientific truth is beyond the possibility
of doubt; the logic of science is infallible, and if the scientists are
sometimes mistaken, this is only from their mistaking its rules.

"The mathematical verities flow from a small number of self-evident
propositions by a chain of impeccable reasonings; they impose themselves
not only on us, but on nature itself. They fetter, so to speak, the
Creator and only permit him to choose between some relatively few
solutions. A few experiments then will suffice to let us know what
choice he has made. From each experiment a crowd of consequences will
follow by a series of mathematical deductions, and thus each experiment
will make known to us a corner of the universe."

Behold what is for many people in the world, for scholars getting their
first notions of physics, the origin of scientific certitude. This is
what they suppose to be the rôle of experimentation and mathematics.
This same conception, a hundred years ago, was held by many savants who
dreamed of constructing the world with as little as possible taken from
experiment.

On a little more reflection it was perceived how great a place
hypothesis occupies; that the mathematician can not do without it, still
less the experimenter. And then it was doubted if all these
constructions were really solid, and believed that a breath would
overthrow them. To be skeptical in this fashion is still to be
superficial. To doubt everything and to believe everything are two
equally convenient solutions; each saves us from thinking.

Instead of pronouncing a summary condemnation, we ought therefore to
examine with care the rôle of hypothesis; we shall then recognize, not
only that it is necessary, but that usually it is legitimate. We shall
also see that there are several sorts of hypotheses; that some are
verifiable, and once confirmed by experiment become fruitful truths;
that others, powerless to lead us astray, may be useful to us in fixing
our ideas; that others, finally, are hypotheses only in appearance and
are reducible to disguised definitions or conventions.

These last are met with above all in mathematics and the related
sciences. Thence precisely it is that these sciences get their rigor;
these conventions are the work of the free activity of our mind, which,
in this domain, recognizes no obstacle. Here our mind can affirm, since
it decrees; but let us understand that while these decrees are imposed
upon _our_ science, which, without them, would be impossible, they are
not imposed upon nature. Are they then arbitrary? No, else were they
sterile. Experiment leaves us our freedom of choice, but it guides us by
aiding us to discern the easiest way. Our decrees are therefore like
those of a prince, absolute but wise, who consults his council of state.

Some people have been struck by this character of free convention
recognizable in certain fundamental principles of the sciences. They
have wished to generalize beyond measure, and, at the same time, they
have forgotten that liberty is not license. Thus they have reached what
is called _nominalism_, and have asked themselves if the savant is not
the dupe of his own definitions and if the world he thinks he discovers
is not simply created by his own caprice.[1] Under these conditions
science would be certain, but deprived of significance.

  [1] See Le Roy, 'Science et Philosophie,' _Revue de Métaphysique
      et de Morale_, 1901.

If this were so, science would be powerless. Now every day we see it
work under our very eyes. That could not be if it taught us nothing of
reality. Still, the things themselves are not what it can reach, as the
naïve dogmatists think, but only the relations between things. Outside
of these relations there is no knowable reality.

Such is the conclusion to which we shall come, but for that we must
review the series of sciences from arithmetic and geometry to mechanics
and experimental physics.

What is the nature of mathematical reasoning? Is is really deductive, as
is commonly supposed? A deeper analysis shows us that it is not, that it
partakes in a certain measure of the nature of inductive reasoning, and
just because of this is it so fruitful. None the less does it retain its
character of rigor absolute; this is the first thing that had to be
shown.

Knowing better now one of the instruments which mathematics puts into
the hands of the investigator, we had to analyze another fundamental
notion, that of mathematical magnitude. Do we find it in nature, or do
we ourselves introduce it there? And, in this latter case, do we not
risk marring everything? Comparing the rough data of our senses with
that extremely complex and subtile concept which mathematicians call
magnitude, we are forced to recognize a difference; this frame into
which we wish to force everything is of our own construction; but we
have not made it at random. We have made it, so to speak, by measure and
therefore we can make the facts fit into it without changing what is
essential in them.

Another frame which we impose on the world is space. Whence come the
first principles of geometry? Are they imposed on us by logic?
Lobachevski has proved not, by creating non-Euclidean geometry. Is space
revealed to us by our senses? Still no, for the space our senses could
show us differs absolutely from that of the geometer. Is experience the
source of geometry? A deeper discussion will show us it is not. We
therefore conclude that the first principles of geometry are only
conventions; but these conventions are not arbitrary and if transported
into another world (that I call the non-Euclidean world and seek to
imagine), then we should have been led to adopt others.

In mechanics we should be led to analogous conclusions, and should see
that the principles of this science, though more directly based on
experiment, still partake of the conventional character of the geometric
postulates. Thus far nominalism triumphs; but now we arrive at the
physical sciences, properly so called. Here the scene changes; we meet
another sort of hypotheses and we see their fertility. Without doubt, at
first blush, the theories seem to us fragile, and the history of science
proves to us how ephemeral they are; yet they do not entirely perish,
and of each of them something remains. It is this something we must seek
to disentangle, since there and there alone is the veritable reality.

The method of the physical sciences rests on the induction which makes
us expect the repetition of a phenomenon when the circumstances under
which it first happened are reproduced. If _all_ these circumstances
could be reproduced at once, this principle could be applied without
fear; but that will never happen; some of these circumstances will
always be lacking. Are we absolutely sure they are unimportant?
Evidently not. That may be probable, it can not be rigorously certain.
Hence the important rôle the notion of probability plays in the physical
sciences. The calculus of probabilities is therefore not merely a
recreation or a guide to players of baccarat, and we must seek to go
deeper with its foundations. Under this head I have been able to give
only very incomplete results, so strongly does this vague instinct which
lets us discern probability defy analysis.

After a study of the conditions under which the physicist works, I have
thought proper to show him at work. For that I have taken instances from
the history of optics and of electricity. We shall see whence have
sprung the ideas of Fresnel, of Maxwell, and what unconscious hypotheses
were made by Ampère and the other founders of electrodynamics.



PART I


NUMBER AND MAGNITUDE



CHAPTER I

ON THE NATURE OF MATHEMATICAL REASONING


I

The very possibility of the science of mathematics seems an insoluble
contradiction. If this science is deductive only in appearance, whence
does it derive that perfect rigor no one dreams of doubting? If, on the
contrary, all the propositions it enunciates can be deduced one from
another by the rules of formal logic, why is not mathematics reduced to
an immense tautology? The syllogism can teach us nothing essentially
new, and, if everything is to spring from the principle of identity,
everything should be capable of being reduced to it. Shall we then admit
that the enunciations of all those theorems which fill so many volumes
are nothing but devious ways of saying _A_ is _A_?

Without doubt, we can go back to the axioms, which are at the source of
all these reasonings. If we decide that these can not be reduced to the
principle of contradiction, if still less we see in them experimental
facts which could not partake of mathematical necessity, we have yet the
resource of classing them among synthetic _a priori_ judgments. This is
not to solve the difficulty, but only to baptize it; and even if the
nature of synthetic judgments were for us no mystery, the contradiction
would not have disappeared, it would only have moved back; syllogistic
reasoning remains incapable of adding anything to the data given it:
these data reduce themselves to a few axioms, and we should find nothing
else in the conclusions.

No theorem could be new if no new axiom intervened in its demonstration;
reasoning could give us only the immediately evident verities borrowed
from direct intuition; it would be only an intermediary parasite, and
therefore should we not have good reason to ask whether the whole
syllogistic apparatus did not serve solely to disguise our borrowing?

The contradiction will strike us the more if we open any book on
mathematics; on every page the author will announce his intention of
generalizing some proposition already known. Does the mathematical
method proceed from the particular to the general, and, if so, how then
can it be called deductive?

If finally the science of number were purely analytic, or could be
analytically derived from a small number of synthetic judgments, it
seems that a mind sufficiently powerful could at a glance perceive all
its truths; nay more, we might even hope that some day one would invent
to express them a language sufficiently simple to have them appear
self-evident to an ordinary intelligence.

If we refuse to admit these consequences, it must be conceded that
mathematical reasoning has of itself a sort of creative virtue and
consequently differs from the syllogism.

The difference must even be profound. We shall not, for example, find
the key to the mystery in the frequent use of that rule according to
which one and the same uniform operation applied to two equal numbers
will give identical results.

All these modes of reasoning, whether or not they be reducible to the
syllogism properly so called, retain the analytic character, and just
because of that are powerless.


II

The discussion is old; Leibnitz tried to prove 2 and 2 make 4; let us
look a moment at his demonstration.

I will suppose the number 1 defined and also the operation _x_ + 1 which
consists in adding unity to a given number _x_.

These definitions, whatever they be, do not enter into the course of the
reasoning.

I define then the numbers 2, 3 and 4 by the equalities

  (1) 1 + 1 = 2;   (2) 2 + 1 = 3;   (3) 3 + 1 = 4.

In the same way, I define the operation _x_ + 2 by the relation:

  (4) _x_ + 2 = (_x_ + 1) + 1.

That presupposed, we have

  2 + 1 + 1 = 3 + 1     (Definition 2),
  3 + 1 = 4             (Definition 3),
  2 + 2 = (2 + 1) + 1   (Definition 4),

whence

  2 + 2 = 4 Q.E.D.

It can not be denied that this reasoning is purely analytic. But ask any
mathematician: 'That is not a demonstration properly so called,' he will
say to you: 'that is a verification.' We have confined ourselves to
comparing two purely conventional definitions and have ascertained their
identity; we have learned nothing new. _Verification_ differs from true
demonstration precisely because it is purely analytic and because it is
sterile. It is sterile because the conclusion is nothing but the
premises translated into another language. On the contrary, true
demonstration is fruitful because the conclusion here is in a sense more
general than the premises.

The equality 2 + 2 = 4 is thus susceptible of a verification only
because it is particular. Every particular enunciation in mathematics
can always be verified in this same way. But if mathematics could be
reduced to a series of such verifications, it would not be a science. So
a chess-player, for example, does not create a science in winning a
game. There is no science apart from the general.

It may even be said the very object of the exact sciences is to spare us
these direct verifications.


III

Let us, therefore, see the geometer at work and seek to catch his
process.

The task is not without difficulty; it does not suffice to open a work
at random and analyze any demonstration in it.

We must first exclude geometry, where the question is complicated by
arduous problems relative to the rôle of the postulates, to the nature
and the origin of the notion of space. For analogous reasons we can not
turn to the infinitesimal analysis. We must seek mathematical thought
where it has remained pure, that is, in arithmetic.

A choice still is necessary; in the higher parts of the theory of
numbers, the primitive mathematical notions have already undergone an
elaboration so profound that it becomes difficult to analyze them.

It is, therefore, at the beginning of arithmetic that we must expect to
find the explanation we seek, but it happens that precisely in the
demonstration of the most elementary theorems the authors of the classic
treatises have shown the least precision and rigor. We must not impute
this to them as a crime; they have yielded to a necessity; beginners are
not prepared for real mathematical rigor; they would see in it only
useless and irksome subtleties; it would be a waste of time to try
prematurely to make them more exacting; they must pass over rapidly, but
without skipping stations, the road traversed slowly by the founders of
the science.

Why is so long a preparation necessary to become habituated to this
perfect rigor, which, it would seem, should naturally impress itself
upon all good minds? This is a logical and psychological problem well
worthy of study.

But we shall not take it up; it is foreign to our purpose; all I wish to
insist on is that, not to fail of our purpose, we must recast the
demonstrations of the most elementary theorems and give them, not the
crude form in which they are left, so as not to harass beginners, but
the form that will satisfy a skilled geometer.

DEFINITION OF ADDITION.--I suppose already defined the operation
_x_ + 1, which consists in adding the number 1 to a given number _x_.

This definition, whatever it be, does not enter into our subsequent
reasoning.

We now have to define the operation _x_ + _a_, which consists in adding
the number _a_ to a given number _x_.

Supposing we have defined the operation

  _x_ + (_a_ - 1),

the operation _x_ + _a_ will be defined by the equality

  (1) _x_ + _a_ = [_x_ + (_a_ - 1)] + 1.

We shall know then what _x + a_ is when we know what _x_ + (_a_ - 1)
is, and as I have supposed that to start with we knew what _x_ + 1 is,
we can define successively and 'by recurrence' the operations _x_ + 2,
_x_ + 3, etc.

This definition deserves a moment's attention; it is of a particular
nature which already distinguishes it from the purely logical
definition; the equality (1) contains an infinity of distinct
definitions, each having a meaning only when one knows the preceding.

PROPERTIES OF ADDITION.--_Associativity._--I say that

  _a_ + (_b_ + _c_) = (_a_ + _b_) + _c_.

In fact the theorem is true for _c_ = 1; it is then written

  _a_ + (_b_ + 1) = (_a_ + _b_) + 1,

which, apart from the difference of notation, is nothing but the
equality (1), by which I have just defined addition.

Supposing the theorem true for _c_ = [gamma], I say it will be true for
_c_ = [gamma] + 1.

In fact, supposing

  (_a_ + _b_) + [gamma] = _a_ + (_b_ + [gamma]),

it follows that

  [(_a_ + _b_) + [gamma]] + 1 = [_a_ + (_b_ + [gamma])] + 1

or by definition (1)

  (_a_ + _b_) + ([gamma] + 1) = _a_ + (_b_ + [gamma] + 1)
                              = _a_ + [_b_ + ([gamma] + 1)],

which shows, by a series of purely analytic deductions, that the
theorem is true for [gamma] + 1.

Being true for _c_ = 1, we thus see successively that so it is for
_c_ = 2, for _c_ = 3, etc.

_Commutativity._--1º I say that

  _a_ + 1 = 1 + _a_.

The theorem is evidently true for _a_ = 1; we can _verify_ by purely
analytic reasoning that if it is true for _a_ = [gamma] it will be true
for _a_ = [gamma] + 1; for then

  ([gamma] + 1) + 1 = (1 + [gamma]) + 1 = 1 + ([gamma] + 1);

now it is true for _a_ = 1, therefore it will be true for _a_ = 2, for
_a_ = 3, etc., which is expressed by saying that the enunciated
proposition is demonstrated by recurrence.

2º I say that

  _a_ + _b_ = _b_ + _a_.

The theorem has just been demonstrated for _b_ = 1; it can be verified
analytically that if it is true for _b_ = [beta], it will be true for
_b_ = [beta] + 1.

The proposition is therefore established by recurrence.

DEFINITION OF MULTIPLICATION.--We shall define multiplication by the
equalities.

  (1) _a_ × 1 = _a_.

  (2) _a_ × _b_ = [_a_ × (_b_ - 1)] + _a_.

Like equality (1), equality (2) contains an infinity of definitions;
having defined a × 1, it enables us to define successively: _a_ × 2,
_a_ × 3, etc.

PROPERTIES OF MULTIPLICATION.--_Distributivity._--I say that

  (_a_ + _b_) × _c_ = (_a_ × _c_) + (_b_ × _c_).

We verify analytically that the equality is true for _c_ = 1; then
that if the theorem is true for _c_ = [gamma], it will be true
for _c_ = [gamma] + 1.

The proposition is, therefore, demonstrated by recurrence.

_Commutativity._--1º I say that

  _a_ × 1 = 1 × _a_.

The theorem is evident for _a_ = 1.

We verify analytically that if it is true for _a_ = [alpha], it will be
true for _a_ = [alpha] + 1.

2º I say that

  _a_ × _b_ = _b_ × _a_.

The theorem has just been proven for _b_ = 1. We could verify
analytically that if it is true for _b_ = [beta], it will be true
for _b_ = [beta] + 1.


IV

Here I stop this monotonous series of reasonings. But this very monotony
has the better brought out the procedure which is uniform and is met
again at each step.

This procedure is the demonstration by recurrence. We first establish a
theorem for _n_ = 1; then we show that if it is true of _n_ - 1, it is
true of _n_, and thence conclude that it is true for all the whole
numbers.

We have just seen how it may be used to demonstrate the rules of
addition and multiplication, that is to say, the rules of the algebraic
calculus; this calculus is an instrument of transformation, which lends
itself to many more differing combinations than does the simple
syllogism; but it is still an instrument purely analytic, and incapable
of teaching us anything new. If mathematics had no other instrument, it
would therefore be forthwith arrested in its development; but it has
recourse anew to the same procedure, that is, to reasoning by
recurrence, and it is able to continue its forward march.

If we look closely, at every step we meet again this mode of reasoning,
either in the simple form we have just given it, or under a form more or
less modified.

Here then we have the mathematical reasoning _par excellence_, and we
must examine it more closely.


V

The essential characteristic of reasoning by recurrence is that it
contains, condensed, so to speak, in a single formula, an infinity of
syllogisms.

That this may the better be seen, I will state one after another these
syllogisms which are, if you will allow me the expression, arranged in
'cascade.'

These are of course hypothetical syllogisms.

The theorem is true of the number 1.

Now, if it is true of 1, it is true of 2.

Therefore it is true of 2.

Now, if it is true of 2, it is true of 3.

Therefore it is true of 3, and so on.

We see that the conclusion of each syllogism serves as minor to the
following.

Furthermore the majors of all our syllogisms can be reduced to a single
formula.

If the theorem is true of _n_ - 1, so it is of _n_.

We see, then, that in reasoning by recurrence we confine ourselves to
stating the minor of the first syllogism, and the general formula which
contains as particular cases all the majors.

This never-ending series of syllogisms is thus reduced to a phrase of a
few lines.

It is now easy to comprehend why every particular consequence of a
theorem can, as I have explained above, be verified by purely analytic
procedures.

If instead of showing that our theorem is true of all numbers, we only
wish to show it true of the number 6, for example, it will suffice for
us to establish the first 5 syllogisms of our cascade; 9 would be
necessary if we wished to prove the theorem for the number 10; more
would be needed for a larger number; but, however great this number
might be, we should always end by reaching it, and the analytic
verification would be possible.

And yet, however far we thus might go, we could never rise to the
general theorem, applicable to all numbers, which alone can be the
object of science. To reach this, an infinity of syllogisms would be
necessary; it would be necessary to overleap an abyss that the patience
of the analyst, restricted to the resources of formal logic alone, never
could fill up.

I asked at the outset why one could not conceive of a mind sufficiently
powerful to perceive at a glance the whole body of mathematical truths.

The answer is now easy; a chess-player is able to combine four moves,
five moves, in advance, but, however extraordinary he may be, he will
never prepare more than a finite number of them; if he applies his
faculties to arithmetic, he will not be able to perceive its general
truths by a single direct intuition; to arrive at the smallest theorem
he can not dispense with the aid of reasoning by recurrence, for this is
an instrument which enables us to pass from the finite to the infinite.

This instrument is always useful, for, allowing us to overleap at a
bound as many stages as we wish, it spares us verifications, long,
irksome and monotonous, which would quickly become impracticable. But it
becomes indispensable as soon as we aim at the general theorem, to which
analytic verification would bring us continually nearer without ever
enabling us to reach it.

In this domain of arithmetic, we may think ourselves very far from the
infinitesimal analysis, and yet, as we have just seen, the idea of the
mathematical infinite already plays a preponderant rôle, and without it
there would be no science, because there would be nothing general.


VI

The judgment on which reasoning by recurrence rests can be put under
other forms; we may say, for example, that in an infinite collection of
different whole numbers there is always one which is less than all the
others.

We can easily pass from one enunciation to the other and thus get the
illusion of having demonstrated the legitimacy of reasoning by
recurrence. But we shall always be arrested, we shall always arrive at
an undemonstrable axiom which will be in reality only the proposition to
be proved translated into another language.

We can not therefore escape the conclusion that the rule of reasoning by
recurrence is irreducible to the principle of contradiction.

Neither can this rule come to us from experience; experience could teach
us that the rule is true for the first ten or hundred numbers; for
example, it can not attain to the indefinite series of numbers, but only
to a portion of this series, more or less long but always limited.

Now if it were only a question of that, the principle of contradiction
would suffice; it would always allow of our developing as many
syllogisms as we wished; it is only when it is a question of including
an infinity of them in a single formula, it is only before the infinite
that this principle fails, and there too, experience becomes powerless.
This rule, inaccessible to analytic demonstration and to experience, is
the veritable type of the synthetic _a priori_ judgment. On the other
hand, we can not think of seeing in it a convention, as in some of the
postulates of geometry.

Why then does this judgment force itself upon us with an irresistible
evidence? It is because it is only the affirmation of the power of the
mind which knows itself capable of conceiving the indefinite repetition
of the same act when once this act is possible. The mind has a direct
intuition of this power, and experience can only give occasion for using
it and thereby becoming conscious of it.

But, one will say, if raw experience can not legitimatize reasoning by
recurrence, is it so of experiment aided by induction? We see
successively that a theorem is true of the number 1, of the number 2, of
the number 3 and so on; the law is evident, we say, and it has the same
warranty as every physical law based on observations, whose number is
very great but limited.

Here is, it must be admitted, a striking analogy with the usual
procedures of induction. But there is an essential difference. Induction
applied to the physical sciences is always uncertain, because it rests
on the belief in a general order of the universe, an order outside of
us. Mathematical induction, that is, demonstration by recurrence, on the
contrary, imposes itself necessarily because it is only the affirmation
of a property of the mind itself.


VII

Mathematicians, as I have said before, always endeavor to _generalize_
the propositions they have obtained, and, to seek no other example, we
have just proved the equality:

  _a_ + 1 = 1 + _a_

and afterwards used it to establish the equality

  _a_ + _b_ = _b_ + _a_

which is manifestly more general.

Mathematics can, therefore, like the other sciences, proceed from the
particular to the general.

This is a fact which would have appeared incomprehensible to us at the
outset of this study, but which is no longer mysterious to us, since we
have ascertained the analogies between demonstration by recurrence and
ordinary induction.

Without doubt recurrent reasoning in mathematics and inductive reasoning
in physics rest on different foundations, but their march is parallel,
they advance in the same sense, that is to say, from the particular to
the general.

Let us examine the case a little more closely.

To demonstrate the equality

  _a_ + 2 = 2 + _a_

it suffices to twice apply the rule

  (1) _a_ + 1 = 1 + _a_

and write

  (2) _a_ + 2 = _a_ + 1 + 1 = 1 + _a_ + 1 = 1 + 1 + _a_ = 2 + _a_.

The equality (2) thus deduced in purely analytic way from the equality
(1) is, however, not simply a particular ease of it; it is something
quite different.

We can not therefore even say that in the really analytic and deductive
part of mathematical reasoning we proceed from the general to the
particular in the ordinary sense of the word.

The two members of the equality (2) are simply combinations more
complicated than the two members of the equality (1), and analysis only
serves to separate the elements which enter into these combinations and
to study their relations.

Mathematicians proceed therefore 'by construction,' they 'construct'
combinations more and more complicated. Coming back then by the analysis
of these combinations, of these aggregates, so to speak, to their
primitive elements, they perceive the relations of these elements and
from them deduce the relations of the aggregates themselves.

This is a purely analytical proceeding, but it is not, however, a
proceeding from the general to the particular, because evidently the
aggregates can not be regarded as more particular than their elements.

Great importance, and justly, has been attached to this procedure of
'construction,' and some have tried to see in it the necessary and
sufficient condition for the progress of the exact sciences.

Necessary, without doubt; but sufficient, no.

For a construction to be useful and not a vain toil for the mind, that
it may serve as stepping-stone to one wishing to mount, it must first of
all possess a sort of unity enabling us to see in it something besides
the juxtaposition of its elements.

Or, more exactly, there must be some advantage in considering the
construction rather than its elements themselves.

What can this advantage be?

Why reason on a polygon, for instance, which is always decomposable into
triangles, and not on the elementary triangles?

It is because there are properties appertaining to polygons of any
number of sides and that may be immediately applied to any particular
polygon.

Usually, on the contrary, it is only at the cost of the most prolonged
exertions that they could be found by studying directly the relations of
the elementary triangles. The knowledge of the general theorem spares us
these efforts.

A construction, therefore, becomes interesting only when it can be
ranged beside other analogous constructions, forming species of the same
genus.

If the quadrilateral is something besides the juxtaposition of two
triangles, this is because it belongs to the genus polygon.

Moreover, one must be able to demonstrate the properties of the genus
without being forced to establish them successively for each of the
species.

To attain that, we must necessarily mount from the particular to the
general, ascending one or more steps.

The analytic procedure 'by construction' does not oblige us to descend,
but it leaves us at the same level.

We can ascend only by mathematical induction, which alone can teach us
something new. Without the aid of this induction, different in certain
respects from physical induction, but quite as fertile, construction
would be powerless to create science.

Observe finally that this induction is possible only if the same
operation can be repeated indefinitely. That is why the theory of chess
can never become a science, for the different moves of the same game do
not resemble one another.



CHAPTER II

MATHEMATICAL MAGNITUDE AND EXPERIENCE


To learn what mathematicians understand by a continuum, one should not
inquire of geometry. The geometer always seeks to represent to himself
more or less the figures he studies, but his representations are for him
only instruments; in making geometry he uses space just as he does
chalk; so too much weight should not be attached to non-essentials,
often of no more importance than the whiteness of the chalk.

The pure analyst has not this rock to fear. He has disengaged the
science of mathematics from all foreign elements, and can answer our
question: 'What exactly is this continuum about which mathematicians
reason?' Many analysts who reflect on their art have answered already;
Monsieur Tannery, for example, in his _Introduction à la théorie des
fonctions d'une variable_.

Let us start from the scale of whole numbers; between two consecutive
steps, intercalate one or more intermediary steps, then between these
new steps still others, and so on indefinitely. Thus we shall have an
unlimited number of terms; these will be the numbers called fractional,
rational or commensurable. But this is not yet enough; between these
terms, which, however, are already infinite in number, it is still
necessary to intercalate others called irrational or incommensurable. A
remark before going further. The continuum so conceived is only a
collection of individuals ranged in a certain order, infinite in number,
it is true, but _exterior_ to one another. This is not the ordinary
conception, wherein is supposed between the elements of the continuum a
sort of intimate bond which makes of them a whole, where the point does
not exist before the line, but the line before the point. Of the
celebrated formula, 'the continuum is unity in multiplicity,' only the
multiplicity remains, the unity has disappeared. The analysts are none
the less right in defining their continuum as they do, for they always
reason on just this as soon as they pique themselves on their rigor. But
this is enough to apprise us that the veritable mathematical continuum
is a very different thing from that of the physicists and that of the
metaphysicians.

It may also be said perhaps that the mathematicians who are content with
this definition are dupes of words, that it is necessary to say
precisely what each of these intermediary steps is, to explain how they
are to be intercalated and to demonstrate that it is possible to do it.
But that would be wrong; the only property of these steps which is used
in their reasonings[2] is that of being before or after such and such
steps; therefore also this alone should occur in the definition.

  [2] With those contained in the special conventions which serve to
      define addition and of which we shall speak later.

So how the intermediary terms should be intercalated need not concern
us; on the other hand, no one will doubt the possibility of this
operation, unless from forgetting that possible, in the language of
geometers, simply means free from contradiction.

Our definition, however, is not yet complete, and I return to it after
this over-long digression.

DEFINITION OF INCOMMENSURABLES.--The mathematicians of the Berlin
school, Kronecker in particular, have devoted themselves to constructing
this continuous scale of fractional and irrational numbers without using
any material other than the whole number. The mathematical continuum
would be, in this view, a pure creation of the mind, where experience
would have no part.

The notion of the rational number seeming to them to present no
difficulty, they have chiefly striven to define the incommensurable
number. But before producing here their definition, I must make a remark
to forestall the astonishment it is sure to arouse in readers unfamiliar
with the customs of geometers.

Mathematicians study not objects, but relations between objects; the
replacement of these objects by others is therefore indifferent to them,
provided the relations do not change. The matter is for them
unimportant, the form alone interests them.

Without recalling this, it would scarcely be comprehensible that
Dedekind should designate by the name _incommensurable number_ a mere
symbol, that is to say, something very different from the ordinary idea
of a quantity, which should be measurable and almost tangible.

Let us see now what Dedekind's definition is:

The commensurable numbers can in an infinity of ways be partitioned into
two classes, such that any number of the first class is greater than any
number of the second class.

It may happen that among the numbers of the first class there is one
smaller than all the others; if, for example, we range in the first
class all numbers greater than 2, and 2 itself, and in the second class
all numbers less than 2, it is clear that 2 will be the least of all
numbers of the first class. The number 2 may be chosen as symbol of this
partition.

It may happen, on the contrary, that among the numbers of the second
class is one greater than all the others; this is the case, for example,
if the first class comprehends all numbers greater than 2, and the
second all numbers less than 2, and 2 itself. Here again the number 2
may be chosen as symbol of this partition.

But it may equally well happen that neither is there in the first class
a number less than all the others, nor in the second class a number
greater than all the others. Suppose, for example, we put in the first
class all commensurable numbers whose squares are greater than 2 and in
the second all whose squares are less than 2. There is none whose square
is precisely 2. Evidently there is not in the first class a number less
than all the others, for, however near the square of a number may be to
2, we can always find a commensurable number whose square is still
closer to 2.

In Dedekind's view, the incommensurable number

  sqrt(2) or (2)^{1/2}

is nothing but the symbol of this particular mode of partition of
commensurable numbers; and to each mode of partition corresponds thus a
number, commensurable or not, which serves as its symbol.

But to be content with this would be to forget too far the origin of
these symbols; it remains to explain how we have been led to attribute
to them a sort of concrete existence, and, besides, does not the
difficulty begin even for the fractional numbers themselves? Should we
have the notion of these numbers if we had not previously known a matter
that we conceive as infinitely divisible, that is to say, a continuum?

THE PHYSICAL CONTINUUM.--We ask ourselves then if the notion of the
mathematical continuum is not simply drawn from experience. If it were,
the raw data of experience, which are our sensations, would be
susceptible of measurement. We might be tempted to believe they really
are so, since in these latter days the attempt has been made to measure
them and a law has even been formulated, known as Fechner's law,
according to which sensation is proportional to the logarithm of the
stimulus.

But if we examine more closely the experiments by which it has been
sought to establish this law, we shall be led to a diametrically
opposite conclusion. It has been observed, for example, that a weight
_A_ of 10 grams and a weight _B_ of 11 grams produce identical
sensations, that the weight _B_ is just as indistinguishable from a
weight _C_ of 12 grams, but that the weight _A_ is easily distinguished
from the weight _C_. Thus the raw results of experience may be expressed
by the following relations:

  _A_ =_B_,   _B_ = _C_,   _A_ < _C_,

which may be regarded as the formula of the physical continuum.

But here is an intolerable discord with the principle of contradiction,
and the need of stopping this has compelled us to invent the
mathematical continuum.

We are, therefore, forced to conclude that this notion has been created
entirely by the mind, but that experience has given the occasion.

We can not believe that two quantities equal to a third are not equal to
one another, and so we are led to suppose that _A_ is different from _B_
and _B_ from _C_, but that the imperfection of our senses has not
permitted of our distinguishing them.

CREATION OF THE MATHEMATICAL CONTINUUM.--_First Stage._ So far it would
suffice, in accounting for the facts, to intercalate between _A_ and _B_
a few terms, which would remain discrete. What happens now if we have
recourse to some instrument to supplement the feebleness of our senses,
if, for example, we make use of a microscope? Terms such as _A_ and _B_,
before indistinguishable, appear now distinct; but between _A_ and _B_,
now become distinct, will be intercalated a new term, _D_, that we can
distinguish neither from _A_ nor from _B_. Despite the employment of the
most highly perfected methods, the raw results of our experience will
always present the characteristics of the physical continuum with the
contradiction which is inherent in it.

We shall escape it only by incessantly intercalating new terms between
the terms already distinguished, and this operation must be continued
indefinitely. We might conceive the stopping of this operation if we
could imagine some instrument sufficiently powerful to decompose the
physical continuum into discrete elements, as the telescope resolves the
milky way into stars. But this we can not imagine; in fact, it is with
the eye we observe the image magnified by the microscope, and
consequently this image must always retain the characteristics of visual
sensation and consequently those of the physical continuum.

Nothing distinguishes a length observed directly from the half of this
length doubled by the microscope. The whole is homogeneous with the
part; this is a new contradiction, or rather it would be if the number
of terms were supposed finite; in fact, it is clear that the part
containing fewer terms than the whole could not be similar to the whole.

The contradiction ceases when the number of terms is regarded as
infinite; nothing hinders, for example, considering the aggregate of
whole numbers as similar to the aggregate of even numbers, which,
however, is only a part of it; and, in fact, to each whole number
corresponds an even number, its double.

But it is not only to escape this contradiction contained in the
empirical data that the mind is led to create the concept of a
continuum, formed of an indefinite number of terms.

All happens as in the sequence of whole numbers. We have the faculty of
conceiving that a unit can be added to a collection of units; thanks to
experience, we have occasion to exercise this faculty and we become
conscious of it; but from this moment we feel that our power has no
limit and that we can count indefinitely, though we have never had to
count more than a finite number of objects.

Just so, as soon as we have been led to intercalate means between two
consecutive terms of a series, we feel that this operation can be
continued beyond all limit, and that there is, so to speak, no intrinsic
reason for stopping.

As an abbreviation, let me call a mathematical continuum of the first
order every aggregate of terms formed according to the same law as the
scale of commensurable numbers. If we afterwards intercalate new steps
according to the law of formation of incommensurable numbers, we shall
obtain what we will call a continuum of the second order.

_Second Stage._--We have made hitherto only the first stride; we have
explained the origin of continua of the first order; but it is necessary
to see why even they are not sufficient and why the incommensurable
numbers had to be invented.

If we try to imagine a line, it must have the characteristics of the
physical continuum, that is to say, we shall not be able to represent it
except with a certain breadth. Two lines then will appear to us under
the form of two narrow bands, and, if we are content with this rough
image, it is evident that if the two lines cross they will have a common
part.

But the pure geometer makes a further effort; without entirely
renouncing the aid of the senses, he tries to reach the concept of the
line without breadth, of the point without extension. This he can only
attain to by regarding the line as the limit toward which tends an ever
narrowing band, and the point as the limit toward which tends an ever
lessening area. And then, our two bands, however narrow they may be,
will always have a common area, the smaller as they are the narrower,
and whose limit will be what the pure geometer calls a point.

This is why it is said two lines which cross have a point in common, and
this truth seems intuitive.

But it would imply contradiction if lines were conceived as continua of
the first order, that is to say, if on the lines traced by the geometer
should be found only points having for coordinates rational numbers. The
contradiction would be manifest as soon as one affirmed, for example,
the existence of straights and circles.

It is clear, in fact, that if the points whose coordinates are
commensurable were alone regarded as real, the circle inscribed in a
square and the diagonal of this square would not intersect, since the
coordinates of the point of intersection are incommensurable.

That would not yet be sufficient, because we should get in this way only
certain incommensurable numbers and not all those numbers.

But conceive of a straight line divided into two rays. Each of these
rays will appear to our imagination as a band of a certain breadth;
these bands moreover will encroach one on the other, since there must be
no interval between them. The common part will appear to us as a point
which will always remain when we try to imagine our bands narrower and
narrower, so that we admit as an intuitive truth that if a straight is
cut into two rays their common frontier is a point; we recognize here
the conception of Dedekind, in which an incommensurable number was
regarded as the common frontier of two classes of rational numbers.

Such is the origin of the continuum of the second order, which is the
mathematical continuum properly so called.

_Résumé._--In recapitulation, the mind has the faculty of creating
symbols, and it is thus that it has constructed the mathematical
continuum, which is only a particular system of symbols. Its power is
limited only by the necessity of avoiding all contradiction; but the
mind only makes use of this faculty if experience furnishes it a
stimulus thereto.

In the case considered, this stimulus was the notion of the physical
continuum, drawn from the rough data of the senses. But this notion
leads to a series of contradictions from which it is necessary
successively to free ourselves. So we are forced to imagine a more and
more complicated system of symbols. That at which we stop is not only
exempt from internal contradiction (it was so already at all the stages
we have traversed), but neither is it in contradiction with various
propositions called intuitive, which are derived from empirical notions
more or less elaborated.

MEASURABLE MAGNITUDE.--The magnitudes we have studied hitherto are not
_measurable_; we can indeed say whether a given one of these magnitudes
is greater than another, but not whether it is twice or thrice as great.

So far, I have only considered the order in which our terms are ranged.
But for most applications that does not suffice. We must learn to
compare the interval which separates any two terms. Only on this
condition does the continuum become a measurable magnitude and the
operations of arithmetic applicable.

This can only be done by the aid of a new and special _convention_. We
will _agree_ that in such and such a case the interval comprised between
the terms _A_ and _B_ is equal to the interval which separates _C_ and
_D_. For example, at the beginning of our work we have set out from the
scale of the whole numbers and we have supposed intercalated between two
consecutive steps _n_ intermediary steps; well, these new steps will be
by convention regarded as equidistant.

This is a way of defining the addition of two magnitudes, because if the
interval _AB_ is by definition equal to the interval _CD_, the interval
_AD_ will be by definition the sum of the intervals _AB_ and _AC_.

This definition is arbitrary in a very large measure. It is not
completely so, however. It is subjected to certain conditions and, for
example, to the rules of commutativity and associativity of addition.
But provided the definition chosen satisfies these rules, the choice is
indifferent, and it is useless to particularize it.

VARIOUS REMARKS.--We can now discuss several important questions:

1º Is the creative power of the mind exhausted by the creation of the
mathematical continuum?

No: the works of Du Bois-Reymond demonstrate it in a striking way.

We know that mathematicians distinguish between infinitesimals of
different orders and that those of the second order are infinitesimal,
not only in an absolute way, but also in relation to those of the first
order. It is not difficult to imagine infinitesimals of fractional or
even of irrational order, and thus we find again that scale of the
mathematical continuum which has been dealt with in the preceding
pages.

Further, there are infinitesimals which are infinitely small in relation
to those of the first order, and, on the contrary, infinitely great in
relation to those of order 1 + [epsilon], and that however small
[epsilon] may be. Here, then, are new terms intercalated in our series,
and if I may be permitted to revert to the phraseology lately employed
which is very convenient though not consecrated by usage, I shall say
that thus has been created a sort of continuum of the third order.

It would be easy to go further, but that would be idle; one would only
be imagining symbols without possible application, and no one will think
of doing that. The continuum of the third order, to which the
consideration of the different orders of infinitesimals leads, is itself
not useful enough to have won citizenship, and geometers regard it only
as a mere curiosity. The mind uses its creative faculty only when
experience requires it.

2º Once in possession of the concept of the mathematical continuum, is
one safe from contradictions analogous to those which gave birth to it?

No, and I will give an example.

One must be very wise not to regard it as evident that every curve has a
tangent; and in fact if we picture this curve and a straight as two
narrow bands we can always so dispose them that they have a part in
common without crossing. If we imagine then the breadth of these two
bands to diminish indefinitely, this common part will always subsist
and, at the limit, so to speak, the two lines will have a point in
common without crossing, that is to say, they will be tangent.

The geometer who reasons in this way, consciously or not, is only doing
what we have done above to prove two lines which cut have a point in
common, and his intuition might seem just as legitimate.

It would deceive him however. We can demonstrate that there are curves
which have no tangent, if such a curve is defined as an analytic
continuum of the second order.

Without doubt some artifice analogous to those we have discussed above
would have sufficed to remove the contradiction; but, as this is met
with only in very exceptional cases, it has received no further
attention.

Instead of seeking to reconcile intuition with analysis, we have been
content to sacrifice one of the two, and as analysis must remain
impeccable, we have decided against intuition.

THE PHYSICAL CONTINUUM OF SEVERAL DIMENSIONS.--We have discussed above
the physical continuum as derived from the immediate data of our senses,
or, if you wish, from the rough results of Fechner's experiments; I have
shown that these results are summed up in the contradictory formulas

  _A_ = _B_,   _B_ = _C_,   _A_ < _C_.

Let us now see how this notion has been generalized and how from it has
come the concept of many-dimensional continua.

Consider any two aggregates of sensations. Either we can discriminate
them one from another, or we can not, just as in Fechner's experiments a
weight of 10 grams can be distinguished from a weight of 12 grams, but
not from a weight of 11 grams. This is all that is required to construct
the continuum of several dimensions.

Let us call one of these aggregates of sensations an _element_. That
will be something analogous to the _point_ of the mathematicians; it
will not be altogether the same thing however. We can not say our
element is without extension, since we can not distinguish it from
neighboring elements and it is thus surrounded by a sort of haze. If the
astronomical comparison may be allowed, our 'elements' would be like
nebulae, whereas the mathematical points would be like stars.

That being granted, a system of elements will form a _continuum_ if we
can pass from any one of them to any other, by a series of consecutive
elements such that each is indistinguishable from the preceding. This
_linear_ series is to the _line_ of the mathematician what an isolated
_element_ was to the point.

Before going farther, I must explain what is meant by a _cut_. Consider
a continuum _C_ and remove from it certain of its elements which for an
instant we shall regard as no longer belonging to this continuum. The
aggregate of the elements so removed will be called a cut. It may happen
that, thanks to this cut, _C_ may be _subdivided_ into several distinct
continua, the aggregate of the remaining elements ceasing to form a
unique continuum.

There will then be on _C_ two elements, _A_ and _B_, that must be
regarded as belonging to two distinct continua, and this will be
recognized because it will be impossible to find a linear series of
consecutive elements of _C_, each of these elements indistinguishable
from the preceding, the first being _A_ and the last _B_, _without one
of the elements of this series being indistinguishable from one of the
elements of the cut_.

On the contrary, it may happen that the cut made is insufficient to
subdivide the continuum _C_. To classify the physical continua, we will
examine precisely what are the cuts which must be made to subdivide
them.

If a physical continuum _C_ can be subdivided by a cut reducing to a
finite number of elements all distinguishable from one another (and
consequently forming neither a continuum, nor several continua), we
shall say _C_ is a _one-dimensional_ continuum.

If, on the contrary, _C_ can be subdivided only by cuts which are
themselves continua, we shall say _C_ has several dimensions. If cuts
which are continua of one dimension suffice, we shall say _C_ has two
dimensions; if cuts of two dimensions suffice, we shall say _C_ has
three dimensions, and so on.

Thus is defined the notion of the physical continuum of several
dimensions, thanks to this very simple fact that two aggregates of
sensations are distinguishable or indistinguishable.

THE MATHEMATICAL CONTINUUM OF SEVERAL DIMENSIONS.--Thence the notion of
the mathematical continuum of _n_ dimensions has sprung quite naturally
by a process very like that we discussed at the beginning of this
chapter. A point of such a continuum, you know, appears to us as defined
by a system of _n_ distinct magnitudes called its coordinates.

These magnitudes need not always be measurable; there is, for instance,
a branch of geometry independent of the measurement of these magnitudes,
in which it is only a question of knowing, for example, whether on a
curve _ABC_, the point _B_ is between the points _A_ and _C_, and not of
knowing whether the arc _AB_ is equal to the arc _BC_ or twice as great.
This is what is called _Analysis Situs_.

This is a whole body of doctrine which has attracted the attention of
the greatest geometers and where we see flow one from another a series
of remarkable theorems. What distinguishes these theorems from those of
ordinary geometry is that they are purely qualitative and that they
would remain true if the figures were copied by a draughtsman so awkward
as to grossly distort the proportions and replace straights by strokes
more or less curved.

Through the wish to introduce measure next into the continuum just
defined this continuum becomes space, and geometry is born. But the
discussion of this is reserved for Part Second.



PART II


SPACE



CHAPTER III

THE NON-EUCLIDEAN GEOMETRIES


Every conclusion supposes premises; these premises themselves either are
self-evident and need no demonstration, or can be established only by
relying upon other propositions, and since we can not go back thus to
infinity, every deductive science, and in particular geometry, must rest
on a certain number of undemonstrable axioms. All treatises on geometry
begin, therefore, by the enunciation of these axioms. But among these
there is a distinction to be made: Some, for example, 'Things which are
equal to the same thing are equal to one another,' are not propositions
of geometry, but propositions of analysis. I regard them as analytic
judgments _a priori_, and shall not concern myself with them.

But I must lay stress upon other axioms which are peculiar to geometry.
Most treatises enunciate three of these explicitly:

1º Through two points can pass only one straight;

2º The straight line is the shortest path from one point to another;

3º Through a given point there is not more than one parallel to a given
straight.

Although generally a proof of the second of these axioms is omitted, it
would be possible to deduce it from the other two and from those, much
more numerous, which are implicitly admitted without enunciating them,
as I shall explain further on.

It was long sought in vain to demonstrate likewise the third axiom,
known as _Euclid's Postulate_. What vast effort has been wasted in this
chimeric hope is truly unimaginable. Finally, in the first quarter of
the nineteenth century, and almost at the same time, a Hungarian and a
Russian, Bolyai and Lobachevski, established irrefutably that this
demonstration is impossible; they have almost rid us of inventors of
geometries 'sans postulatum'; since then the Académie des Sciences
receives only about one or two new demonstrations a year.

The question was not exhausted; it soon made a great stride by the
publication of Riemann's celebrated memoir entitled: _Ueber die
Hypothesen welche der Geometrie zu Grunde liegen_. This paper has
inspired most of the recent works of which I shall speak further on, and
among which it is proper to cite those of Beltrami and of Helmholtz.

THE BOLYAI-LOBACHEVSKI GEOMETRY.--If it were possible to deduce Euclid's
postulate from the other axioms, it is evident that in denying the
postulate and admitting the other axioms, we should be led to
contradictory consequences; it would therefore be impossible to base on
such premises a coherent geometry.

Now this is precisely what Lobachevski did.

He assumes at the start that: _Through a given point can be drawn two
parallels to a given straight_.

And he retains besides all Euclid's other axioms. From these hypotheses
he deduces a series of theorems among which it is impossible to find any
contradiction, and he constructs a geometry whose faultless logic is
inferior in nothing to that of the Euclidean geometry.

The theorems are, of course, very different from those to which we are
accustomed, and they can not fail to be at first a little disconcerting.

Thus the sum of the angles of a triangle is always less than two right
angles, and the difference between this sum and two right angles is
proportional to the surface of the triangle.

It is impossible to construct a figure similar to a given figure but of
different dimensions.

If we divide a circumference into _n_ equal parts, and draw tangents at
the points of division, these _n_ tangents will form a polygon if the
radius of the circle is small enough; but if this radius is sufficiently
great they will not meet.

It is useless to multiply these examples; Lobachevski's propositions
have no relation to those of Euclid, but they are not less logically
bound one to another.

RIEMANN'S GEOMETRY.--Imagine a world uniquely peopled by beings of no
thickness (height); and suppose these 'infinitely flat' animals are all
in the same plane and can not get out. Admit besides that this world is
sufficiently far from others to be free from their influence. While we
are making hypotheses, it costs us no more to endow these beings with
reason and believe them capable of creating a geometry. In that case,
they will certainly attribute to space only two dimensions.

But suppose now that these imaginary animals, while remaining without
thickness, have the form of a spherical, and not of a plane, figure, and
are all on the same sphere without power to get off. What geometry will
they construct? First it is clear they will attribute to space only two
dimensions; what will play for them the rôle of the straight line will
be the shortest path from one point to another on the sphere, that is to
say, an arc of a great circle; in a word, their geometry will be the
spherical geometry.

What they will call space will be this sphere on which they must stay,
and on which happen all the phenomena they can know. Their space will
therefore be _unbounded_ since on a sphere one can always go forward
without ever being stopped, and yet it will be _finite_; one can never
find the end of it, but one can make a tour of it.

Well, Riemann's geometry is spherical geometry extended to three
dimensions. To construct it, the German mathematician had to throw
overboard, not only Euclid's postulate, but also the first axiom: _Only
one straight can pass through two points_.

On a sphere, through two given points we can draw _in general_ only one
great circle (which, as we have just seen, would play the rôle of the
straight for our imaginary beings); but there is an exception: if the
two given points are diametrically opposite, an infinity of great
circles can be drawn through them.

In the same way, in Riemann's geometry (at least in one of its forms),
through two points will pass in general only a single straight; but
there are exceptional cases where through two points an infinity of
straights can pass.

There is a sort of opposition between Riemann's geometry and that of
Lobachevski.

Thus the sum of the angles of a triangle is:

Equal to two right angles in Euclid's geometry;

Less than two right angles in that of Lobachevski;

Greater than two right angles in that of Riemann.

The number of straights through a given point that can be drawn coplanar
to a given straight, but nowhere meeting it, is equal:

To one in Euclid's geometry;

To zero in that of Riemann;

To infinity in that of Lobachevski.

Add that Riemann's space is finite, although unbounded, in the sense
given above to these two words.

THE SURFACES OF CONSTANT CURVATURE.--One objection still remained
possible. The theorems of Lobachevski and of Riemann present no
contradiction; but however numerous the consequences these two geometers
have drawn from their hypotheses, they must have stopped before
exhausting them, since their number would be infinite; who can say then
that if they had pushed their deductions farther they would not have
eventually reached some contradiction?

This difficulty does not exist for Riemann's geometry, provided it is
limited to two dimensions; in fact, as we have seen, two-dimensional
Riemannian geometry does not differ from spherical geometry, which is
only a branch of ordinary geometry, and consequently is beyond all
discussion.

Beltrami, in correlating likewise Lobachevski's two-dimensional geometry
with a branch of ordinary geometry, has equally refuted the objection so
far as it is concerned.

Here is how he accomplished it. Consider any figure on a surface.
Imagine this figure traced on a flexible and inextensible canvas applied
over this surface in such a way that when the canvas is displaced and
deformed, the various lines of this figure can change their form without
changing their length. In general, this flexible and inextensible figure
can not be displaced without leaving the surface; but there are certain
particular surfaces for which such a movement would be possible; these
are the surfaces of constant curvature.

If we resume the comparison made above and imagine beings without
thickness living on one of these surfaces, they will regard as possible
the motion of a figure all of whose lines remain constant in length. On
the contrary, such a movement would appear absurd to animals without
thickness living on a surface of variable curvature.

These surfaces of constant curvature are of two sorts: Some are of
_positive curvature_, and can be deformed so as to be applied over a
sphere. The geometry of these surfaces reduces itself therefore to the
spherical geometry, which is that of Riemann.

The others are of _negative curvature_. Beltrami has shown that the
geometry of these surfaces is none other than that of Lobachevski. The
two-dimensional geometries of Riemann and Lobachevski are thus
correlated to the Euclidean geometry.

INTERPRETATION OF NON-EUCLIDEAN GEOMETRIES.--So vanishes the objection
so far as two-dimensional geometries are concerned.

It would be easy to extend Beltrami's reasoning to three-dimensional
geometries. The minds that space of four dimensions does not repel will
see no difficulty in it, but they are few. I prefer therefore to proceed
otherwise.

Consider a certain plane, which I shall call the fundamental plane, and
construct a sort of dictionary, by making correspond each to each a
double series of terms written in two columns, just as correspond in the
ordinary dictionaries the words of two languages whose significance is
the same:

_Space_: Portion of space situated above the fundamental plane.

_Plane_: Sphere cutting the fundamental plane orthogonally.

_Straight_: Circle cutting the fundamental plane orthogonally.

_Sphere_: Sphere.

_Circle_: Circle.

_Angle_: Angle.

_Distance between two points_: Logarithm of the cross ratio of these two
points and the intersections of the fundamental plane with a circle
passing through these two points and cutting it orthogonally. Etc.,
Etc.

Now take Lobachevski's theorems and translate them with the aid of this
dictionary as we translate a German text with the aid of a
German-English dictionary. _We shall thus obtain theorems of the
ordinary geometry._ For example, that theorem of Lobachevski: 'the sum
of the angles of a triangle is less than two right angles' is translated
thus: "If a curvilinear triangle has for sides circle-arcs which
prolonged would cut orthogonally the fundamental plane, the sum of the
angles of this curvilinear triangle will be less than two right angles."
Thus, however far the consequences of Lobachevski's hypotheses are
pushed, they will never lead to a contradiction. In fact, if two of
Lobachevski's theorems were contradictory, it would be the same with the
translations of these two theorems, made by the aid of our dictionary,
but these translations are theorems of ordinary geometry and no one
doubts that the ordinary geometry is free from contradiction. Whence
comes this certainty and is it justified? That is a question I can not
treat here because it would require to be enlarged upon, but which is
very interesting and I think not insoluble.

Nothing remains then of the objection above formulated. This is not all.
Lobachevski's geometry, susceptible of a concrete interpretation, ceases
to be a vain logical exercise and is capable of applications; I have not
the time to speak here of these applications, nor of the aid that Klein
and I have gotten from them for the integration of linear differential
equations.

This interpretation moreover is not unique, and several dictionaries
analogous to the preceding could be constructed, which would enable us
by a simple 'translation' to transform Lobachevski's theorems into
theorems of ordinary geometry.

THE IMPLICIT AXIOMS.--Are the axioms explicitly enunciated in our
treatises the sole foundations of geometry? We may be assured of the
contrary by noticing that after they are successively abandoned there
are still left over some propositions common to the theories of Euclid,
Lobachevski and Riemann. These propositions must rest on premises the
geometers admit without enunciation. It is interesting to try to
disentangle them from the classic demonstrations.

Stuart Mill has claimed that every definition contains an axiom,
because in defining one affirms implicitly the existence of the object
defined. This is going much too far; it is rare that in mathematics a
definition is given without its being followed by the demonstration of
the existence of the object defined, and when this is dispensed with it
is generally because the reader can easily supply it. It must not be
forgotten that the word existence has not the same sense when it refers
to a mathematical entity and when it is a question of a material object.
A mathematical entity exists, provided its definition implies no
contradiction, either in itself, or with the propositions already
admitted.

But if Stuart Mill's observation can not be applied to all definitions,
it is none the less just for some of them. The plane is sometimes
defined as follows:

The plane is a surface such that the straight which joins any two of its
points is wholly on this surface.

This definition manifestly hides a new axiom; it is true we might change
it, and that would be preferable, but then we should have to enunciate
the axiom explicitly.

Other definitions would suggest reflections not less important.

Such, for example, is that of the equality of two figures; two figures
are equal when they can be superposed; to superpose them one must be
displaced until it coincides with the other; but how shall it be
displaced? If we should ask this, no doubt we should be told that it
must be done without altering the shape and as a rigid solid. The
vicious circle would then be evident.

In fact this definition defines nothing; it would have no meaning for a
being living in a world where there were only fluids. If it seems clear
to us, that is because we are used to the properties of natural solids
which do not differ much from those of the ideal solids, all of whose
dimensions are invariable.

Yet, imperfect as it may be, this definition implies an axiom.

The possibility of the motion of a rigid figure is not a self-evident
truth, or at least it is so only in the fashion of Euclid's postulate
and not as an analytic judgment _a priori_ would be.

Moreover, in studying the definitions and the demonstrations of
geometry, we see that one is obliged to admit without proof not only the
possibility of this motion, but some of its properties besides.

This is at once seen from the definition of the straight line. Many
defective definitions have been given, but the true one is that which is
implied in all the demonstrations where the straight line enters:

"It may happen that the motion of a rigid figure is such that all the
points of a line belonging to this figure remain motionless while all
the points situated outside of this line move. Such a line will be
called a straight line." We have designedly, in this enunciation,
separated the definition from the axiom it implies.

Many demonstrations, such as those of the cases of the equality of
triangles, of the possibility of dropping a perpendicular from a point
to a straight, presume propositions which are not enunciated, for they
require the admission that it is possible to transport a figure in a
certain way in space.

THE FOURTH GEOMETRY.--Among these implicit axioms, there is one which
seems to me to merit some attention, because when it is abandoned a
fourth geometry can be constructed as coherent as those of Euclid,
Lobachevski and Riemann.

To prove that a perpendicular may always be erected at a point _A_ to a
straight _AB_, we consider a straight _AC_ movable around the point _A_
and initially coincident with the fixed straight _AB_; and we make it
turn about the point _A_ until it comes into the prolongation of _AB_.

Thus two propositions are presupposed: First, that such a rotation is
possible, and next that it may be continued until the two straights come
into the prolongation one of the other.

If the first point is admitted and the second rejected, we are led to a
series of theorems even stranger than those of Lobachevski and Riemann,
but equally exempt from contradiction.

I shall cite only one of these theorems and that not the most singular:
_A real straight may be perpendicular to itself_.

LIE'S THEOREM.--The number of axioms implicitly introduced in the
classic demonstrations is greater than necessary, and it would be
interesting to reduce it to a minimum. It may first be asked whether
this reduction is possible, whether the number of necessary axioms and
that of imaginable geometries are not infinite.

A theorem of Sophus Lie dominates this whole discussion. It may be thus
enunciated:

Suppose the following premises are admitted:

1º Space has _n_ dimensions;

2º The motion of a rigid figure is possible;

3º It requires _p_ conditions to determine the position of this figure
in space.

_The number of geometries compatible with these premises will be
limited._

I may even add that if _n_ is given, a superior limit can be assigned to
_p_.

If therefore the possibility of motion is admitted, there can be
invented only a finite (and even a rather small) number of
three-dimensional geometries.

RIEMANN'S GEOMETRIES.--Yet this result seems contradicted by Riemann,
for this savant constructs an infinity of different geometries, and that
to which his name is ordinarily given is only a particular case.

All depends, he says, on how the length of a curve is defined. Now,
there is an infinity of ways of defining this length, and each of them
may be the starting point of a new geometry.

That is perfectly true, but most of these definitions are incompatible
with the motion of a rigid figure, which in the theorem of Lie is
supposed possible. These geometries of Riemann, in many ways so
interesting, could never therefore be other than purely analytic and
would not lend themselves to demonstrations analogous to those of
Euclid.

ON THE NATURE OF AXIOMS.--Most mathematicians regard Lobachevski's
geometry only as a mere logical curiosity; some of them, however, have
gone farther. Since several geometries are possible, is it certain ours
is the true one? Experience no doubt teaches us that the sum of the
angles of a triangle is equal to two right angles; but this is because
the triangles we deal with are too little; the difference, according to
Lobachevski, is proportional to the surface of the triangle; will it not
perhaps become sensible when we shall operate on larger triangles or
when our measurements shall become more precise? The Euclidean geometry
would thus be only a provisional geometry.

To discuss this opinion, we should first ask ourselves what is the
nature of the geometric axioms.

Are they synthetic _a priori_ judgments, as Kant said?

They would then impose themselves upon us with such force that we could
not conceive the contrary proposition, nor build upon it a theoretic
edifice. There would be no non-Euclidean geometry.

To be convinced of it take a veritable synthetic _a priori_ judgment,
the following, for instance, of which we have seen the preponderant rôle
in the first chapter:

_If a theorem is true for the number 1, and if it has been proved that
it is true of n + 1 provided it is true of n, it will be true of all the
positive whole numbers._

Then try to escape from that and, denying this proposition, try to found
a false arithmetic analogous to non-Euclidean geometry--it can not be
done; one would even be tempted at first blush to regard these judgments
as analytic.

Moreover, resuming our fiction of animals without thickness, we can
hardly admit that these beings, if their minds are like ours, would
adopt the Euclidean geometry which would be contradicted by all their
experience.

Should we therefore conclude that the axioms of geometry are
experimental verities? But we do not experiment on ideal straights or
circles; it can only be done on material objects. On what then could be
based experiments which should serve as foundation for geometry? The
answer is easy.

We have seen above that we constantly reason as if the geometric figures
behaved like solids. What geometry would borrow from experience would
therefore be the properties of these bodies. The properties of light and
its rectilinear propagation have also given rise to some of the
propositions of geometry, and in particular those of projective
geometry, so that from this point of view one would be tempted to say
that metric geometry is the study of solids, and projective, that of
light.

But a difficulty remains, and it is insurmountable. If geometry were an
experimental science, it would not be an exact science, it would be
subject to a continual revision. Nay, it would from this very day be
convicted of error, since we know that there is no rigorously rigid
solid.

The _axioms of geometry therefore are neither synthetic_ a priori
_judgments nor experimental facts_.

They are _conventions_; our choice among all possible conventions is
_guided_ by experimental facts; but it remains _free_ and is limited
only by the necessity of avoiding all contradiction. Thus it is that the
postulates can remain _rigorously_ true even though the experimental
laws which have determined their adoption are only approximative.

In other words, _the axioms of geometry_ (I do not speak of those of
arithmetic) _are merely disguised definitions_.

Then what are we to think of that question: Is the Euclidean geometry
true?

It has no meaning.

As well ask whether the metric system is true and the old measures
false; whether Cartesian coordinates are true and polar coordinates
false. One geometry can not be more true than another; it can only be
_more convenient_.

Now, Euclidean geometry is, and will remain, the most convenient:

1º Because it is the simplest; and it is so not only in consequence of
our mental habits, or of I know not what direct intuition that we may
have of Euclidean space; it is the simplest in itself, just as a
polynomial of the first degree is simpler than one of the second; the
formulas of spherical trigonometry are more complicated than those of
plane trigonometry, and they would still appear so to an analyst
ignorant of their geometric signification.

2º Because it accords sufficiently well with the properties of natural
solids, those bodies which our hands and our eyes compare and with which
we make our instruments of measure.



CHAPTER IV

SPACE AND GEOMETRY


Let us begin by a little paradox.

Beings with minds like ours, and having the same senses as we, but
without previous education, would receive from a suitably chosen
external world impressions such that they would be led to construct a
geometry other than that of Euclid and to localize the phenomena of that
external world in a non-Euclidean space, or even in a space of four
dimensions.

As for us, whose education has been accomplished by our actual world, if
we were suddenly transported into this new world, we should have no
difficulty in referring its phenomena to our Euclidean space.
Conversely, if these beings were transported into our environment, they
would be led to relate our phenomena to non-Euclidean space.

Nay more; with a little effort we likewise could do it. A person who
should devote his existence to it might perhaps attain to a realization
of the fourth dimension.

GEOMETRIC SPACE AND PERCEPTUAL SPACE.--It is often said the images of
external objects are localized in space, even that they can not be
formed except on this condition. It is also said that this space, which
serves thus as a ready prepared _frame_ for our sensations and our
representations, is identical with that of the geometers, of which it
possesses all the properties.

To all the good minds who think thus, the preceding statement must have
appeared quite extraordinary. But let us see whether they are not
subject to an illusion that a more profound analysis would dissipate.

What, first of all, are the properties of space, properly so called? I
mean of that space which is the object of geometry and which I shall
call _geometric space_.

The following are some of the most essential:

1º It is continuous;

2º It is infinite;

3º It has three dimensions;

4º It is homogeneous, that is to say, all its points are identical one
with another;

5º It is isotropic, that is to say, all the straights which pass through
the same point are identical one with another.

Compare it now to the frame of our representations and our sensations,
which I may call _perceptual space_.

VISUAL SPACE.--Consider first a purely visual impression, due to an
image formed on the bottom of the retina.

A cursory analysis shows us this image as continuous, but as possessing
only two dimensions; this already distinguishes from geometric space
what we may call _pure visual space_.

Besides, this image is enclosed in a limited frame.

Finally, there is another difference not less important: _this pure
visual space is not homogeneous_. All the points of the retina, aside
from the images which may there be formed, do not play the same rôle.
The yellow spot can in no way be regarded as identical with a point on
the border of the retina. In fact, not only does the same object produce
there much more vivid impressions, but in every _limited_ frame the
point occupying the center of the frame will never appear as equivalent
to a point near one of the borders.

No doubt a more profound analysis would show us that this continuity of
visual space and its two dimensions are only an illusion; it would
separate it therefore still more from geometric space, but we shall not
dwell on this remark.

Sight, however, enables us to judge of distances and consequently to
perceive a third dimension. But every one knows that this perception of
the third dimension reduces itself to the sensation of the effort at
accommodation it is necessary to make, and to that of the convergence
which must be given to the two eyes, to perceive an object distinctly.

These are muscular sensations altogether different from the visual
sensations which have given us the notion of the first two dimensions.
The third dimension therefore will not appear to us as playing the same
rôle as the other two. What may be called _complete visual space_ is
therefore not an isotropic space.

It has, it is true, precisely three dimensions, which means that the
elements of our visual sensations (those at least which combine to form
the notion of extension) will be completely defined when three of them
are known; to use the language of mathematics, they will be functions of
three independent variables.

But examine the matter a little more closely. The third dimension is
revealed to us in two different ways: by the effort of accommodation and
by the convergence of the eyes.

No doubt these two indications are always concordant, there is a
constant relation between them, or, in mathematical terms, the two
variables which measure these two muscular sensations do not appear to
us as independent; or again, to avoid an appeal to mathematical notions
already rather refined, we may go back to the language of the preceding
chapter and enunciate the same fact as follows: If two sensations of
convergence, _A_ and _B_, are indistinguishable, the two sensations of
accommodation, _A'_ and _B'_, which respectively accompany them, will be
equally indistinguishable.

But here we have, so to speak, an experimental fact; _a priori_ nothing
prevents our supposing the contrary, and if the contrary takes place, if
these two muscular sensations vary independently of one another, we
shall have to take account of one more independent variable, and
'complete visual space' will appear to us as a physical continuum of
four dimensions.

We have here even, I will add, a fact of _external_ experience. Nothing
prevents our supposing that a being with a mind like ours, having the
same sense organs that we have, may be placed in a world where light
would only reach him after having traversed reflecting media of
complicated form. The two indications which serve us in judging
distances would cease to be connected by a constant relation. A being
who should achieve in such a world the education of his senses would no
doubt attribute four dimensions to complete visual space.

TACTILE SPACE AND MOTOR SPACE.--'Tactile space' is still more
complicated than visual space and farther removed from geometric space.
It is superfluous to repeat for touch the discussion I have given for
sight.

But apart from the data of sight and touch, there are other sensations
which contribute as much and more than they to the genesis of the notion
of space. These are known to every one; they accompany all our
movements, and are usually called muscular sensations.

The corresponding frame constitutes what may be called _motor space_.

Each muscle gives rise to a special sensation capable of augmenting or
of diminishing, so that the totality of our muscular sensations will
depend upon as many variables as we have muscles. From this point of
view, _motor space would have as many dimensions as we have muscles_.

I know it will be said that if the muscular sensations contribute to
form the notion of space, it is because we have the sense of the
_direction_ of each movement and that it makes an integrant part of the
sensation. If this were so, if a muscular sensation could not arise
except accompanied by this geometric sense of direction, geometric space
would indeed be a form imposed upon our sensibility.

But I perceive nothing at all of this when I analyze my sensations.

What I do see is that the sensations which correspond to movements in
the same direction are connected in my mind by a mere _association of
ideas_. It is to this association that what we call 'the sense of
direction' is reducible. This feeling therefore can not be found in a
single sensation.

This association is extremely complex, for the contraction of the same
muscle may correspond, according to the position of the limbs, to
movements of very different direction.

Besides, it is evidently acquired; it is, like all associations of
ideas, the result of a _habit_; this habit itself results from very
numerous _experiences_; without any doubt, if the education of our
senses had been accomplished in a different environment, where we should
have been subjected to different impressions, contrary habits would have
arisen and our muscular sensations would have been associated according
to other laws.

CHARACTERISTICS OF PERCEPTUAL SPACE.--Thus perceptual space, under its
triple form, visual, tactile and motor, is essentially different from
geometric space.

It is neither homogeneous, nor isotropic; one can not even say that it
has three dimensions.

It is often said that we 'project' into geometric space the objects of
our external perception; that we 'localize' them.

Has this a meaning, and if so what?

Does it mean that we _represent_ to ourselves external objects in
geometric space?

Our representations are only the reproduction of our sensations; they
can therefore be ranged only in the same frame as these, that is to say,
in perceptual space.

It is as impossible for us to represent to ourselves external bodies in
geometric space, as it is for a painter to paint on a plane canvas
objects with their three dimensions.

Perceptual space is only an image of geometric space, an image altered
in shape by a sort of perspective, and we can represent to ourselves
objects only by bringing them under the laws of this perspective.

Therefore we do not _represent_ to ourselves external bodies in
geometric space, but we _reason_ on these bodies as if they were
situated in geometric space.

When it is said then that we 'localize' such and such an object at such
and such a point of space, what does it mean?

_It simply means that we represent to ourselves the movements it would
be necessary to make to reach that object_; and one may not say that to
represent to oneself these movements, it is necessary to project the
movements themselves in space and that the notion of space must,
consequently, pre-exist.

When I say that we represent to ourselves these movements, I mean only
that we represent to ourselves the muscular sensations which accompany
them and which have no geometric character whatever, which consequently
do not at all imply the preexistence of the notion of space.

CHANGE OF STATE AND CHANGE OF POSITION.--But, it will be said, if the
idea of geometric space is not imposed upon our mind, and if, on the
other hand, none of our sensations can furnish it, how could it have
come into existence?

This is what we have now to examine, and it will take some time, but I
can summarize in a few words the attempt at explanation that I am about
to develop.

_None of our sensations, isolated, could have conducted us to the idea
of space; we are led to it only in studying the laws, according to which
these sensations succeed each other._

We see first that our impressions are subject to change; but among the
changes we ascertain we are soon led to make a distinction.

At one time we say that the objects which cause these impressions have
changed state, at another time that they have changed position, that
they have only been displaced.

Whether an object changes its state or merely its position, this is
always translated for us in the same manner: _by a modification in an
aggregate of impressions_.

How then could we have been led to distinguish between the two? It is
easy to account for. If there has only been a change of position, we can
restore the primitive aggregate of impressions by making movements which
replace us opposite the mobile object in the same _relative_ situation.
We thus _correct_ the modification that happened and we reestablish the
initial state by an inverse modification.

If it is a question of sight, for example, and if an object changes its
place before our eye, we can 'follow it with the eye' and maintain its
image on the same point of the retina by appropriate movements of the
eyeball.

These movements we are conscious of because they are voluntary and
because they are accompanied by muscular sensations, but that does not
mean that we represent them to ourselves in geometric space.

So what characterizes change of position, what distinguishes it from
change of state, is that it can always be corrected in this way.

It may therefore happen that we pass from the totality of impressions
_A_ to the totality _B_ in two different ways:

1º Involuntarily and without experiencing muscular sensations; this
happens when it is the object which changes place;

2° Voluntarily and with muscular sensations; this happens when the
object is motionless, but we move so that the object has relative motion
with reference to us.

If this be so, the passage from the totality _A_ to the totality _B_ is
only a change of position.

It follows from this that sight and touch could not have given us the
notion of space without the aid of the 'muscular sense.'

Not only could this notion not be derived from a single sensation or
even _from a series of sensations_, but what is more, an _immobile_
being could never have acquired it, since, not being able to _correct_
by his movements the effects of the changes of position of exterior
objects, he would have had no reason whatever to distinguish them from
changes of state. Just as little could he have acquired it if his
motions had not been voluntary or were unaccompanied by any sensations.

CONDITIONS OF COMPENSATION.--How is a like compensation possible, of
such sort that two changes, otherwise independent of each other,
reciprocally correct each other?

A mind already familiar with geometry would reason as follows:
Evidently, if there is to be compensation, the various parts of the
external object, on the one hand, and the various sense organs, on the
other hand, must be in the same _relative_ position after the double
change. And, for that to be the case, the various parts of the external
object must likewise have retained in reference to each other the same
relative position, and the same must be true of the various parts of our
body in regard to each other.

In other words, the external object, in the first change, must be
displaced as is a rigid solid, and so must it be with the whole of our
body in the second change which corrects the first.

Under these conditions, compensation may take place.

But we who as yet know nothing of geometry, since for us the notion of
space is not yet formed, we can not reason thus, we can not foresee _a
priori_ whether compensation is possible. But experience teaches us that
it sometimes happens, and it is from this experimental fact that we
start to distinguish changes of state from changes of position.

SOLID BODIES AND GEOMETRY.--Among surrounding objects there are some
which frequently undergo displacements susceptible of being thus
corrected by a correlative movement of our own body; these are the
_solid bodies_. The other objects, whose form is variable, only
exceptionally undergo like displacements (change of position without
change of form). When a body changes its place _and its shape_, we can
no longer, by appropriate movements, bring back our sense-organs into
the same _relative_ situation with regard to this body; consequently we
can no longer reestablish the primitive totality of impressions.

It is only later, and as a consequence of new experiences, that we learn
how to decompose the bodies of variable form into smaller elements, such
that each is displaced almost in accordance with the same laws as solid
bodies. Thus we distinguish 'deformations' from other changes of state;
in these deformations, each element undergoes a mere change of position,
which can be corrected, but the modification undergone by the aggregate
is more profound and is no longer susceptible of correction by a
correlative movement.

Such a notion is already very complex and must have been relatively late
in appearing; moreover it could not have arisen if the observation of
solid bodies had not already taught us to distinguish changes of
position.

_Therefore, if there were no solid bodies in nature, there would be no
geometry._

Another remark also deserves a moment's attention. Suppose a solid body
to occupy successively the positions [alpha] and [beta]; in its first
position, it will produce on us the totality of impressions _A_, and in
its second position the totality of impressions _B_. Let there be now a
second solid body, having qualities entirely different from the first,
for example, a different color. Suppose it to pass from the position
[alpha], where it gives us the totality of impressions _A'_, to the
position [beta], where it gives the totality of impressions _B'_.

In general, the totality _A_ will have nothing in common with the
totality _A'_, nor the totality _B_ with the totality _B'_. The
transition from the totality _A_ to the totality _B_ and that from the
totality _A'_ to the totality _B'_ are therefore two changes which _in
themselves_ have in general nothing in common.

And yet we regard these two changes both as displacements and,
furthermore, we consider them as the _same_ displacement. How can that
be?

It is simply because they can both be corrected by the _same_
correlative movement of our body.

'Correlative movement' therefore constitutes the _sole connection_
between two phenomena which otherwise we never should have dreamt of
likening.

On the other hand, our body, thanks to the number of its articulations
and muscles, may make a multitude of different movements; but all are
not capable of 'correcting' a modification of external objects; only
those will be capable of it in which our whole body, or at least all
those of our sense-organs which come into play, are displaced as a
whole, that is, without their relative positions varying, or in the
fashion of a solid body.

To summarize:

1º We are led at first to distinguish two categories of phenomena:

Some, involuntary, unaccompanied by muscular sensations, are attributed
by us to external objects; these are external changes;

Others, opposite in character and attributed by us to the movements of
our own body, are internal changes;

2º We notice that certain changes of each of these categories may be
corrected by a correlative change of the other category;

3º We distinguish among external changes those which have thus a
correlative in the other category; these we call displacements; and just
so among the internal changes, we distinguish those which have a
correlative in the first category.

Thus are defined, thanks to this reciprocity, a particular class of
phenomena which we call displacements.

_The laws of these phenomena constitute the object of geometry._

LAW OF HOMOGENEITY.--The first of these laws is the law of homogeneity.

Suppose that, by an external change [alpha], we pass from the totality
of impressions _A_ to the totality _B_, then that this change [alpha] is
corrected by a correlative voluntary movement [beta], so that we are
brought back to the totality _A_.

Suppose now that another external change [alpha]' makes us pass anew
from the totality _A_ to the totality _B_.

Experience teaches us that this change [alpha]' is, like [alpha],
susceptible of being corrected by a correlative voluntary movement
[beta]' and that this movement [beta]' corresponds to the same muscular
sensations as the movement [beta] which corrected [alpha].

This fact is usually enunciated by saying that _space is homogeneous and
isotropic_.

It may also be said that a movement which has once been produced may be
repeated a second and a third time, and so on, without its properties
varying.

In the first chapter, where we discussed the nature of mathematical
reasoning, we saw the importance which must be attributed to the
possibility of repeating indefinitely the same operation.

It is from this repetition that mathematical reasoning gets its power;
it is, therefore, thanks to the law of homogeneity, that it has a hold
on the geometric facts.

For completeness, to the law of homogeneity should be added a multitude
of other analogous laws, into the details of which I do not wish to
enter, but which mathematicians sum up in a word by saying that
displacements form 'a group.'

THE NON-EUCLIDEAN WORLD.--If geometric space were a frame imposed on
_each_ of our representations, considered individually, it would be
impossible to represent to ourselves an image stripped of this frame,
and we could change nothing of our geometry.

But this is not the case; geometry is only the résumé of the laws
according to which these images succeed each other. Nothing then
prevents us from imagining a series of representations, similar in all
points to our ordinary representations, but succeeding one another
according to laws different from those to which we are accustomed.

We can conceive then that beings who received their education in an
environment where these laws were thus upset might have a geometry very
different from ours.

Suppose, for example, a world enclosed in a great sphere and subject to
the following laws:

The temperature is not uniform; it is greatest at the center, and
diminishes in proportion to the distance from the center, to sink to
absolute zero when the sphere is reached in which this world is
enclosed.

To specify still more precisely the law in accordance with which this
temperature varies: Let _R_ be the radius of the limiting sphere;
let _r_ be the distance of the point considered from the center
of this sphere. The absolute temperature shall be proportional
to _R_^{2} - _r_^{2}.

I shall further suppose that, in this world, all bodies have the same
coefficient of dilatation, so that the length of any rule is
proportional to its absolute temperature.

Finally, I shall suppose that a body transported from one point to
another of different temperature is put immediately into thermal
equilibrium with its new environment.

Nothing in these hypotheses is contradictory or unimaginable.

A movable object will then become smaller and smaller in proportion as
it approaches the limit-sphere.

Note first that, though this world is limited from the point of view of
our ordinary geometry, it will appear infinite to its inhabitants.

In fact, when these try to approach the limit-sphere, they cool off and
become smaller and smaller. Therefore the steps they take are also
smaller and smaller, so that they can never reach the limiting sphere.

If, for us, geometry is only the study of the laws according to which
rigid solids move, for these imaginary beings it will be the study of
the laws of motion of solids _distorted by the differences of
temperature_ just spoken of.

No doubt, in our world, natural solids likewise undergo variations of
form and volume due to warming or cooling. But we neglect these
variations in laying the foundations of geometry, because, besides their
being very slight, they are irregular and consequently seem to us
accidental.

In our hypothetical world, this would no longer be the case, and these
variations would follow regular and very simple laws.

Moreover, the various solid pieces of which the bodies of its
inhabitants would be composed would undergo the same variations of form
and volume.

I will make still another hypothesis; I will suppose light traverses
media diversely refractive and such that the index of refraction is
inversely proportional to _R_^{2} - _r_^{2}. It is easy to see that,
under these conditions, the rays of light would not be rectilinear, but
circular.

To justify what precedes, it remains for me to show that certain changes
in the position of external objects can be _corrected_ by correlative
movements of the sentient beings inhabiting this imaginary world, and
that in such a way as to restore the primitive aggregate of impressions
experienced by these sentient beings.

Suppose in fact that an object is displaced, undergoing deformation, not
as a rigid solid, but as a solid subjected to unequal dilatations in
exact conformity to the law of temperature above supposed. Permit me for
brevity to call such a movement a _non-Euclidean displacement_.

If a sentient being happens to be in the neighborhood, his impressions
will be modified by the displacement of the object, but he can
reestablish them by moving in a suitable manner. It suffices if finally
the aggregate of the object and the sentient being, considered as
forming a single body, has undergone one of those particular
displacements I have just called non-Euclidean. This is possible if it
be supposed that the limbs of these beings dilate according to the same
law as the other bodies of the world they inhabit.

Although from the point of view of our ordinary geometry there is a
deformation of the bodies in this displacement and their various parts
are no longer in the same relative position, nevertheless we shall see
that the impressions of the sentient being have once more become the
same.

In fact, though the mutual distances of the various parts may have
varied, yet the parts originally in contact are again in contact.
Therefore the tactile impressions have not changed.

On the other hand, taking into account the hypothesis made above in
regard to the refraction and the curvature of the rays of light, the
visual impressions will also have remained the same.

These imaginary beings will therefore like ourselves be led to classify
the phenomena they witness and to distinguish among them the 'changes of
position' susceptible of correction by a correlative voluntary movement.

If they construct a geometry, it will not be, as ours is, the study of
the movements of our rigid solids; it will be the study of the changes
of position which they will thus have distinguished and which are none
other than the 'non-Euclidean displacements'; _it will be non-Euclidean
geometry_.

Thus beings like ourselves, educated in such a world, would not have the
same geometry as ours.

THE WORLD OF FOUR DIMENSIONS.--We can represent to ourselves a
four-dimensional world just as well as a non-Euclidean.

The sense of sight, even with a single eye, together with the muscular
sensations relative to the movements of the eyeball, would suffice to
teach us space of three dimensions.

The images of external objects are painted on the retina, which is a
two-dimensional canvas; they are _perspectives_.

But, as eye and objects are movable, we see in succession various
perspectives of the same body, taken from different points of view.

At the same time, we find that the transition from one perspective to
another is often accompanied by muscular sensations.

If the transition from the perspective _A_ to the perspective _B_, and
that from the perspective _A'_ to the perspective _B'_ are accompanied
by the same muscular sensations, we liken them one to the other as
operations of the same nature.

Studying then the laws according to which these operations combine, we
recognize that they form a group, which has the same structure as that
of the movements of rigid solids.

Now, we have seen that it is from the properties of this group we have
derived the notion of geometric space and that of three dimensions.

We understand thus how the idea of a space of three dimensions could
take birth from the pageant of these perspectives, though each of them
is of only two dimensions, since _they follow one another according to
certain laws_.

Well, just as the perspective of a three-dimensional figure can be made
on a plane, we can make that of a four-dimensional figure on a picture
of three (or of two) dimensions. To a geometer this is only child's
play.

We can even take of the same figure several perspectives from several
different points of view.

We can easily represent to ourselves these perspectives, since they are
of only three dimensions.

Imagine that the various perspectives of the same object succeed one
another, and that the transition from one to the other is accompanied by
muscular sensations.

We shall of course consider two of these transitions as two operations
of the same nature when they are associated with the same muscular
sensations.

Nothing then prevents us from imagining that these operations combine
according to any law we choose, for example, so as to form a group with
the same structure as that of the movements of a rigid solid of four
dimensions.

Here there is nothing unpicturable, and yet these sensations are
precisely those which would be felt by a being possessed of a
two-dimensional retina who could move in space of four dimensions. In
this sense we may say the fourth dimension is imaginable.

CONCLUSIONS.--We see that experience plays an indispensable rôle in the
genesis of geometry; but it would be an error thence to conclude that
geometry is, even in part, an experimental science.

If it were experimental, it would be only approximative and provisional.
And what rough approximation!

Geometry would be only the study of the movements of solids; but in
reality it is not occupied with natural solids, it has for object
certain ideal solids, absolutely rigid, which are only a simplified and
very remote image of natural solids.

The notion of these ideal solids is drawn from all parts of our mind,
and experience is only an occasion which induces us to bring it forth
from them.

The object of geometry is the study of a particular 'group'; but the
general group concept pre-exists, at least potentially, in our minds. It
is imposed on us, not as form of our sense, but as form of our
understanding.

Only, from among all the possible groups, that must be chosen which will
be, so to speak, the _standard_ to which we shall refer natural
phenomena.

Experience guides us in this choice without forcing it upon us; it
tells us not which is the truest geometry, but which is the most
_convenient_.

Notice that I have been able to describe the fantastic worlds above
imagined _without ceasing to employ the language of ordinary geometry_.

And, in fact, we should not have to change it if transported thither.

Beings educated there would doubtless find it more convenient to create
a geometry different from ours, and better adapted to their impressions.
As for us, in face of the _same_ impressions, it is certain we should
find it more convenient not to change our habits.



CHAPTER V

EXPERIENCE AND GEOMETRY


1. Already in the preceding pages I have several times tried to show
that the principles of geometry are not experimental facts and that in
particular Euclid's postulate can not be proven experimentally.

However decisive appear to me the reasons already given, I believe I
should emphasize this point because here a false idea is profoundly
rooted in many minds.

2. If we construct a material circle, measure its radius and
circumference, and see if the ratio of these two lengths is equal to
[pi], what shall we have done? We shall have made an experiment on the
properties of the matter with which we constructed this _round thing_,
and of that of which the measure used was made.

3. GEOMETRY AND ASTRONOMY.--The question has also been put in another
way. If Lobachevski's geometry is true, the parallax of a very distant
star will be finite; if Riemann's is true, it will be negative. These
are results which seem within the reach of experiment, and there have
been hopes that astronomical observations might enable us to decide
between the three geometries.

But in astronomy 'straight line' means simply 'path of a ray of light.'

If therefore negative parallaxes were found, or if it were demonstrated
that all parallaxes are superior to a certain limit, two courses would
be open to us; we might either renounce Euclidean geometry, or else
modify the laws of optics and suppose that light does not travel
rigorously in a straight line.

It is needless to add that all the world would regard the latter
solution as the more advantageous.

The Euclidean geometry has, therefore, nothing to fear from fresh
experiments.

4. Is the position tenable, that certain phenomena, possible in
Euclidean space, would be impossible in non-Euclidean space, so that
experience, in establishing these phenomena, would directly contradict
the non-Euclidean hypothesis? For my part I think no such question can
be put. To my mind it is precisely equivalent to the following, whose
absurdity is patent to all eyes: are there lengths expressible in meters
and centimeters, but which can not be measured in fathoms, feet and
inches, so that experience, in ascertaining the existence of these
lengths, would directly contradict the hypothesis that there are fathoms
divided into six feet?

Examine the question more closely. I suppose that the straight line
possesses in Euclidean space any two properties which I shall call _A_
and _B_; that in non-Euclidean space it still possesses the property
_A_, but no longer has the property _B_; finally I suppose that in both
Euclidean and non-Euclidean space the straight line is the only line
having the property _A_.

If this were so, experience would be capable of deciding between the
hypothesis of Euclid and that of Lobachevski. It would be ascertained
that a definite concrete object, accessible to experiment, for example,
a pencil of rays of light, possesses the property _A_; we should
conclude that it is rectilinear, and then investigate whether or not it
has the property _B_.

But _this is not so_; no property exists which, like this property _A_,
can be an absolute criterion enabling us to recognize the straight line
and to distinguish it from every other line.

Shall we say, for instance: "the following is such a property: the
straight line is a line such that a figure of which this line forms a
part can be moved without the mutual distances of its points varying and
so that all points of this line remain fixed"?

This, in fact, is a property which, in Euclidean or non-Euclidean space,
belongs to the straight and belongs only to it. But how shall we
ascertain experimentally whether it belongs to this or that concrete
object? It will be necessary to measure distances, and how shall one
know that any concrete magnitude which I have measured with my material
instrument really represents the abstract distance?

We have only pushed back the difficulty.

In reality the property just enunciated is not a property of the
straight line alone, it is a property of the straight line and
distance. For it to serve as absolute criterion, we should have to be
able to establish not only that it does not also belong to a line other
than the straight and to distance, but in addition that it does not
belong to a line other than the straight and to a magnitude other than
distance. Now this is not true.

It is therefore impossible to imagine a concrete experiment which can be
interpreted in the Euclidean system and not in the Lobachevskian system,
so that I may conclude:

No experience will ever be in contradiction to Euclid's postulate; nor,
on the other hand, will any experience ever contradict the postulate of
Lobachevski.

5. But it is not enough that the Euclidean (or non-Euclidean) geometry
can never be directly contradicted by experience. Might it not happen
that it can accord with experience only by violating the principle of
sufficient reason or that of the relativity of space?

I will explain myself: consider any material system; we shall have to
regard, on the one hand, 'the state' of the various bodies of this
system (for instance, their temperature, their electric potential,
etc.), and, on the other hand, their position in space; and among the
data which enable us to define this position we shall, moreover,
distinguish the mutual distances of these bodies, which define their
relative positions, from the conditions which define the absolute
position of the system and its absolute orientation in space.

The laws of the phenomena which will happen in this system will depend
on the state of these bodies and their mutual distances; but, because of
the relativity and passivity of space, they will not depend on the
absolute position and orientation of the system.

In other words, the state of the bodies and their mutual distances at
any instant will depend solely on the state of these same bodies and on
their mutual distances at the initial instant, but will not at all
depend on the absolute initial position of the system or on its absolute
initial orientation. This is what for brevity I shall call the _law of
relativity_.

Hitherto I have spoken as a Euclidean geometer. As I have said, an
experience, whatever it be, admits of an interpretation on the Euclidean
hypothesis; but it admits of one equally on the non-Euclidean
hypothesis. Well, we have made a series of experiments; we have
interpreted them on the Euclidean hypothesis, and we have recognized
that these experiments thus interpreted do not violate this 'law of
relativity.'

We now interpret them on the non-Euclidean hypothesis: this is always
possible; only the non-Euclidean distances of our different bodies in
this new interpretation will not generally be the same as the Euclidean
distances in the primitive interpretation.

Will our experiments, interpreted in this new manner, still be in accord
with our 'law of relativity'? And if there were not this accord, should
we not have also the right to say experience had proven the falsity of
the non-Euclidean geometry?

It is easy to see that this is an idle fear; in fact, to apply the law
of relativity in all rigor, it must be applied to the entire universe.
For if only a part of this universe were considered, and if the absolute
position of this part happened to vary, the distances to the other
bodies of the universe would likewise vary, their influence on the part
of the universe considered would consequently augment or diminish, which
might modify the laws of the phenomena happening there.

But if our system is the entire universe, experience is powerless to
give information about its absolute position and orientation in space.
All that our instruments, however perfected they may be, can tell us
will be the state of the various parts of the universe and their mutual
distances.

So our law of relativity may be thus enunciated:

The readings we shall be able to make on our instruments at any instant
will depend only on the readings we could have made on these same
instruments at the initial instant.

Now such an enunciation is independent of every interpretation of
experimental facts. If the law is true in the Euclidean interpretation,
it will also be true in the non-Euclidean interpretation.

Allow me here a short digression. I have spoken above of the data which
define the position of the various bodies of the system; I should
likewise have spoken of those which define their velocities; I should
then have had to distinguish the velocities with which the mutual
distances of the different bodies vary; and, on the other hand, the
velocities of translation and rotation of the system, that is to say,
the velocities with which its absolute position and orientation vary.

To fully satisfy the mind, the law of relativity should be expressible
thus:

The state of bodies and their mutual distances at any instant, as well
as the velocities with which these distances vary at this same instant,
will depend only on the state of those bodies and their mutual distances
at the initial instant, and the velocities with which these distances
vary at this initial instant, but they will not depend either upon the
absolute initial position of the system, or upon its absolute
orientation, or upon the velocities with which this absolute position
and orientation varied at the initial instant.

Unhappily the law thus enunciated is not in accord with experiments, at
least as they are ordinarily interpreted.

Suppose a man be transported to a planet whose heavens were always
covered with a thick curtain of clouds, so that he could never see the
other stars; on that planet he would live as if it were isolated in
space. Yet this man could become aware that it turned, either by
measuring its oblateness (done ordinarily by the aid of astronomic
observations, but capable of being done by purely geodetic means), or by
repeating the experiment of Foucault's pendulum. The absolute rotation
of this planet could therefore be made evident.

That is a fact which shocks the philosopher, but which the physicist is
compelled to accept.

We know that from this fact Newton inferred the existence of absolute
space; I myself am quite unable to adopt this view. I shall explain why
in Part III. For the moment it is not my intention to enter upon this
difficulty.

Therefore I must resign myself, in the enunciation of the law of
relativity, to including velocities of every kind among the data which
define the state of the bodies.

However that may be, this difficulty is the same for Euclid's geometry
as for Lobachevski's; I therefore need not trouble myself with it, and
have only mentioned it incidentally.

What is important is the conclusion: experiment can not decide between
Euclid and Lobachevski.

To sum up, whichever way we look at it, it is impossible to discover in
geometric empiricism a rational meaning.

6. Experiments only teach us the relations of bodies to one another;
none of them bears or can bear on the relations of bodies with space, or
on the mutual relations of different parts of space.

"Yes," you reply, "a single experiment is insufficient, because it gives
me only a single equation with several unknowns; but when I shall have
made enough experiments I shall have equations enough to calculate all
my unknowns."

To know the height of the mainmast does not suffice for calculating the
age of the captain. When you have measured every bit of wood in the ship
you will have many equations, but you will know his age no better. All
your measurements bearing only on your bits of wood can reveal to you
nothing except concerning these bits of wood. Just so your experiments,
however numerous they may be, bearing only on the relations of bodies to
one another, will reveal to us nothing about the mutual relations of the
various parts of space.

7. Will you say that if the experiments bear on the bodies, they bear at
least upon the geometric properties of the bodies? But, first, what do
you understand by geometric properties of the bodies? I assume that it
is a question of the relations of the bodies with space; these
properties are therefore inaccessible to experiments which bear only on
the relations of the bodies to one another. This alone would suffice to
show that there can be no question of these properties.

Still let us begin by coming to an understanding about the sense of the
phrase: geometric properties of bodies. When I say a body is composed of
several parts, I assume that I do not enunciate therein a geometric
property, and this would remain true even if I agreed to give the
improper name of points to the smallest parts I consider.

When I say that such a part of such a body is in contact with such a
part of such another body, I enunciate a proposition which concerns the
mutual relations of these two bodies and not their relations with
space.

I suppose you will grant me these are not geometric properties; at least
I am sure you will grant me these properties are independent of all
knowledge of metric geometry.

This presupposed, I imagine that we have a solid body formed of eight
slender iron rods, _OA_, _OB_, _OC_, _OD_, _OE_, _OF_, _OG_, _OH_,
united at one of their extremities _O_. Let us besides have a second
solid body, for example a bit of wood, to be marked with three little
flecks of ink which I shall call [alpha], [beta], [gamma]. I further
suppose it ascertained that [alpha][beta][gamma] may be brought into
contact with _AGO_ (I mean [alpha] with _A_, and at the same time [beta]
with _G_ and [gamma] with _O_), then that we may bring successively into
contact [alpha][beta][gamma] with _BGO_, _CGO_, _DGO_, _EGO_, _FGO_,
then with _AHO_, _BHO_, _CHO_, _DHO_, _EHO_, _FHO_, then [alpha][gamma]
successively with _AB_, _BC_, _CD_, _DE_, _EF_, _FA_.

These are determinations we may make without having in advance any
notion about form or about the metric properties of space. They in no
wise bear on the 'geometric properties of bodies.' And these
determinations will not be possible if the bodies experimented upon move
in accordance with a group having the same structure as the
Lobachevskian group (I mean according to the same laws as solid bodies
in Lobachevski's geometry). They suffice therefore to prove that these
bodies move in accordance with the Euclidean group, or at least that
they do not move according to the Lobachevskian group.

That they are compatible with the Euclidean group is easy to see. For
they could be made if the body [alpha][beta][gamma] was a rigid solid of
our ordinary geometry presenting the form of a right-angled triangle,
and if the points _ABCDEFGH_ were the summits of a polyhedron formed of
two regular hexagonal pyramids of our ordinary geometry, having for
common base _ABCDEF_ and for apices the one _G_ and the other _H_.

Suppose now that in place of the preceding determination it is observed
that as above [alpha][beta][gamma] can be successively applied to _AGO_,
_BGO_, _CGO_, _DGO_, _EGO_, _AHO_, _BHO_, _CHO_, _DHO_, _EHO_, _FHO_,
then that [alpha][beta] (and no longer [alpha][gamma]) can be
successively applied to _AB_, _BC_, _CD_, _DE_, _EF_ and _FA_.

These are determinations which could be made if non-Euclidean geometry
were true, if the bodies [alpha][beta][gamma] and _OABCDEFGH_ were rigid
solids, and if the first were a right-angled triangle and the second a
double regular hexagonal pyramid of suitable dimensions.

Therefore these new determinations are not possible if the bodies move
according to the Euclidean group; but they become so if it be supposed
that the bodies move according to the Lobachevskian group. They would
suffice, therefore (if one made them), to prove that the bodies in
question do not move according to the Euclidean group.

Thus, without making any hypothesis about form, about the nature of
space, about the relations of bodies to space, and without attributing
to bodies any geometric property, I have made observations which have
enabled me to show in one case that the bodies experimented upon move
according to a group whose structure is Euclidean, in the other case
that they move according to a group whose structure is Lobachevskian.

And one may not say that the first aggregate of determinations would
constitute an experiment proving that space is Euclidean, and the second
an experiment proving that space is non-Euclidean.

In fact one could imagine (I say imagine) bodies moving so as to render
possible the second series of determinations. And the proof is that the
first mechanician met could construct such bodies if he cared to take
the pains and make the outlay. You will not conclude from that, however,
that space is non-Euclidean.

Nay, since the ordinary solid bodies would continue to exist when the
mechanician had constructed the strange bodies of which I have just
spoken, it would be necessary to conclude that space is at the same time
Euclidean and non-Euclidean.

Suppose, for example, that we have a great sphere of radius _R_ and that
the temperature decreases from the center to the surface of this sphere
according to the law of which I have spoken in describing the
non-Euclidean world.

We might have bodies whose expansion would be negligible and which would
act like ordinary rigid solids; and, on the other hand, bodies very
dilatable and which would act like non-Euclidean solids. We might have
two double pyramids _OABCDEFGH_ and _O'A'B'C'D'E'F'G'H'_ and two
triangles [alpha][beta][gamma] and [alpha]'[beta]'[gamma]'. The first
double pyramid might be rectilinear and the second curvilinear; the
triangle [alpha][beta][gamma] might be made of inexpansible matter and
the other of a very dilatable matter.

It would then be possible to make the first observations with the double
pyramid _OAH_ and the triangle [alpha][beta][gamma], and the second with
the double pyramid _O'A'H'_ and the triangle [alpha]'[beta]'[gamma]'.
And then experiment would seem to prove first that the Euclidean
geometry is true and then that it is false.

_Experiments therefore have a bearing, not on space, but on bodies._


SUPPLEMENT

8. To complete the matter, I ought to speak of a very delicate question,
which would require long development; I shall confine myself to
summarizing here what I have expounded in the _Revue de Métaphysique et
de Morale_ and in _The Monist_. When we say space has three dimensions,
what do we mean?

We have seen the importance of those 'internal changes' revealed to us
by our muscular sensations. They may serve to characterize the various
_attitudes_ of our body. Take arbitrarily as origin one of these
attitudes _A_. When we pass from this initial attitude to any other
attitude _B_, we feel a series of muscular sensations, and this series
_S_ will define _B_. Observe, however, that we shall often regard two
series _S_ and _S'_ as defining the same attitude _B_ (since the initial
and final attitudes _A_ and _B_ remaining the same, the intermediary
attitudes and the corresponding sensations may differ). How then shall
we recognize the equivalence of these two series? Because they may serve
to compensate the same external change, or more generally because, when
it is a question of compensating an external change, one of the series
can be replaced by the other. Among these series, we have distinguished
those which of themselves alone can compensate an external change, and
which we have called 'displacements.' As we can not discriminate between
two displacements which are too close together, the totality of these
displacements presents the characteristics of a physical continuum;
experience teaches us that they are those of a physical continuum of six
dimensions; but we do not yet know how many dimensions space itself has,
we must first solve another question.

What is a point of space? Everybody thinks he knows, but that is an
illusion. What we see when we try to represent to ourselves a point of
space is a black speck on white paper, a speck of chalk on a blackboard,
always an object. The question should therefore be understood as
follows:

What do I mean when I say the object _B_ is at the same point that the
object _A_ occupied just now? Or further, what criterion will enable me
to apprehend this?

I mean that, _although I have not budged_ (which my muscular sense tells
me), my first finger which just now touched the object _A_ touches at
present the object _B_. I could have used other criteria; for instance
another finger or the sense of sight. But the first criterion is
sufficient; I know that if it answers yes, all the other criteria will
give the same response. I know it _by experience_, I can not know it _a
priori_. For the same reason I say that touch can not be exercised at a
distance; this is another way of enunciating the same experimental fact.
And if, on the contrary, I say that sight acts at a distance, it means
that the criterion furnished by sight may respond yes while the others
reply no.

And in fact, the object, although moved away, may form its image at the
same point of the retina. Sight responds yes, the object has remained at
the same point and touch answers no, because my finger which just now
touched the object, at present touches it no longer. If experience had
shown us that one finger may respond no when the other says yes, we
should likewise say that touch acts at a distance.

In short, for each attitude of my body, my first finger determines a
point, and this it is, and this alone, which defines a point of space.

To each attitude corresponds thus a point; but it often happens that the
same point corresponds to several different attitudes (in this case we
say our finger has not budged, but the rest of the body has moved). We
distinguish, therefore, among the changes of attitude those where the
finger does not budge. How are we led thereto? It is because often we
notice that in these changes the object which is in contact with the
finger remains in contact with it.

Range, therefore, in the same class all the attitudes obtainable from
each other by one of the changes we have thus distinguished. To all the
attitudes of the class will correspond the same point of space.
Therefore to each class will correspond a point and to each point a
class. But one may say that what experience arrives at is not the point,
it is this class of changes or, better, the corresponding class of
muscular sensations.

And when we say space has three dimensions, we simply mean that the
totality of these classes appears to us with the characteristics of a
physical continuum of three dimensions.

One might be tempted to conclude that it is experience which has taught
us how many dimensions space has. But in reality here also our
experiences have bearing, not on space, but on our body and its
relations with the neighboring objects. Moreover they are excessively
crude.

In our mind pre-existed the latent idea of a certain number of
groups--those whose theory Lie has developed. Which group shall we
choose, to make of it a sort of standard with which to compare natural
phenomena? And, this group chosen, which of its sub-groups shall we take
to characterize a point of space? Experience has guided us by showing us
which choice best adapts itself to the properties of our body. But its
rôle is limited to that.


ANCESTRAL EXPERIENCE

It has often been said that if individual experience could not create
geometry the same is not true of ancestral experience. But what does
that mean? Is it meant that we could not experimentally demonstrate
Euclid's postulate, but that our ancestors have been able to do it? Not
in the least. It is meant that by natural selection our mind has
_adapted_ itself to the conditions of the external world, that it has
adopted the geometry _most advantageous_ to the species: or in other
words _the most convenient_. This is entirely in conformity with our
conclusions; geometry is not true, it is advantageous.



PART III


FORCE



CHAPTER VI

THE CLASSIC MECHANICS


The English teach mechanics as an experimental science; on the continent
it is always expounded as more or less a deductive and _a priori_
science. The English are right, that goes without saying; but how could
the other method have been persisted in so long? Why have the
continental savants who have sought to get out of the ruts of their
predecessors been usually unable to free themselves completely?

On the other hand, if the principles of mechanics are only of
experimental origin, are they not therefore only approximate and
provisional? Might not new experiments some day lead us to modify or
even to abandon them?

Such are the questions which naturally obtrude themselves, and the
difficulty of solution comes principally from the fact that the
treatises on mechanics do not clearly distinguish between what is
experiment, what is mathematical reasoning, what is convention, what is
hypothesis.

That is not all:

1º There is no absolute space and we can conceive only of relative
motions; yet usually the mechanical facts are enunciated as if there
were an absolute space to which to refer them.

2º There is no absolute time; to say two durations are equal is an
assertion which has by itself no meaning and which can acquire one only
by convention.

3º Not only have we no direct intuition of the equality of two
durations, but we have not even direct intuition of the simultaneity of
two events occurring in different places: this I have explained in an
article entitled _La mesure du temps_.[3]

  [3] _Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale_, t. VI., pp. 1-13
      (January, 1898).

4º Finally, our Euclidean geometry is itself only a sort of convention
of language; mechanical facts might be enunciated with reference to a
non-Euclidean space which would be a guide less convenient than, but
just as legitimate as, our ordinary space; the enunciation would thus
become much more complicated, but it would remain possible.

Thus absolute space, absolute time, geometry itself, are not conditions
which impose themselves on mechanics; all these things are no more
antecedent to mechanics than the French language is logically antecedent
to the verities one expresses in French.

We might try to enunciate the fundamental laws of mechanics in a
language independent of all these conventions; we should thus without
doubt get a better idea of what these laws are in themselves; this is
what M. Andrade has attempted to do, at least in part, in his _Leçons de
mécanique physique_.

The enunciation of these laws would become of course much more
complicated, because all these conventions have been devised expressly
to abridge and simplify this enunciation.

As for me, save in what concerns absolute space, I shall ignore all
these difficulties; not that I fail to appreciate them, far from that;
but we have sufficiently examined them in the first two parts of the
book.

I shall therefore admit, _provisionally_, absolute time and Euclidean
geometry.

THE PRINCIPLE OF INERTIA.--A body acted on by no force can only move
uniformly in a straight line.

Is this a truth imposed _a priori_ upon the mind? If it were so, how
should the Greeks have failed to recognize it? How could they have
believed that motion stops when the cause which gave birth to it ceases?
Or again that every body if nothing prevents, will move in a circle, the
noblest of motions?

If it is said that the velocity of a body can not change if there is no
reason for it to change, could it not be maintained just as well that
the position of this body can not change, or that the curvature of its
trajectory can not change, if no external cause intervenes to modify
them?

Is the principle of inertia, which is not an _a priori_ truth, therefore
an experimental fact? But has any one ever experimented on bodies
withdrawn from the action of every force? and, if so, how was it known
that these bodies were subjected to no force? The example ordinarily
cited is that of a ball rolling a very long time on a marble table; but
why do we say it is subjected to no force? Is this because it is too
remote from all other bodies to experience any appreciable action from
them? Yet it is not farther from the earth than if it were thrown freely
into the air; and every one knows that in this case it would experience
the influence of gravity due to the attraction of the earth.

Teachers of mechanics usually pass rapidly over the example of the ball;
but they add that the principle of inertia is verified indirectly by its
consequences. They express themselves badly; they evidently mean it is
possible to verify various consequences of a more general principle, of
which that of inertia is only a particular case.

I shall propose for this general principle the following enunciation:

The acceleration of a body depends only upon the position of this body
and of the neighboring bodies and upon their velocities.

Mathematicians would say the movements of all the material molecules of
the universe depend on differential equations of the second order.

To make it clear that this is really the natural generalization of the
law of inertia, I shall beg you to permit me a bit of fiction. The law
of inertia, as I have said above, is not imposed upon us _a priori_;
other laws would be quite as compatible with the principle of sufficient
reason. If a body is subjected to no force, in lieu of supposing its
velocity not to change, it might be supposed that it is its position or
else its acceleration which is not to change.

Well, imagine for an instant that one of these two hypothetical laws is
a law of nature and replaces our law of inertia. What would be its
natural generalization? A moment's thought will show us.

In the first case, we must suppose that the velocity of a body depends
only upon its position and upon that of the neighboring bodies; in the
second case that the change of acceleration of a body depends only upon
the position of this body and of the neighboring bodies, upon their
velocities and upon their accelerations.

Or to speak the language of mathematics, the differential equations of
motion would be of the first order in the first case, and of the third
order in the second case.

Let us slightly modify our fiction. Suppose a world analogous to our
solar system, but where, by a strange chance, the orbits of all the
planets are without eccentricity and without inclination. Suppose
further that the masses of these planets are too slight for their mutual
perturbations to be sensible. Astronomers inhabiting one of these
planets could not fail to conclude that the orbit of a star can only be
circular and parallel to a certain plane; the position of a star at a
given instant would then suffice to determine its velocity and its whole
path. The law of inertia which they would adopt would be the first of
the two hypothetical laws I have mentioned.

Imagine now that this system is some day traversed with great velocity
by a body of vast mass, coming from distant constellations. All the
orbits would be profoundly disturbed. Still our astronomers would not be
too greatly astonished; they would very well divine that this new star
was alone to blame for all the mischief. "But," they would say, "when it
is gone, order will of itself be reestablished; no doubt the distances
of the planets from the sun will not revert to what they were before the
cataclysm, but when the perturbing star is gone, the orbits will again
become circular."

It would only be when the disturbing body was gone and when nevertheless
the orbits, in lieu of again becoming circular, became elliptic, that
these astronomers would become conscious of their error and the
necessity of remaking all their mechanics.

I have dwelt somewhat upon these hypotheses because it seems to me one
can clearly comprehend what our generalized law of inertia really is
only in contrasting it with a contrary hypothesis.

Well, now, has this generalized law of inertia been verified by
experiment, or can it be? When Newton wrote the _Principia_ he quite
regarded this truth as experimentally acquired and demonstrated. It was
so in his eyes, not only through the anthropomorphism of which we shall
speak further on, but through the work of Galileo. It was so even from
Kepler's laws themselves; in accordance with these laws, in fact, the
path of a planet is completely determined by its initial position and
initial velocity; this is just what our generalized law of inertia
requires.

For this principle to be only in appearance true, for one to have cause
to dread having some day to replace it by one of the analogous
principles I have just now contrasted with it, would be necessary our
having been misled by some amazing chance, like that which, in the
fiction above developed, led into error our imaginary astronomers.

Such a hypothesis is too unlikely to delay over. No one will believe
that such coincidences can happen; no doubt the probability of two
eccentricities being both precisely null, to within errors of
observation, is not less than the probability of one being precisely
equal to 0.1, for instance, and the other to 0.2, to within errors of
observation. The probability of a simple event is not less than that of
a complicated event; and yet, if the first happens, we shall not consent
to attribute it to chance; we should not believe that nature had acted
expressly to deceive us. The hypothesis of an error of this sort being
discarded, it may therefore be admitted that in so far as astronomy is
concerned, our law has been verified by experiment.

But astronomy is not the whole of physics.

May we not fear lest some day a new experiment should come to falsify
the law in some domain of physics? An experimental law is always subject
to revision; one should always expect to see it replaced by a more
precise law.

Yet no one seriously thinks that the law we are speaking of will ever be
abandoned or amended. Why? Precisely because it can never be subjected
to a decisive test.

First of all, in order that this trial should be complete, it would be
necessary that after a certain time all the bodies in the universe
should revert to their initial positions with their initial velocities.
It might then be seen whether, starting from this moment, they would
resume their original paths.

But this test is impossible, it can be only partially applied, and,
however well it is made, there will always be some bodies which will not
revert to their initial positions; thus every derogation of the law will
easily find its explanation.

This is not all; in astronomy we _see_ the bodies whose motions we study
and we usually assume that they are not subjected to the action of other
invisible bodies. Under these conditions our law must indeed be either
verified or not verified.

But it is not the same in physics; if the physical phenomena are due to
motions, it is to the motions of molecules which we do not see. If then
the acceleration of one of the bodies we see appears to us to depend on
_something else_ besides the positions or velocities of other visible
bodies or of invisible molecules whose existence we have been previously
led to admit, nothing prevents our supposing that this _something else_
is the position or the velocity of other molecules whose presence we
have not before suspected. The law will find itself safeguarded.

Permit me to employ mathematical language a moment to express the same
thought under another form. Suppose we observe _n_ molecules and
ascertain that their 3_n_ coordinates satisfy a system of 3_n_
differential equations of the fourth order (and not of the second order
as the law of inertia would require). We know that by introducing 3_n_
auxiliary variables, a system of 3_n_ equations of the fourth order can
be reduced to a system of 6_n_ equations of the second order. If then we
suppose these 3_n_ auxiliary variables represent the coordinates of _n_
invisible molecules, the result is again in conformity with the law of
inertia.

To sum up, this law, verified experimentally in some particular cases,
may unhesitatingly be extended to the most general cases, since we know
that in these general cases experiment no longer is able either to
confirm or to contradict it.

THE LAW OF ACCELERATION.--The acceleration of a body is equal to the
force acting on it divided by its mass. Can this law be verified by
experiment? For that it would be necessary to measure the three
magnitudes which figure in the enunciation: acceleration, force and
mass.

I assume that acceleration can be measured, for I pass over the
difficulty arising from the measurement of time. But how measure force,
or mass? We do not even know what they are.

What is _mass_? According to Newton, it is the product of the volume by
the density. According to Thomson and Tait, it would be better to say
that density is the quotient of the mass by the volume. What is _force_?
It is, replies Lagrange, that which moves or tends to move a body. It
is, Kirchhoff will say, the product of the mass by the _acceleration_.
But then, why not say the mass is the quotient of the force by the
acceleration?

These difficulties are inextricable.

When we say force is the cause of motion, we talk metaphysics, and this
definition, if one were content with it, would be absolutely sterile.
For a definition to be of any use, it must teach us to _measure_ force;
moreover that suffices; it is not at all necessary that it teach us what
force is _in itself_, nor whether it is the cause or the effect of
motion.

We must therefore first define the equality of two forces. When shall we
say two forces are equal? It is, we are told, when, applied to the same
mass, they impress upon it the same acceleration, or when, opposed
directly one to the other, they produce equilibrium. This definition is
only a sham. A force applied to a body can not be uncoupled to hook it
up to another body, as one uncouples a locomotive to attach it to
another train. It is therefore impossible to know what acceleration such
a force, applied to such a body, would impress upon such another body,
_if_ it were applied to it. It is impossible to know how two forces
which are not directly opposed would act, _if_ they were directly
opposed.

It is this definition we try to materialize, so to speak, when we
measure a force with a dynamometer, or in balancing it with a weight.
Two forces _F_ and _F'_, which for simplicity I will suppose vertical
and directed upward, are applied respectively to two bodies _C_ and
_C'_; I suspend the same heavy body _P_ first to the body _C_, then to
the body _C'_; if equilibrium is produced in both cases, I shall
conclude that the two forces _F_ and _F'_ are equal to one another,
since they are each equal to the weight of the body _P_.

But am I sure the body _P_ has retained the same weight when I have
transported it from the first body to the second? Far from it; _I am
sure of the contrary_; I know the intensity of gravity varies from one
point to another, and that it is stronger, for instance, at the pole
than at the equator. No doubt the difference is very slight and, in
practise, I shall take no account of it; but a properly constructed
definition should have mathematical rigor; this rigor is lacking. What I
say of weight would evidently apply to the force of the resiliency of a
dynamometer, which the temperature and a multitude of circumstances may
cause to vary.

This is not all; we can not say the weight of the body _P_ may be
applied to the body _C_ and directly balance the force _F_. What is
applied to the body _C_ is the action _A_ of the body _P_ on the body
_C_; the body _P_ is submitted on its part, on the one hand, to its
weight; on the other hand, to the reaction _R_ of the body _C_ on _P_.
Finally, the force _F_ is equal to the force _A_, since it balances it;
the force _A_ is equal to _R_, in virtue of the principle of the
equality of action and reaction; lastly, the force _R_ is equal to the
weight of _P_, since it balances it. It is from these three equalities
we deduce as consequence the equality of _F_ and the weight of _P_.

We are therefore obliged in the definition of the equality of the two
forces to bring in the principle of the equality of action and reaction;
_on this account, this principle must no longer be regarded as an
experimental law, but as a definition_.

For recognizing the equality of two forces here, we are then in
possession of two rules: equality of two forces which balance; equality
of action and reaction. But, as we have seen above, these two rules are
insufficient; we are obliged to have recourse to a third rule and to
assume that certain forces, as, for instance, the weight of a body, are
constant in magnitude and direction. But this third rule, as I have
said, is an experimental law; it is only approximately true; _it is a
bad definition_.

We are therefore reduced to Kirchhoff's definition; _force is equal to
the mass multiplied by the acceleration_. This 'law of Newton' in its
turn ceases to be regarded as an experimental law, it is now only a
definition. But this definition is still insufficient, for we do not
know what mass is. It enables us doubtless to calculate the relation of
two forces applied to the same body at different instants; it teaches us
nothing about the relation of two forces applied to two different
bodies.

To complete it, it is necessary to go back anew to Newton's third law
(equality of action and reaction), regarded again, not as an
experimental law, but as a definition. Two bodies _A_ and _B_ act one
upon the other; the acceleration of _A_ multiplied by the mass of _A_ is
equal to the action of _B_ upon _A_; in the same way, the product of the
acceleration of _B_ by its mass is equal to the reaction of _A_ upon
_B_. As, by definition, action is equal to reaction, the masses of _A_
and _B_ are in the inverse ratio of their accelerations. Here we have
the ratio of these two masses defined, and it is for experiment to
verify that this ratio is constant.

That would be all very well if the two bodies _A_ and _B_ alone were
present and removed from the action of the rest of the world. This is
not at all the case; the acceleration of _A_ is not due merely to the
action of _B_, but to that of a multitude of other bodies _C_, _D_,...
To apply the preceding rule, it is therefore necessary to separate the
acceleration of _A_ into many components, and discern which of these
components is due to the action of _B_.

This separation would still be possible, if we _should assume_ that the
action of _C_ upon _A_ is simply adjoined to that of _B_ upon _A_,
without the presence of the body _C_ modifying the action of _B_ upon
_A_; or the presence of _B_ modifying the action of _C_ upon _A_; if we
should assume, consequently, that any two bodies attract each other,
that their mutual action is along their join and depends only upon their
distance apart; if, in a word, we assume _the hypothesis of central
forces_.

You know that to determine the masses of the celestial bodies we use a
wholly different principle. The law of gravitation teaches us that the
attraction of two bodies is proportional to their masses; if _r_ is
their distance apart, _m_ and _m'_ their masses, _k_ a constant, their
attraction will be _kmm'_/_r_^{2}.

What we are measuring then is not mass, the ratio of force to
acceleration, but the attracting mass; it is not the inertia of the
body, but its attracting force.

This is an indirect procedure, whose employment is not theoretically
indispensable. It might very well have been that attraction was
inversely proportional to the square of the distance without being
proportional to the product of the masses, that it was equal
to _f_/_r_^{2}, but without our having _f_ = _kmm'_.

If it were so, we could nevertheless, by observation of the _relative_
motions of the heavenly bodies, measure the masses of these bodies.

But have we the right to admit the hypothesis of central forces? Is this
hypothesis rigorously exact? Is it certain it will never be contradicted
by experiment? Who would dare affirm that? And if we must abandon this
hypothesis, the whole edifice so laboriously erected will crumble.

We have no longer the right to speak of the component of the
acceleration of _A_ due to the action of _B_. We have no means of
distinguishing it from that due to the action of _C_ or of another body.
The rule for the measurement of masses becomes inapplicable.

What remains then of the principle of the equality of action and
reaction? If the hypothesis of central forces is rejected, this
principle should evidently be enunciated thus: the geometric resultant
of all the forces applied to the various bodies of a system isolated
from all external action will be null. Or, in other words, _the motion
of the center of gravity of this system will be rectilinear and
uniform_.

There it seems we have a means of defining mass; the position of the
center of gravity evidently depends on the values attributed to the
masses; it will be necessary to dispose of these values in such a way
that the motion of the center of gravity may be rectilinear and uniform;
this will always be possible if Newton's third law is true, and possible
in general only in a single way.

But there exists no system isolated from all external action; all the
parts of the universe are subject more or less to the action of all the
other parts. _The law of the motion of the center of gravity is
rigorously true only if applied to the entire universe._

But then, to get from it the values of the masses, it would be necessary
to observe the motion of the center of gravity of the universe. The
absurdity of this consequence is manifest; we know only relative
motions; the motion of the center of gravity of the universe will remain
for us eternally unknown.

Therefore nothing remains and our efforts have been fruitless; we are
driven to the following definition, which is only an avowal of
powerlessness: _masses are coefficients it is convenient to introduce
into calculations_.

We could reconstruct all mechanics by attributing different values to
all the masses. This new mechanics would not be in contradiction either
with experience or with the general principles of dynamics (principle of
inertia, proportionality of forces to masses and to accelerations,
equality of action and reaction, rectilinear and uniform motion of the
center of gravity, principle of areas).

Only the equations of this new mechanics would be _less simple_. Let us
understand clearly: it would only be the first terms which would be less
simple, that is those experience has already made us acquainted with;
perhaps one could alter the masses by small quantities without the
_complete_ equations gaining or losing in simplicity.

Hertz has raised the question whether the principles of mechanics are
rigorously true. "In the opinion of many physicists," he says, "it is
inconceivable that the remotest experience should ever change anything
in the immovable principles of mechanics; and yet, what comes from
experience may always be rectified by experience." After what we have
just said, these fears will appear groundless.

The principles of dynamics at first appeared to us as experimental
truths; but we have been obliged to use them as definitions. It is _by
definition_ that force is equal to the product of mass by acceleration;
here, then, is a principle which is henceforth beyond the reach of any
further experiment. It is in the same way by definition that action is
equal to reaction.

But then, it will be said, these unverifiable principles are absolutely
devoid of any significance; experiment can not contradict them; but they
can teach us nothing useful; then what is the use of studying dynamics?

This over-hasty condemnation would be unjust. There is not in nature any
system _perfectly_ isolated, perfectly removed from all external action;
but there are systems _almost_ isolated.

If such a system be observed, one may study not only the relative
motion of its various parts one in reference to another, but also the
motion of its center of gravity in reference to the other parts of the
universe. We ascertain then that the motion of this center of gravity is
_almost_ rectilinear and uniform, in conformity with Newton's third law.

That is an experimental truth, but it can not be invalidated by
experience; in fact, what would a more precise experiment teach us? It
would teach us that the law was only almost true; but that we knew
already.

_We can now understand how experience has been able to serve as basis
for the principles of mechanics and yet will never be able to contradict
them._

ANTHROPOMORPHIC MECHANICS.--"Kirchhoff," it will be said, "has only
acted in obedience to the general tendency of mathematicians toward
nominalism; from this his ability as a physicist has not saved him. He
wanted a definition of force, and he took for it the first proposition
that presented itself; but we need no definition of force: the idea of
force is primitive, irreducible, indefinable; we all know what it is, we
have a direct intuition of it. This direct intuition comes from the
notion of effort, which is familiar to us from infancy."

But first, even though this direct intuition made known to us the real
nature of force in itself, it would be insufficient as a foundation for
mechanics; it would besides be wholly useless. What is of importance is
not to know what force is, but to know how to measure it.

Whatever does not teach us to measure it is as useless to mechanics as
is, for instance, the subjective notion of warmth and cold to the
physicist who is studying heat. This subjective notion can not be
translated into numbers, therefore it is of no use; a scientist whose
skin was an absolutely bad conductor of heat and who, consequently,
would never have felt either sensations of cold or sensations of warmth,
could read a thermometer just as well as any one else, and that would
suffice him for constructing the whole theory of heat.

Now this immediate notion of effort is of no use to us for measuring
force; it is clear, for instance, that I should feel more fatigue in
lifting a weight of fifty kilos than a man accustomed to carry burdens.

But more than that: this notion of effort does not teach us the real
nature of force; it reduces itself finally to a remembrance of muscular
sensations, and it will hardly be maintained that the sun feels a
muscular sensation when it draws the earth.

All that can there be sought is a symbol, less precise and less
convenient than the arrows the geometers use, but just as remote from
the reality.

Anthropomorphism has played a considerable historic rôle in the genesis
of mechanics; perhaps it will still at times furnish a symbol which will
appear convenient to some minds; but it can not serve as foundation for
anything of a truly scientific or philosophic character.

'THE SCHOOL OF THE THREAD.'--M. Andrade, in his _Leçons de mécanique
physique_, has rejuvenated anthropomorphic mechanics. To the school of
mechanics to which Kirchhoff belongs, he opposes that which he bizarrely
calls the school of the thread.

This school tries to reduce everything to "the consideration of certain
material systems of negligible mass, envisaged in the state of tension
and capable of transmitting considerable efforts to distant bodies,
systems of which the ideal type is the _thread_."

A thread which transmits any force is slightly elongated under the
action of this force; the direction of the thread tells us the direction
of the force, whose magnitude is measured by the elongation of the
thread.

One may then conceive an experiment such as this. A body _A_ is attached
to a thread; at the other extremity of the thread any force acts which
varies until the thread takes an elongation [alpha]; the acceleration of
the body _A_ is noted; _A_ is detached and the body _B_ attached to the
same thread; the same force or another force acts anew, and is made to
vary until the thread takes again the elongation [alpha]; the
acceleration of the body _B_ is noted. The experiment is then renewed
with both _A_ and _B_, but so that the thread takes the elongation
[beta]. The four observed accelerations should be proportional. We have
thus an experimental verification of the law of acceleration above
enunciated.

Or still better, a body is submitted to the simultaneous action of
several identical threads in equal tension, and by experiment it is
sought what must be the orientations of all these threads that the body
may remain in equilibrium. We have then an experimental verification of
the law of the composition of forces.

But, after all, what have we done? We have defined the force to which
the thread is subjected by the deformation undergone by this thread,
which is reasonable enough; we have further assumed that if a body is
attached to this thread, the effort transmitted to it by the thread is
equal to the action this body exercises on this thread; after all, we
have therefore used the principle of the equality of action and
reaction, in considering it, not as an experimental truth, but as the
very definition of force.

This definition is just as conventional as Kirchhoff's, but far less
general.

All forces are not transmitted by threads (besides, to be able to
compare them, they would all have to be transmitted by identical
threads). Even if it should be conceded that the earth is attached to
the sun by some invisible thread, at least it would be admitted that we
have no means of measuring its elongation.

Nine times out of ten, consequently, our definition would be at fault;
no sort of sense could be attributed to it, and it would be necessary to
fall back on Kirchhoff's.

Why then take this détour? You admit a certain definition of force which
has a meaning only in certain particular cases. In these cases you
verify by experiment that it leads to the law of acceleration. On the
strength of this experiment, you then take the law of acceleration as a
definition of force in all the other cases.

Would it not be simpler to consider the law of acceleration as a
definition in all cases, and to regard the experiments in question, not
as verifications of this law, but as verifications of the principle of
reaction, or as demonstrating that the deformations of an elastic body
depend only on the forces to which this body is subjected?

And this is without taking into account that the conditions under which
your definition could be accepted are never fulfilled except
imperfectly, that a thread is never without mass, that it is never
removed from every force except the reaction of the bodies attached to
its extremities.

Andrade's ideas are nevertheless very interesting; if they do not
satisfy our logical craving, they make us understand better the historic
genesis of the fundamental ideas of mechanics. The reflections they
suggest show us how the human mind has raised itself from a naïve
anthropomorphism to the present conceptions of science.

We see at the start a very particular and in sum rather crude
experiment; at the finish, a law perfectly general, perfectly precise,
the certainty of which we regard as absolute. This certainty we
ourselves have bestowed upon it voluntarily, so to speak, by looking
upon it as a convention.

Are the law of acceleration, the rule of the composition of forces then
only arbitrary conventions? Conventions, yes; arbitrary, no; they would
be if we lost sight of the experiments which led the creators of the
science to adopt them, and which, imperfect as they may be, suffice to
justify them. It is well that from time to time our attention is carried
back to the experimental origin of these conventions.



CHAPTER VII

RELATIVE MOTION AND ABSOLUTE MOTION


THE PRINCIPLE OF RELATIVE MOTION.--The attempt has sometimes been made
to attach the law of acceleration to a more general principle. The
motion of any system must obey the same laws, whether it be referred to
fixed axes, or to movable axes carried along in a rectilinear and
uniform motion. This is the principle of relative motion, which forces
itself upon us for two reasons: first, the commonest experience confirms
it, and second, the contrary hypothesis is singularly repugnant to the
mind.

Assume it then, and consider a body subjected to a force; the relative
motion of this body, in reference to an observer moving with a uniform
velocity equal to the initial velocity of the body, must be identical to
what its absolute motion would be if it started from rest. We conclude
hence that its acceleration can not depend upon its absolute velocity;
the attempt has even been made to derive from this a demonstration of
the law of acceleration.

There long were traces of this demonstration in the regulations for the
degree B. ès Sc. It is evident that this attempt is idle. The obstacle
which prevented our demonstrating the law of acceleration is that we had
no definition of force; this obstacle subsists in its entirety, since
the principle invoked has not furnished us the definition we lacked.

The principle of relative motion is none the less highly interesting and
deserves study for its own sake. Let us first try to enunciate it in a
precise manner.

We have said above that the accelerations of the different bodies
forming part of an isolated system depend only on their relative
velocities and positions, and not on their absolute velocities and
positions, provided the movable axes to which the relative motion is
referred move uniformly in a straight line. Or, if we prefer, their
accelerations depend only on the differences of their velocities and the
differences of their coordinates, and not on the absolute values of
these velocities and coordinates.

If this principle is true for relative accelerations, or rather for
differences of acceleration, in combining it with the law of reaction we
shall thence deduce that it is still true of absolute accelerations.

It then remains to be seen how we may demonstrate that the differences
of the accelerations depend only on the differences of the velocities
and of the coordinates, or, to speak in mathematical language, that
these differences of coordinates satisfy differential equations of the
second order.

Can this demonstration be deduced from experiments or from _a priori_
considerations?

Recalling what we have said above, the reader can answer for himself.

Thus enunciated, in fact, the principle of relative motion singularly
resembles what I called above the generalized principle of inertia; it
is not altogether the same thing, since it is a question of the
differences of coordinates and not of the coordinates themselves. The
new principle teaches us therefore something more than the old, but the
same discussion is applicable and would lead to the same conclusions; it
is unnecessary to return to it.

NEWTON'S ARGUMENT.--Here we encounter a very important and even somewhat
disconcerting question. I have said the principle of relative motion was
for us not solely a result of experiment and that _a priori_ every
contrary hypothesis would be repugnant to the mind.

But then, why is the principle true only if the motion of the movable
axes is rectilinear and uniform? It seems that it ought to impose itself
upon us with the same force, if this motion is varied, or at any rate if
it reduces to a uniform rotation. Now, in these two cases, the principle
is not true. I will not dwell long on the case where the motion of the
axes is rectilinear without being uniform; the paradox does not bear a
moment's examination. If I am on board, and if the train, striking any
obstacle, stops suddenly, I shall be thrown against the seat in front of
me, although I have not been directly subjected to any force. There is
nothing mysterious in that; if I have undergone the action of no
external force, the train itself has experienced an external impact.
There can be nothing paradoxical in the relative motion of two bodies
being disturbed when the motion of one or the other is modified by an
external cause.

I will pause longer on the case of relative motions referred to axes
which rotate uniformly. If the heavens were always covered with clouds,
if we had no means of observing the stars, we nevertheless might
conclude that the earth turns round; we could learn this from its
flattening or again by the Foucault pendulum experiment.

And yet, in this case, would it have any meaning, to say the earth turns
round? If there is no absolute space, can one turn without turning in
reference to something else? and, on the other hand, how could we admit
Newton's conclusion and believe in absolute space?

But it does not suffice to ascertain that all possible solutions are
equally repugnant to us; we must analyze, in each case, the reasons for
our repugnance, so as to make our choice intelligently. The long
discussion which follows will therefore be excused.

Let us resume our fiction: thick clouds hide the stars from men, who can
not observe them and are ignorant even of their existence; how shall
these men know the earth turns round?

Even more than our ancestors, no doubt, they will regard the ground
which bears them as fixed and immovable; they will await much longer the
advent of a Copernicus. But in the end the Copernicus would come--how?

The students of mechanics in this world would not at first be confronted
with an absolute contradiction. In the theory of relative motion,
besides real forces, two fictitious forces are met which are called
ordinary and compound centrifugal force. Our imaginary scientists could
therefore explain everything by regarding these two forces as real, and
they would not see therein any contradiction of the generalized
principle of inertia, for these forces would depend, the one on the
relative positions of the various parts of the system, as real
attractions do, the other on their relative velocities, as real
frictions do.

Many difficulties, however, would soon awaken their attention; if they
succeeded in realizing an isolated system, the center of gravity of this
system would not have an almost rectilinear path. They would invoke, to
explain this fact, the centrifugal forces which they would regard as
real, and which they would attribute no doubt to the mutual actions of
the bodies. Only they would not see these forces become null at great
distances, that is to say in proportion as the isolation was better
realized; far from it; centrifugal force increases indefinitely with the
distance.

This difficulty would seem to them already sufficiently great; and yet
it would not stop them long; they would soon imagine some very subtile
medium, analogous to our ether, in which all bodies would be immersed
and which would exert a repellent action upon them.

But this is not all. Space is symmetric, and yet the laws of motion
would not show any symmetry; they would have to distinguish between
right and left. It would be seen for instance that cyclones turn always
in the same sense, whereas by reason of symmetry these winds should turn
indifferently in one sense and in the other. If our scientists by their
labor had succeeded in rendering their universe perfectly symmetric,
this symmetry would not remain, even though there was no apparent reason
why it should be disturbed in one sense rather than in the other.

They would get themselves out of the difficulty doubtless, they would
invent something which would be no more extraordinary than the glass
spheres of Ptolemy, and so it would go on, complications accumulating,
until the long-expected Copernicus sweeps them all away at a single
stroke, saying: It is much simpler to assume the earth turns round.

And just as our Copernicus said to us: It is more convenient to suppose
the earth turns round, since thus the laws of astronomy are expressible
in a much simpler language; this one would say: It is more convenient to
suppose the earth turns round, since thus the laws of mechanics are
expressible in a much simpler language.

This does not preclude maintaining that absolute space, that is to say
the mark to which it would be necessary to refer the earth to know
whether it really moves, has no objective existence. Hence, this
affirmation: 'the earth turns round' has no meaning, since it can be
verified by no experiment; since such an experiment, not only could not
be either realized or dreamed by the boldest Jules Verne, but can not be
conceived of without contradiction; or rather these two propositions:
'the earth turns round,' and, 'it is more convenient to suppose the
earth turns round' have the same meaning; there is nothing more in the
one than in the other.

Perhaps one will not be content even with that, and will find it already
shocking that among all the hypotheses, or rather all the conventions we
can make on this subject, there is one more convenient than the others.

But if it has been admitted without difficulty when it was a question of
the laws of astronomy, why should it be shocking in that which concerns
mechanics?

We have seen that the coordinates of bodies are determined by
differential equations of the second order, and that so are the
differences of these coordinates. This is what we have called the
generalized principle of inertia and the principle of relative motion.
If the distances of these bodies were determined likewise by equations
of the second order, it seems that the mind ought to be entirely
satisfied. In what measure does the mind get this satisfaction and why
is it not content with it?

To account for this, we had better take a simple example. I suppose a
system analogous to our solar system, but where one can not perceive
fixed stars foreign to this system, so that astronomers can observe only
the mutual distances of the planets and the sun, and not the absolute
longitudes of the planets. If we deduce directly from Newton's law the
differential equations which define the variation of these distances,
these equations will not be of the second order. I mean that if, besides
Newton's law, one knew the initial values of these distances and of
their derivatives with respect to the time, that would not suffice to
determine the values of these same distances at a subsequent instant.
There would still be lacking one datum, and this datum might be for
instance what astronomers call the area-constant.

But here two different points of view may be taken; we may distinguish
two sorts of constants. To the eyes of the physicist the world reduces
to a series of phenomena, depending, on the one hand, solely upon the
initial phenomena; on the other hand, upon the laws which bind the
consequents to the antecedents. If then observation teaches us that a
certain quantity is a constant, we shall have the choice between two
conceptions.

Either we shall assume that there is a law requiring this quantity not
to vary, but that by chance, at the beginning of the ages, it had,
rather than another, this value it has been forced to keep ever since.
This quantity might then be called an _accidental_ constant.

Or else we shall assume, on the contrary, that there is a law of nature
which imposes upon this quantity such a value and not such another.

We shall then have what we may call an _essential_ constant.

For example, in virtue of Newton's laws, the duration of the revolution
of the earth must be constant. But if it is 366 sidereal days and
something over, and not 300 or 400, this is in consequence of I know not
what initial chance. This is an accidental constant. If, on the
contrary, the exponent of the distance which figures in the expression
of the attractive force is equal to -2 and not to -3, this is not by
chance, but because Newton's law requires it. This is an essential
constant.

I know not whether this way of giving chance its part is legitimate in
itself, and whether this distinction is not somewhat artificial; it is
certain at least that, so long as nature shall have secrets, this
distinction will be in application extremely arbitrary and always
precarious.

As to the area-constant, we are accustomed to regard it as accidental.
Is it certain our imaginary astronomers would do the same? If they could
have compared two different solar systems, they would have the idea that
this constant may have several different values; but my very supposition
in the beginning was that their system should appear as isolated, and
that they should observe no star foreign to it. Under these conditions,
they would see only one single constant which would have a single value
absolutely invariable; they would be led without any doubt to regard it
as an essential constant.

A word in passing to forestall an objection: the inhabitants of this
imaginary world could neither observe nor define the area-constant as we
do, since the absolute longitudes escape them; that would not preclude
their being quickly led to notice a certain constant which would
introduce itself naturally into their equations and which would be
nothing but what we call the area-constant.

But then see what would happen. If the area-constant is regarded as
essential, as depending upon a law of nature, to calculate the distances
of the planets at any instant it will suffice to know the initial values
of these distances and those of their first derivatives. From this new
point of view, the distances will be determined by differential
equations of the second order.

Yet would the mind of these astronomers be completely satisfied? I do
not believe so; first, they would soon perceive that in differentiating
their equations and thus raising their order, these equations became
much simpler. And above all they would be struck by the difficulty which
comes from symmetry. It would be necessary to assume different laws,
according as the aggregate of the planets presented the figure of a
certain polyhedron or of the symmetric polyhedron, and one would escape
from this consequence only by regarding the area-constant as accidental.

I have taken a very special example, since I have supposed astronomers
who did not at all consider terrestrial mechanics, and whose view was
limited to the solar system. Our universe is more extended than theirs,
as we have fixed stars, but still it too is limited, and so we might
reason on the totality of our universe as the astronomers on their solar
system.

Thus we see that finally we should be led to conclude that the equations
which define distances are of an order superior to the second. Why
should we be shocked at that, why do we find it perfectly natural for
the series of phenomena to depend upon the initial values of the first
derivatives of these distances, while we hesitate to admit that they may
depend on the initial values of the second derivatives? This can only be
because of the habits of mind created in us by the constant study of the
generalized principle of inertia and its consequences.

The values of the distances at any instant depend upon their initial
values, upon those of their first derivatives and also upon something
else. What is this _something else_?

If we will not admit that this may be simply one of the second
derivatives, we have only the choice of hypotheses. Either it may be
supposed, as is ordinarily done, that this something else is the
absolute orientation of the universe in space, or the rapidity with
which this orientation varies; and this supposition may be correct; it
is certainly the most convenient solution for geometry; it is not the
most satisfactory for the philosopher, because this orientation does not
exist.

Or it may be supposed that this something else is the position or the
velocity of some invisible body; this has been done by certain persons
who have even called it the body alpha, although we are doomed never to
know anything of this body but its name. This is an artifice entirely
analogous to that of which I spoke at the end of the paragraph devoted
to my reflections on the principle of inertia.

But, after all, the difficulty is artificial. Provided the future
indications of our instruments can depend only on the indications they
have given us or would have given us formerly, this is all that is
necessary. Now as to this we may rest easy.



CHAPTER VIII

ENERGY AND THERMODYNAMICS


ENERGETICS.--The difficulties inherent in the classic mechanics have led
certain minds to prefer a new system they call _energetics_.

Energetics took its rise as an outcome of the discovery of the principle
of the conservation of energy. Helmholtz gave it its final form.

It begins by defining two quantities which play the fundamental rôle in
this theory. They are _kinetic energy_, or _vis viva_, and _potential
energy_.

All the changes which bodies in nature can undergo are regulated by two
experimental laws:

1º The sum of kinetic energy and potential energy is constant. This is
the principle of the conservation of energy.

2º If a system of bodies is at _A_ at the time t_{0} and at _B_ at the
time t_{1}, it always goes from the first situation to the second in
such a way that the _mean_ value of the difference between the two sorts
of energy, in the interval of time which separates the two epochs t_{0}
and t_{1}, may be as small as possible.

This is Hamilton's principle, which is one of the forms of the principle
of least action.

The energetic theory has the following advantages over the classic
theory:

1º It is less incomplete; that is to say, Hamilton's principle and that
of the conservation of energy teach us more than the fundamental
principles of the classic theory, and exclude certain motions not
realized in nature and which would be compatible with the classic
theory:

2º It saves us the hypothesis of atoms, which it was almost impossible
to avoid with the classic theory.

But it raises in its turn new difficulties:

The definitions of the two sorts of energy would raise difficulties
almost as great as those of force and mass in the first system. Yet
they may be gotten over more easily, at least in the simplest cases.

Suppose an isolated system formed of a certain number of material
points; suppose these points subjected to forces depending only on their
relative position and their mutual distances, and independent of their
velocities. In virtue of the principle of the conservation of energy, a
function of forces must exist.

In this simple case the enunciation of the principle of the conservation
of energy is of extreme simplicity. A certain quantity, accessible to
experiment, must remain constant. This quantity is the sum of two terms;
the first depends only on the position of the material points and is
independent of their velocities; the second is proportional to the
square of these velocities. This resolution can take place only in a
single way.

The first of these terms, which I shall call _U_, will be the potential
energy; the second, which I shall call _T_, will be the kinetic energy.

It is true that if _T_ + _U_ is a constant, so is any function of _T_ +
_U_,

  {Phi}(_T_ + _U_).

But this function {Phi}(_T_ + _U_) will not be the sum of two terms the
one independent of the velocities, the other proportional to the square
of these velocities. Among the functions which remain constant there is
only one which enjoys this property, that is _T_ + _U_ (or a linear
function of _T_ + _U_, which comes to the same thing, since this linear
function may always be reduced to _T_ + _U_ by change of unit and of
origin). This then is what we shall call energy; the first term we shall
call potential energy and the second kinetic energy. The definition of
the two sorts of energy can therefore be carried through without any
ambiguity.

It is the same with the definition of the masses. Kinetic energy, or
_vis viva_, is expressed very simply by the aid of the masses and the
relative velocities of all the material points with reference to one of
them. These relative velocities are accessible to observation, and, when
we know the expression of the kinetic energy as function of these
relative velocities, the coefficients of this expression will give us
the masses.

Thus, in this simple case, the fundamental ideas may be defined without
difficulty. But the difficulties reappear in the more complicated cases
and, for instance, if the forces, in lieu of depending only on the
distances, depend also on the velocities. For example, Weber supposes
the mutual action of two electric molecules to depend not only on their
distance, but on their velocity and their acceleration. If material
points should attract each other according to an analogous law, _U_
would depend on the velocity, and might contain a term proportional to
the square of the velocity.

Among the terms proportional to the squares of the velocities, how
distinguish those which come from _T_ or from _U_? Consequently, how
distinguish the two parts of energy?

But still more; how define energy itself? We no longer have any reason
to take as definition _T_ + _U_ rather than any other function of _T_ +
_U_, when the property which characterized _T_ + _U_ has disappeared,
that, namely, of being the sum of two terms of a particular form.

But this is not all; it is necessary to take account, not only of
mechanical energy properly so called, but of the other forms of energy,
heat, chemical energy, electric energy, etc. The principle of the
conservation of energy should be written:

  _T_ + _U_ + _Q_ = const.

where _T_ would represent the sensible kinetic energy, _U_ the potential
energy of position, depending only on the position of the bodies, _Q_
the internal molecular energy, under the thermal, chemic or electric
form.

All would go well if these three terms were absolutely distinct, if _T_
were proportional to the square of the velocities, _U_ independent of
these velocities and of the state of the bodies, _Q_ independent of the
velocities and of the positions of the bodies and dependent only on
their internal state.

The expression for the energy could be resolved only in one single way
into three terms of this form.

But this is not the case; consider electrified bodies; the electrostatic
energy due to their mutual action will evidently depend upon their
charge, that is to say, on their state; but it will equally depend upon
their position. If these bodies are in motion, they will act one upon
another electrodynamically and the electrodynamic energy will depend not
only upon their state and their position, but upon their velocities.

We therefore no longer have any means of making the separation of the
terms which should make part of _T_, of _U_ and of _Q_, and of
separating the three parts of energy.

If (_T_ + _U_ + _Q_) is constant so is any function [phi](_T_ + _U_ +
_Q_).

If _T_ + _U_ + _Q_ were of the particular form I have above considered,
no ambiguity would result; among the functions [phi](_T_ + _U_ + _Q_)
which remain constant, there would only be one of this particular form,
and that I should convene to call energy.

But as I have said, this is not rigorously the case; among the functions
which remain constant, there is none which can be put rigorously under
this particular form; hence, how choose among them the one which should
be called energy? We no longer have anything to guide us in our choice.

There only remains for us one enunciation of the principle of the
conservation of energy: _There is something which remains constant_.
Under this form it is in its turn out of the reach of experiment and
reduces to a sort of tautology. It is clear that if the world is
governed by laws, there will be quantities which will remain constant.
Like Newton's laws, and, for an analogous reason, the principle of the
conservation of energy, founded on experiment, could no longer be
invalidated by it.

This discussion shows that in passing from the classic to the energetic
system progress has been made; but at the same time it shows this
progress is insufficient.

Another objection seems to me still more grave: the principle of least
action is applicable to reversible phenomena; but it is not at all
satisfactory in so far as irreversible phenomena are concerned; the
attempt by Helmholtz to extend it to this kind of phenomena did not
succeed and could not succeed; in this regard everything remains to be
done. The very statement of the principle of least action has something
about it repugnant to the mind. To go from one point to another, a
material molecule, acted upon by no force, but required to move on a
surface, will take the geodesic line, that is to say, the shortest
path.

This molecule seems to know the point whither it is to go, to foresee
the time it would take to reach it by such and such a route, and then to
choose the most suitable path. The statement presents the molecule to
us, so to speak, as a living and free being. Clearly it would be better
to replace it by an enunciation less objectionable, and where, as the
philosophers would say, final causes would not seem to be substituted
for efficient causes.

THERMODYNAMICS.[4]--The rôle of the two fundamental principles of
thermodynamics in all branches of natural philosophy becomes daily more
important. Abandoning the ambitious theories of forty years ago, which
were encumbered by molecular hypotheses, we are trying to-day to erect
upon thermodynamics alone the entire edifice of mathematical physics.
Will the two principles of Mayer and of Clausius assure to it
foundations solid enough for it to last some time? No one doubts it; but
whence comes this confidence?

  [4] The following lines are a partial reproduction of the preface
      of my book _Thermodynamique_.

An eminent physicist said to me one day _à propos_ of the law of errors:
"All the world believes it firmly, because the mathematicians imagine
that it is a fact of observation, and the observers that it is a theorem
of mathematics." It was long so for the principle of the conservation of
energy. It is no longer so to-day; no one is ignorant that this is an
experimental fact.

But then what gives us the right to attribute to the principle itself
more generality and more precision than to the experiments which have
served to demonstrate it? This is to ask whether it is legitimate, as is
done every day, to generalize empirical data, and I shall not have the
presumption to discuss this question, after so many philosophers have
vainly striven to solve it. One thing is certain; if this power were
denied us, science could not exist or, at least, reduced to a sort of
inventory, to the ascertaining of isolated facts, it would have no value
for us, since it could give no satisfaction to our craving for order and
harmony and since it would be at the same time incapable of foreseeing.
As the circumstances which have preceded any fact will probably never be
simultaneously reproduced, a first generalization is already necessary
to foresee whether this fact will be reproduced again after the least of
these circumstances shall be changed.

But every proposition may be generalized in an infinity of ways. Among
all the generalizations possible, we must choose, and we can only choose
the simplest. We are therefore led to act as if a simple law were, other
things being equal, more probable than a complicated law.

Half a century ago this was frankly confessed, and it was proclaimed
that nature loves simplicity; she has since too often given us the lie.
To-day we no longer confess this tendency, and we retain only so much of
it as is indispensable if science is not to become impossible.

In formulating a general, simple and precise law on the basis of
experiments relatively few and presenting certain divergences, we have
therefore only obeyed a necessity from which the human mind can not free
itself.

But there is something more, and this is why I dwell upon the point.

No one doubts that Mayer's principle is destined to survive all the
particular laws from which it was obtained, just as Newton's law has
survived Kepler's laws, from which it sprang, and which are only
approximative if account be taken of perturbations.

Why does this principle occupy thus a sort of privileged place among all
the physical laws? There are many little reasons for it.

First of all it is believed that we could not reject it or even doubt
its absolute rigor without admitting the possibility of perpetual
motion; of course we are on our guard at such a prospect, and we think
ourselves less rash in affirming Mayer's principle than in denying it.

That is perhaps not wholly accurate; the impossibility of perpetual
motion implies the conservation of energy only for reversible phenomena.

The imposing simplicity of Mayer's principle likewise contributes to
strengthen our faith. In a law deduced immediately from experiment, like
Mariotte's, this simplicity would rather seem to us a reason for
distrust; but here this is no longer the case; we see elements, at first
sight disparate, arrange themselves in an unexpected order and form a
harmonious whole; and we refuse to believe that an unforeseen harmony
may be a simple effect of chance. It seems that our conquest is the
dearer to us the more effort it has cost us, or that we are the surer of
having wrested her true secret from nature the more jealously she has
hidden it from us.

But those are only little reasons; to establish Mayer's law as an
absolute principle, a more profound discussion is necessary. But if this
be attempted, it is seen that this absolute principle is not even easy
to state.

In each particular case it is clearly seen what energy is and at least a
provisional definition of it can be given; but it is impossible to find
a general definition for it.

If we try to enunciate the principle in all its generality and apply it
to the universe, we see it vanish, so to speak, and nothing is left but
this: _There is something which remains constant_.

But has even this any meaning? In the determinist hypothesis, the state
of the universe is determined by an extremely great number _n_ of
parameters which I shall call x_{1}, x_{2},... x_{_n_}. As soon as
the values of these _n_ parameters at any instant are known, their
derivatives with respect to the time are likewise known and consequently
the values of these same parameters at a preceding or subsequent instant
can be calculated. In other words, these _n_ parameters satisfy _n_
differential equations of the first order.

These equations admit of _n_ - 1 integrals and consequently there are
_n_ - 1 functions of x_{1}, x_{2},... x_{_n_}, which remain constant.
_If then we say there is something which remains constant_, we only
utter a tautology. We should even be puzzled to say which among all our
integrals should retain the name of energy.

Besides, Mayer's principle is not understood in this sense when it is
applied to a limited system. It is then assumed that _p_ of our
parameters vary independently, so that we only have _n_ - _p_ relations,
generally linear, between our _n_ parameters and their derivatives.

To simplify the enunciation, suppose that the sum of the work of the
external forces is null, as well as that of the quantities of heat given
off to the outside. Then the signification of our principle will be:

_There is a combination of these n - p relations whose first member is
an exact differential_; and then this differential vanishing in virtue
of our _n_ - _p_ relations, its integral is a constant and this integral
is called energy.

But how can it be possible that there are several parameters whose
variations are independent? That can only happen under the influence of
external forces (although we have supposed, for simplicity, that the
algebraic sum of the effects of these forces is null). In fact, if the
system were completely isolated from all external action, the values of
our _n_ parameters at a given instant would suffice to determine the
state of the system at any subsequent instant, provided always we retain
the determinist hypothesis; we come back therefore to the same
difficulty as above.

If the future state of the system is not entirely determined by its
present state, this is because it depends besides upon the state of
bodies external to the system. But then is it probable that there exist
between the parameters _x_, which define the state of the system,
equations independent of this state of the external bodies? and if in
certain cases we believe we can find such, is this not solely in
consequence of our ignorance and because the influence of these bodies
is too slight for our experimenting to detect it?

If the system is not regarded as completely isolated, it is probable
that the rigorously exact expression of its internal energy will depend
on the state of the external bodies. Again, I have above supposed the
sum of the external work was null, and if we try to free ourselves from
this rather artificial restriction, the enunciation becomes still more
difficult.

To formulate Mayer's principle in an absolute sense, it is therefore
necessary to extend it to the whole universe, and then we find ourselves
face to face with the very difficulty we sought to avoid.

In conclusion, using ordinary language, the law of the conservation of
energy can have only one signification, which is that there is a
property common to all the possibilities; but on the determinist
hypothesis there is only a single possibility, and then the law has no
longer any meaning.

On the indeterminist hypothesis, on the contrary, it would have a
meaning, even if it were taken in an absolute sense; it would appear as
a limitation imposed upon freedom.

But this word reminds me that I am digressing and am on the point of
leaving the domain of mathematics and physics. I check myself therefore
and will stress of all this discussion only one impression, that Mayer's
law is a form flexible enough for us to put into it almost whatever we
wish. By that I do not mean it corresponds to no objective reality, nor
that it reduces itself to a mere tautology, since, in each particular
case, and provided one does not try to push to the absolute, it has a
perfectly clear meaning.

This flexibility is a reason for believing in its permanence, and as, on
the other hand, it will disappear only to lose itself in a higher
harmony, we may work with confidence, supporting ourselves upon it,
certain beforehand that our labor will not be lost.

Almost everything I have just said applies to the principle of Clausius.
What distinguishes it is that it is expressed by an inequality. Perhaps
it will be said it is the same with all physical laws, since their
precision is always limited by errors of observation. But they at least
claim to be first approximations, and it is hoped to replace them little
by little by laws more and more precise. If, on the other hand, the
principle of Clausius reduces to an inequality, this is not caused by
the imperfection of our means of observation, but by the very nature of
the question.


GENERAL CONCLUSIONS ON PART THIRD

The principles of mechanics, then, present themselves to us under two
different aspects. On the one hand, they are truths founded on
experiment and approximately verified so far as concerns almost isolated
systems. On the other hand, they are postulates applicable to the
totality of the universe and regarded as rigorously true.

If these postulates possess a generality and a certainty which are
lacking to the experimental verities whence they are drawn, this is
because they reduce in the last analysis to a mere convention which we
have the right to make, because we are certain beforehand that no
experiment can ever contradict it.

This convention, however, is not absolutely arbitrary; it does not
spring from our caprice; we adopt it because certain experiments have
shown us that it would be convenient.

Thus is explained how experiment could make the principles of mechanics,
and yet why it can not overturn them.

Compare with geometry: The fundamental propositions of geometry, as for
instance Euclid's postulate, are nothing more than conventions, and it
is just as unreasonable to inquire whether they are true or false as to
ask whether the metric system is true or false.

Only, these conventions are convenient, and it is certain experiments
which have taught us that.

At first blush, the analogy is complete; the rôle of experiment seems
the same. One will therefore be tempted to say: Either mechanics must be
regarded as an experimental science, and then the same must hold for
geometry; or else, on the contrary, geometry is a deductive science, and
then one may say as much of mechanics.

Such a conclusion would be illegitimate. The experiments which have led
us to adopt as more convenient the fundamental conventions of geometry
bear on objects which have nothing in common with those geometry
studies; they bear on the properties of solid bodies, on the rectilinear
propagation of light. They are experiments of mechanics, experiments of
optics; they can not in any way be regarded as experiments of geometry.
And even the principal reason why our geometry seems convenient to us is
that the different parts of our body, our eye, our limbs, have the
properties of solid bodies. On this account, our fundamental experiments
are preeminently physiological experiments, which bear, not on space
which is the object the geometer must study, but on his body, that is
to say, on the instrument he must use for this study.

On the contrary, the fundamental conventions of mechanics, and the
experiments which prove to us that they are convenient, bear on exactly
the same objects or on analogous objects. The conventional and general
principles are the natural and direct generalization of the experimental
and particular principles.

Let it not be said that thus I trace artificial frontiers between the
sciences; that if I separate by a barrier geometry properly so called
from the study of solid bodies, I could just as well erect one between
experimental mechanics and the conventional mechanics of the general
principles. In fact, who does not see that in separating these two
sciences I mutilate them both, and that what will remain of conventional
mechanics when it shall be isolated will be only a very small thing and
can in no way be compared to that superb body of doctrine called
geometry?

One sees now why the teaching of mechanics should remain experimental.

Only thus can it make us comprehend the genesis of the science, and that
is indispensable for the complete understanding of the science itself.

Besides, if we study mechanics, it is to apply it; and we can apply it
only if it remains objective. Now, as we have seen, what the principles
gain in generality and certainty they lose in objectivity. It is,
therefore, above all with the objective side of the principles that we
must be familiarized early, and that can be done only by going from the
particular to the general, instead of the inverse.

The principles are conventions and disguised definitions. Yet they are
drawn from experimental laws; these laws have, so to speak, been exalted
into principles to which our mind attributes an absolute value.

Some philosophers have generalized too far; they believed the principles
were the whole science and consequently that the whole science was
conventional.

This paradoxical doctrine, called nominalism, will not bear
examination.

How can a law become a principle? It expressed a relation between two
real terms _A_ and _B_. But it was not rigorously true, it was only
approximate. We introduce arbitrarily an intermediary term _C_ more or
less fictitious, and _C_ is _by definition_ that which has with _A_
_exactly_ the relation expressed by the law.

Then our law is separated into an absolute and rigorous principle which
expresses the relation of _A_ to _C_ and an experimental law,
approximate and subject to revision, which expresses the relation of _C_
to _B_. It is clear that, however far this partition is pushed, some
laws will always be left remaining.

We go to enter now the domain of laws properly so called.



PART IV


NATURE



CHAPTER IX

HYPOTHESES IN PHYSICS


THE RÔLE OF EXPERIMENT AND GENERALIZATION.--Experiment is the sole
source of truth. It alone can teach us anything new; it alone can give
us certainty. These are two points that can not be questioned.

But then, if experiment is everything, what place will remain for
mathematical physics? What has experimental physics to do with such an
aid, one which seems useless and perhaps even dangerous?

And yet mathematical physics exists, and has done unquestionable
service. We have here a fact that must be explained.

The explanation is that merely to observe is not enough. We must use our
observations, and to do that we must generalize. This is what men always
have done; only as the memory of past errors has made them more and more
careful, they have observed more and more, and generalized less and
less.

Every age has ridiculed the one before it, and accused it of having
generalized too quickly and too naïvely. Descartes pitied the Ionians;
Descartes, in his turn, makes us smile. No doubt our children will some
day laugh at us.

But can we not then pass over immediately to the goal? Is not this the
means of escaping the ridicule that we foresee? Can we not be content
with just the bare experiment?

No, that is impossible; it would be to mistake utterly the true nature
of science. The scientist must set in order. Science is built up with
facts, as a house is with stones. But a collection of facts is no more a
science than a heap of stones is a house.

And above all the scientist must foresee. Carlyle has somewhere said
something like this: "Nothing but facts are of importance. John Lackland
passed by here. Here is something that is admirable. Here is a reality
for which I would give all the theories in the world." Carlyle was a
fellow countryman of Bacon; but Bacon would not have said that. That is
the language of the historian. The physicist would say rather: "John
Lackland passed by here; that makes no difference to me, for he never
will pass this way again."

We all know that there are good experiments and poor ones. The latter
will accumulate in vain; though one may have made a hundred or a
thousand, a single piece of work by a true master, by a Pasteur, for
example, will suffice to tumble them into oblivion. Bacon would have
well understood this; it is he who invented the phrase _Experimentum
crucis_. But Carlyle would not have understood it. A fact is a fact. A
pupil has read a certain number on his thermometer; he has taken no
precaution; no matter, he has read it, and if it is only the fact that
counts, here is a reality of the same rank as the peregrinations of King
John Lackland. Why is the fact that this pupil has made this reading of
no interest, while the fact that a skilled physicist had made another
reading might be on the contrary very important? It is because from the
first reading we could not infer anything. What then is a good
experiment? It is that which informs us of something besides an isolated
fact; it is that which enables us to foresee, that is, that which
enables us to generalize.

For without generalization foreknowledge is impossible. The
circumstances under which one has worked will never reproduce themselves
all at once. The observed action then will never recur; the only thing
that can be affirmed is that under analogous circumstances an analogous
action will be produced. In order to foresee, then, it is necessary to
invoke at least analogy, that is to say, already then to generalize.

No matter how timid one may be, still it is necessary to interpolate.
Experiment gives us only a certain number of isolated points. We must
unite these by a continuous line. This is a veritable generalization.
But we do more; the curve that we shall trace will pass between the
observed points and near these points; it will not pass through these
points themselves. Thus one does not restrict himself to generalizing
the experiments, but corrects them; and the physicist who should try to
abstain from these corrections and really be content with the bare
experiment, would be forced to enunciate some very strange laws.

The bare facts, then, would not be enough for us; and that is why we
must have science ordered, or rather organized.

It is often said experiments must be made without a preconceived idea.
That is impossible. Not only would it make all experiment barren, but
that would be attempted which could not be done. Every one carries in
his mind his own conception of the world, of which he can not so easily
rid himself. We must, for instance, use language; and our language is
made up only of preconceived ideas and can not be otherwise. Only these
are unconscious preconceived ideas, a thousand times more dangerous than
the others.

Shall we say that if we introduce others, of which we are fully
conscious, we shall only aggravate the evil? I think not. I believe
rather that they will serve as counterbalances to each other--I was
going to say as antidotes; they will in general accord ill with one
another--they will come into conflict with one another, and thereby
force us to regard things under different aspects. This is enough to
emancipate us. He is no longer a slave who can choose his master.

Thus, thanks to generalization, each fact observed enables us to foresee
a great many others; only we must not forget that the first alone is
certain, that all others are merely probable. No matter how solidly
founded a prediction may appear to us, we are never _absolutely_ sure
that experiment will not contradict it, if we undertake to verify it.
The probability, however, is often so great that practically we may be
content with it. It is far better to foresee even without certainty than
not to foresee at all.

One must, then, never disdain to make a verification when opportunity
offers. But all experiment is long and difficult; the workers are few;
and the number of facts that we need to foresee is immense. Compared
with this mass the number of direct verifications that we can make will
never be anything but a negligible quantity.

Of this few that we can directly attain, we must make the best use; it
is very necessary to get from every experiment the greatest possible
number of predictions, and with the highest possible degree of
probability. The problem is, so to speak, to increase the yield of the
scientific machine.

Let us compare science to a library that ought to grow continually. The
librarian has at his disposal for his purchases only insufficient funds.
He ought to make an effort not to waste them.

It is experimental physics that is entrusted with the purchases. It
alone, then, can enrich the library.

As for mathematical physics, its task will be to make out the catalogue.
If the catalogue is well made, the library will not be any richer, but
the reader will be helped to use its riches.

And even by showing the librarian the gaps in his collections, it will
enable him to make a judicious use of his funds; which is all the more
important because these funds are entirely inadequate.

Such, then, is the rôle of mathematical physics. It must direct
generalization in such a manner as to increase what I just now called
the yield of science. By what means it can arrive at this, and how it
can do it without danger, is what remains for us to investigate.

THE UNITY OF NATURE.--Let us notice, first of all, that every
generalization implies in some measure the belief in the unity and
simplicity of nature. As to the unity there can be no difficulty. If the
different parts of the universe were not like the members of one body,
they would not act on one another, they would know nothing of one
another; and we in particular would know only one of these parts. We do
not ask, then, if nature is one, but how it is one.

As for the second point, that is not such an easy matter. It is not
certain that nature is simple. Can we without danger act as if it were?

There was a time when the simplicity of Mariotte's law was an argument
invoked in favor of its accuracy; when Fresnel himself, after having
said in a conversation with Laplace that nature was not concerned about
analytical difficulties, felt himself obliged to make explanations, in
order not to strike too hard at prevailing opinion.

To-day ideas have greatly changed; and yet, those who do not believe
that natural laws have to be simple, are still often obliged to act as
if they did. They could not entirely avoid this necessity without making
impossible all generalization, and consequently all science.

It is clear that any fact can be generalized in an infinity of ways, and
it is a question of choice. The choice can be guided only by
considerations of simplicity. Let us take the most commonplace case,
that of interpolation. We pass a continuous line, as regular as
possible, between the points given by observation. Why do we avoid
points making angles and too abrupt turns? Why do we not make our curve
describe the most capricious zig-zags? It is because we know beforehand,
or believe we know, that the law to be expressed can not be so
complicated as all that.

We may calculate the mass of Jupiter from either the movements of its
satellites, or the perturbations of the major planets, or those of the
minor planets. If we take the averages of the determinations obtained by
these three methods, we find three numbers very close together, but
different. We might interpret this result by supposing that the
coefficient of gravitation is not the same in the three cases. The
observations would certainly be much better represented. Why do we
reject this interpretation? Not because it is absurd, but because it is
needlessly complicated. We shall only accept it when we are forced to,
and that is not yet.

To sum up, ordinarily every law is held to be simple till the contrary
is proved.

This custom is imposed upon physicists by the causes that I have just
explained. But how shall we justify it in the presence of discoveries
that show us every day new details that are richer and more complex? How
shall we even reconcile it with the belief in the unity of nature? For
if everything depends on everything, relationships where so many diverse
factors enter can no longer be simple.

If we study the history of science, we see happen two inverse phenomena,
so to speak. Sometimes simplicity hides under complex appearances;
sometimes it is the simplicity which is apparent, and which disguises
extremely complicated realities.

What is more complicated than the confused movements of the planets?
What simpler than Newton's law? Here nature, making sport, as Fresnel
said, of analytical difficulties, employs only simple means, and by
combining them produces I know not what inextricable tangle. Here it is
the hidden simplicity which must be discovered.

Examples of the opposite abound. In the kinetic theory of gases, one
deals with molecules moving with great velocities, whose paths, altered
by incessant collisions, have the most capricious forms and traverse
space in every direction. The observable result is Mariotte's simple
law. Every individual fact was complicated. The law of great numbers has
reestablished simplicity in the average. Here the simplicity is merely
apparent, and only the coarseness of our senses prevents our perceiving
the complexity.

Many phenomena obey a law of proportionality. But why? Because in these
phenomena there is something very small. The simple law observed, then,
is only a result of the general analytical rule that the infinitely
small increment of a function is proportional to the increment of the
variable. As in reality our increments are not infinitely small, but
very small, the law of proportionality is only approximate, and the
simplicity is only apparent. What I have just said applies to the rule
of the superposition of small motions, the use of which is so fruitful,
and which is the basis of optics.

And Newton's law itself? Its simplicity, so long undetected, is perhaps
only apparent. Who knows whether it is not due to some complicated
mechanism, to the impact of some subtile matter animated by irregular
movements, and whether it has not become simple only through the action
of averages and of great numbers? In any case, it is difficult not to
suppose that the true law contains complementary terms, which would
become sensible at small distances. If in astronomy they are negligible
as modifying Newton's law, and if the law thus regains its simplicity,
it would be only because of the immensity of celestial distances.

No doubt, if our means of investigation should become more and more
penetrating, we should discover the simple under the complex, then the
complex under the simple, then again the simple under the complex, and
so on, without our being able to foresee what will be the last term.

We must stop somewhere, and that science may be possible we must stop
when we have found simplicity. This is the only ground on which we can
rear the edifice of our generalizations. But this simplicity being only
apparent, will the ground be firm enough? This is what must be
investigated.

For that purpose, let us see what part is played in our generalizations
by the belief in simplicity. We have verified a simple law in a good
many particular cases; we refuse to admit that this agreement, so often
repeated, is simply the result of chance, and conclude that the law must
be true in the general case.

Kepler notices that a planet's positions, as observed by Tycho, are all
on one ellipse. Never for a moment does he have the thought that by a
strange play of chance Tycho never observed the heavens except at a
moment when the real orbit of the planet happened to cut this ellipse.

What does it matter then whether the simplicity be real, or whether it
covers a complex reality? Whether it is due to the influence of great
numbers, which levels down individual differences, or to the greatness
or smallness of certain quantities, which allows us to neglect certain
terms, in no case is it due to chance. This simplicity, real or
apparent, always has a cause. We can always follow, then, the same
course of reasoning, and if a simple law has been observed in several
particular cases, we can legitimately suppose that it will still be true
in analogous cases. To refuse to do this would be to attribute to chance
an inadmissible rôle.

There is, however, a difference. If the simplicity were real and
essential, it would resist the increasing precision of our means of
measure. If then we believe nature to be essentially simple, we must,
from a simplicity that is approximate, infer a simplicity that is
rigorous. This is what was done formerly; and this is what we no longer
have a right to do.

The simplicity of Kepler's laws, for example, is only apparent. That
does not prevent their being applicable, very nearly, to all systems
analogous to the solar system; but it does prevent their being
rigorously exact.

THE RÔLE OF HYPOTHESIS.--All generalization is a hypothesis. Hypothesis,
then, has a necessary rôle that no one has ever contested. Only, it
ought always, as soon as possible and as often as possible, to be
subjected to verification. And, of course, if it does not stand this
test, it ought to be abandoned without reserve. This is what we
generally do, but sometimes with rather an ill humor.

Well, even this ill humor is not justified. The physicist who has just
renounced one of his hypotheses ought, on the contrary, to be full of
joy; for he has found an unexpected opportunity for discovery. His
hypothesis, I imagine, had not been adopted without consideration; it
took account of all the known factors that it seemed could enter into
the phenomenon. If the test does not support it, it is because there is
something unexpected and extraordinary; and because there is going to be
something found that is unknown and new.

Has the discarded hypothesis, then, been barren? Far from that, it may
be said it has rendered more service than a true hypothesis. Not only
has it been the occasion of the decisive experiment, but, without having
made the hypothesis, the experiment would have been made by chance, so
that nothing would have been derived from it. One would have seen
nothing extraordinary; only one fact the more would have been catalogued
without deducing from it the least consequence.

Now on what condition is the use of hypothesis without danger?

The firm determination to submit to experiment is not enough; there are
still dangerous hypotheses; first, and above all, those which are tacit
and unconscious. Since we make them without knowing it, we are powerless
to abandon them. Here again, then, is a service that mathematical
physics can render us. By the precision that is characteristic of it, it
compels us to formulate all the hypotheses that we should make without
it, but unconsciously.

Let us notice besides that it is important not to multiply hypotheses
beyond measure, and to make them only one after the other. If we
construct a theory based on a number of hypotheses, and if experiment
condemns it, which of our premises is it necessary to change? It will be
impossible to know. And inversely, if the experiment succeeds, shall we
believe that we have demonstrated all the hypotheses at once? Shall we
believe that with one single equation we have determined several
unknowns?

We must equally take care to distinguish between the different kinds of
hypotheses. There are first those which are perfectly natural and from
which one can scarcely escape. It is difficult not to suppose that the
influence of bodies very remote is quite negligible, that small
movements follow a linear law, that the effect is a continuous function
of its cause. I will say as much of the conditions imposed by symmetry.
All these hypotheses form, as it were, the common basis of all the
theories of mathematical physics. They are the last that ought to be
abandoned.

There is a second class of hypotheses, that I shall term neutral. In
most questions the analyst assumes at the beginning of his calculations
either that matter is continuous or, on the contrary, that it is formed
of atoms. He might have made the opposite assumption without changing
his results. He would only have had more trouble to obtain them; that is
all. If, then, experiment confirms his conclusions, will he think that
he has demonstrated, for instance, the real existence of atoms?

In optical theories two vectors are introduced, of which one is regarded
as a velocity, the other as a vortex. Here again is a neutral
hypothesis, since the same conclusions would have been reached by taking
precisely the opposite. The success of the experiment, then, can not
prove that the first vector is indeed a velocity; it can only prove one
thing, that it is a vector. This is the only hypothesis that has really
been introduced in the premises. In order to give it that concrete
appearance which the weakness of our minds requires, it has been
necessary to consider it either as a velocity or as a vortex, in the
same way that it has been necessary to represent it by a letter, either
_x_ or _y_. The result, however, whatever it may be, will not prove that
it was right or wrong to regard it as a velocity any more than it will
prove that it was right or wrong to call it _x_ and not _y_.

These neutral hypotheses are never dangerous, if only their character is
not misunderstood. They may be useful, either as devices for
computation, or to aid our understanding by concrete images, to fix our
ideas as the saying is. There is, then, no occasion to exclude them.

The hypotheses of the third class are the real generalizations. They are
the ones that experiment must confirm or invalidate. Whether verified or
condemned, they will always be fruitful. But for the reasons that I have
set forth, they will only be fruitful if they are not too numerous.

ORIGIN OF MATHEMATICAL PHYSICS.--Let us penetrate further, and study
more closely the conditions that have permitted the development of
mathematical physics. We observe at once that the efforts of scientists
have always aimed to resolve the complex phenomenon directly given by
experiment into a very large number of elementary phenomena.

This is done in three different ways: first, in time. Instead of
embracing in its entirety the progressive development of a phenomenon,
the aim is simply to connect each instant with the instant immediately
preceding it. It is admitted that the actual state of the world depends
only on the immediate past, without being directly influenced, so to
speak, by the memory of a distant past. Thanks to this postulate,
instead of studying directly the whole succession of phenomena, it is
possible to confine ourselves to writing its 'differential equation.'
For Kepler's laws we substitute Newton's law.

Next we try to analyze the phenomenon in space. What experiment gives us
is a confused mass of facts presented on a stage of considerable extent.
We must try to discover the elementary phenomenon, which will be, on the
contrary, localized in a very small region of space.

Some examples will perhaps make my thought better understood. If we
wished to study in all its complexity the distribution of temperature in
a cooling solid, we should never succeed. Everything becomes simple if
we reflect that one point of the solid can not give up its heat directly
to a distant point; it will give up its heat only to the points in the
immediate neighborhood, and it is by degrees that the flow of heat can
reach other parts of the solid. The elementary phenomenon is the
exchange of heat between two contiguous points. It is strictly
localized, and is relatively simple, if we admit, as is natural, that it
is not influenced by the temperature of molecules whose distance is
sensible.

I bend a rod. It is going to take a very complicated form, the direct
study of which would be impossible. But I shall be able, however, to
attack it, if I observe that its flexure is a result only of the
deformation of the very small elements of the rod, and that the
deformation of each of these elements depends only on the forces that
are directly applied to it, and not at all on those which may act on the
other elements.

In all these examples, which I might easily multiply, we admit that
there is no action at a distance, or at least at a great distance. This
is a hypothesis. It is not always true, as the law of gravitation shows
us. It must, then, be submitted to verification. If it is confirmed,
even approximately, it is precious, for it will enable us to make
mathematical physics, at least by successive approximations.

If it does not stand the test, we must look for something else
analogous; for there are still other means of arriving at the elementary
phenomenon. If several bodies act simultaneously, it may happen that
their actions are independent and are simply added to one another,
either as vectors or as scalars. The elementary phenomenon is then the
action of an isolated body. Or again, we have to deal with small
movements, or more generally with small variations, which obey the
well-known law of superposition. The observed movement will then be
decomposed into simple movements, for example, sound into its harmonics,
white light into its monochromatic components.

When we have discovered in what direction it is advisable to look for
the elementary phenomenon, by what means can we reach it?

First of all, it will often happen that in order to detect it, or rather
to detect the part of it useful to us, it will not be necessary to
penetrate the mechanism; the law of great numbers will suffice.

Let us take again the instance of the propagation of heat. Every
molecule emits rays toward every neighboring molecule. According to what
law, we do not need to know. If we should make any supposition in regard
to this, it would be a neutral hypothesis and consequently useless and
incapable of verification. And, in fact, by the action of averages and
thanks to the symmetry of the medium, all the differences are leveled
down, and whatever hypothesis may be made, the result is always the
same.

The same circumstance is presented in the theory of electricity and in
that of capillarity. The neighboring molecules attract and repel one
another. We do not need to know according to what law; it is enough for
us that this attraction is sensible only at small distances, and that
the molecules are very numerous, that the medium is symmetrical, and we
shall only have to let the law of great numbers act.

Here again the simplicity of the elementary phenomenon was hidden under
the complexity of the resultant observable phenomenon; but, in its turn,
this simplicity was only apparent, and concealed a very complex
mechanism.

The best means of arriving at the elementary phenomenon would evidently
be experiment. We ought by experimental contrivance to dissociate the
complex sheaf that nature offers to our researches, and to study with
care the elements as much isolated as possible. For example, natural
white light would be decomposed into monochromatic lights by the aid of
the prism, and into polarized light by the aid of the polarizer.

Unfortunately that is neither always possible nor always sufficient, and
sometimes the mind must outstrip experiment. I shall cite only one
example, which has always struck me forcibly.

If I decompose white light, I shall be able to isolate a small part of
the spectrum, but however small it may be, it will retain a certain
breadth. Likewise the natural lights, called _monochromatic_, give us a
very narrow line, but not, however, infinitely narrow. It might be
supposed that by studying experimentally the properties of these natural
lights, by working with finer and finer lines of the spectrum, and by
passing at last to the limit, so to speak, we should succeed in learning
the properties of a light strictly monochromatic.

That would not be accurate. Suppose that two rays emanate from the same
source, that we polarize them first in two perpendicular planes, then
bring them back to the same plane of polarization, and try to make them
interfere. If the light were _strictly_ monochromatic, they would
interfere. With our lights, which are nearly monochromatic, there will
be no interference, and that no matter how narrow the line. In order to
be otherwise it would have to be several million times as narrow as the
finest known lines.

Here, then, the passage to the limit would have deceived us. The mind
must outstrip the experiment, and if it has done so with success, it is
because it has allowed itself to be guided by the instinct of
simplicity.

The knowledge of the elementary fact enables us to put the problem in an
equation. Nothing remains but to deduce from this by combination the
complex fact that can be observed and verified. This is what is called
_integration_, and is the business of the mathematician.

It may be asked why, in physical sciences, generalization so readily
takes the mathematical form. The reason is now easy to see. It is not
only because we have numerical laws to express; it is because the
observable phenomenon is due to the superposition of a great number of
elementary phenomena _all alike_. Thus quite naturally are introduced
differential equations.

It is not enough that each elementary phenomenon obeys simple laws; all
those to be combined must obey the same law. Then only can the
intervention of mathematics be of use; mathematics teaches us in fact to
combine like with like. Its aim is to learn the result of a combination
without needing to go over the combination piece by piece. If we have to
repeat several times the same operation, it enables us to avoid this
repetition by telling us in advance the result of it by a sort of
induction. I have explained this above, in the chapter on mathematical
reasoning.

But for this, all the operations must be alike. In the opposite case, it
would evidently be necessary to resign ourselves to doing them in
reality one after another, and mathematics would become useless.

It is then thanks to the approximate homogeneity of the matter studied
by physicists that mathematical physics could be born.

In the natural sciences, we no longer find these conditions:
homogeneity, relative independence of remote parts, simplicity of the
elementary fact; and this is why naturalists are obliged to resort to
other methods of generalization.



CHAPTER X

THE THEORIES OF MODERN PHYSICS


MEANING OF PHYSICAL THEORIES.--The laity are struck to see how ephemeral
scientific theories are. After some years of prosperity, they see them
successively abandoned; they see ruins accumulate upon ruins; they
foresee that the theories fashionable to-day will shortly succumb in
their turn and hence they conclude that these are absolutely idle. This
is what they call the _bankruptcy of science_.

Their skepticism is superficial; they give no account to themselves of
the aim and the rôle of scientific theories; otherwise they would
comprehend that the ruins may still be good for something.

No theory seemed more solid than that of Fresnel which attributed light
to motions of the ether. Yet now Maxwell's is preferred. Does this mean
the work of Fresnel was in vain? No, because the aim of Fresnel was not
to find out whether there is really an ether, whether it is or is not
formed of atoms, whether these atoms really move in this or that sense;
his object was to foresee optical phenomena.

Now, Fresnel's theory always permits of this, to-day as well as before
Maxwell. The differential equations are always true; they can always be
integrated by the same procedures and the results of this integration
always retain their value.

And let no one say that thus we reduce physical theories to the rôle of
mere practical recipes; these equations express relations, and if the
equations remain true it is because these relations preserve their
reality. They teach us, now as then, that there is such and such a
relation between some thing and some other thing; only this something
formerly we called _motion_; we now call it _electric current_. But
these appellations were only images substituted for the real objects
which nature will eternally hide from us. The true relations between
these real objects are the only reality we can attain to, and the only
condition is that the same relations exist between these objects as
between the images by which we are forced to replace them. If these
relations are known to us, what matter if we deem it convenient to
replace one image by another.

That some periodic phenomenon (an electric oscillation, for instance) is
really due to the vibration of some atom which, acting like a pendulum,
really moves in this or that sense, is neither certain nor interesting.
But that between electric oscillation, the motion of the pendulum and
all periodic phenomena there exists a close relationship which
corresponds to a profound reality; that this relationship, this
similitude, or rather this parallelism extends into details; that it is
a consequence of more general principles, that of energy and that of
least action; this is what we can affirm; this is the truth which will
always remain the same under all the costumes in which we may deem it
useful to deck it out.

Numerous theories of dispersion have been proposed; the first was
imperfect and contained only a small part of truth. Afterwards came that
of Helmholtz; then it was modified in various ways, and its author
himself imagined another founded on the principles of Maxwell. But, what
is remarkable, all the scientists who came after Helmholtz reached the
same equations, starting from points of departure in appearance very
widely separated. I will venture to say these theories are all true at
the same time, not only because they make us foresee the same phenomena,
but because they put in evidence a true relation, that of absorption and
anomalous dispersion. What is true in the premises of these theories is
what is common to all the authors; this is the affirmation of this or
that relation between certain things which some call by one name, others
by another.

The kinetic theory of gases has given rise to many objections, which we
could hardly answer if we pretended to see in it the absolute truth. But
all these objections will not preclude its having been useful, and
particularly so in revealing to us a relation true and but for it
profoundly hidden, that of the gaseous pressure and the osmotic
pressure. In this sense, then, it may be said to be true.

When a physicist finds a contradiction between two theories equally
dear to him, he sometimes says: "We will not bother about that, but hold
firmly the two ends of the chain, though the intermediate links are
hidden from us." This argument of an embarrassed theologian would be
ridiculous if it were necessary to attribute to physical theories the
sense the laity give them. In case of contradiction, one of them at
least must then be regarded as false. It is no longer the same if in
them be sought only what should be sought. May be they both express true
relations and the contradiction is only in the images wherewith we have
clothed the reality.

To those who find we restrict too much the domain accessible to the
scientist, I answer: These questions which we interdict to you and which
you regret, are not only insoluble, they are illusory and devoid of
meaning.

Some philosopher pretends that all physics may be explained by the
mutual impacts of atoms. If he merely means there are between physical
phenomena the same relations as between the mutual impacts of a great
number of balls, well and good, that is verifiable, that is perhaps
true. But he means something more; and we think we understand it because
we think we know what impact is in itself; why? Simply because we have
often seen games of billiards. Shall we think God, contemplating his
work, feels the same sensations as we in watching a billiard match? If
we do not wish to give this bizarre sense to his assertion, if neither
do we wish the restricted sense I have just explained, which is good
sense, then it has none.

Hypotheses of this sort have therefore only a metaphorical sense. The
scientist should no more interdict them than the poet does metaphors;
but he ought to know what they are worth. They may be useful to give a
certain satisfaction to the mind, and they will not be injurious
provided they are only indifferent hypotheses.

These considerations explain to us why certain theories, supposed to be
abandoned and finally condemned by experiment, suddenly arise from their
ashes and recommence a new life. It is because they expressed true
relations; and because they had not ceased to do so when, for one reason
or another, we felt it necessary to enunciate the same relations in
another language. So they retained a sort of latent life.

Scarcely fifteen years ago was there anything more ridiculous, more
naïvely antiquated, than Coulomb's fluids? And yet here they are
reappearing under the name of _electrons_. Wherein do these permanently
electrified molecules differ from Coulomb's electric molecules? It is
true that in the electrons the electricity is supported by a little, a
very little matter; in other words, they have a mass (and yet this is
now contested); but Coulomb did not deny mass to his fluids, or, if he
did, it was only with reluctance. It would be rash to affirm that the
belief in electrons will not again suffer eclipse; it was none the less
curious to note this unexpected resurrection.

But the most striking example is Carnot's principle. Carnot set it up
starting from false hypotheses; when it was seen that heat is not
indestructible, but may be transformed into work, his ideas were
completely abandoned; afterwards Clausius returned to them and made them
finally triumph. Carnot's theory, under its primitive form, expressed,
aside from true relations, other inexact relations, _débris_ of
antiquated ideas; but the presence of these latter did not change the
reality of the others. Clausius had only to discard them as one lops off
dead branches.

The result was the second fundamental law of thermodynamics. There were
always the same relations; though these relations no longer subsisted,
at least in appearance, between the same objects. This was enough for
the principle to retain its value. And even the reasonings of Carnot
have not perished because of that; they were applied to a material
tainted with error; but their form (that is to say, the essential)
remained correct.

What I have just said illuminates at the same time the rôle of general
principles such as the principle of least action, or that of the
conservation of energy.

These principles have a very high value; they were obtained in seeking
what there was in common in the enunciation of numerous physical laws;
they represent therefore, as it were, the quintessence of innumerable
observations.

However, from their very generality a consequence results to which I
have called attention in Chapter VIII, namely, that they can no longer
be verified. As we can not give a general definition of energy, the
principle of the conservation of energy signifies simply that there is
_something_ which remains constant. Well, whatever be the new notions
that future experiments shall give us about the world, we are sure in
advance that there will be something there which will remain constant
and which may be called _energy_.

Is this to say that the principle has no meaning and vanishes in a
tautology? Not at all; it signifies that the different things to which
we give the name of _energy_ are connected by a true kinship; it affirms
a real relation between them. But then if this principle has a meaning,
it may be false; it may be that we have not the right to extend
indefinitely its applications, and yet it is certain beforehand to be
verified in the strict acceptation of the term; how then shall we know
when it shall have attained all the extension which can legitimately be
given it? Just simply when it shall cease to be useful to us, that is,
to make us correctly foresee new phenomena. We shall be sure in such a
case that the relation affirmed is no longer real; for otherwise it
would be fruitful; experiment, without directly contradicting a new
extension of the principle, will yet have condemned it.

PHYSICS AND MECHANISM.--Most theorists have a constant predilection for
explanations borrowed from mechanics or dynamics. Some would be
satisfied if they could explain all phenomena by motions of molecules
attracting each other according to certain laws. Others are more
exacting; they would suppress attractions at a distance; their molecules
should follow rectilinear paths from which they could be made to deviate
only by impacts. Others again, like Hertz, suppress forces also, but
suppose their molecules subjected to geometric attachments analogous,
for instance, to those of our linkages; they try thus to reduce dynamics
to a sort of kinematics.

In a word, all would bend nature into a certain form outside of which
their mind could not feel satisfied. Will nature be sufficiently
flexible for that?

We shall examine this question in Chapter XII, _à propos_ of Maxwell's
theory. Whenever the principles of energy and of least action are
satisfied, we shall see not only that there is always one possible
mechanical explanation, but that there is always an infinity of them.
Thanks to a well-known theorem of König's on linkages, it could be
shown that we can, in an infinity of ways, explain everything by
attachments after the manner of Hertz, or also by central forces.
Without doubt it could be demonstrated just as easily that everything
can always be explained by simple impacts.

For that, of course, we need not be content with ordinary matter, with
that which falls under our senses and whose motions we observe directly.
Either we shall suppose that this common matter is formed of atoms whose
internal motions elude us, the displacement of the totality alone
remaining accessible to our senses. Or else we shall imagine some one of
those subtile fluids which under the name of _ether_ or under other
names, have at all times played so great a rôle in physical theories.

Often one goes further and regards the ether as the sole primitive
matter or even as the only true matter. The more moderate consider
common matter as condensed ether, which is nothing startling; but others
reduce still further its importance and see in it nothing more than the
geometric locus of the ether's singularities. For instance, what we call
_matter_ is for Lord Kelvin only the locus of points where the ether is
animated by vortex motions; for Riemann, it was the locus of points
where ether is constantly destroyed; for other more recent authors,
Wiechert or Larmor, it is the locus of points where the ether undergoes
a sort of torsion of a very particular nature. If the attempt is made to
occupy one of these points of view, I ask myself by what right shall we
extend to the ether, under pretext that this is the true matter,
mechanical properties observed in ordinary matter, which is only false
matter.

The ancient fluids, caloric, electricity, etc., were abandoned when it
was perceived that heat is not indestructible. But they were abandoned
for another reason also. In materializing them, their individuality was,
so to speak, emphasized, a sort of abyss was opened between them. This
had to be filled up on the coming of a more vivid feeling of the unity
of nature, and the perception of the intimate relations which bind
together all its parts. Not only did the old physicists, in multiplying
fluids, create entities unnecessarily, but they broke real ties.

It is not sufficient for a theory to affirm no false relations, it must
not hide true relations.

And does our ether really exist? We know the origin of our belief in the
ether. If light reaches us from a distant star, during several years it
was no longer on the star and not yet on the earth; it must then be
somewhere and sustained, so to speak, by some material support.

The same idea may be expressed under a more mathematical and more
abstract form. What we ascertain are the changes undergone by material
molecules; we see, for instance, that our photographic plate feels the
consequences of phenomena of which the incandescent mass of the star was
the theater several years before. Now, in ordinary mechanics the state
of the system studied depends only on its state at an instant
immediately anterior; therefore the system satisfies differential
equations. On the contrary, if we should not believe in the ether, the
state of the material universe would depend not only on the state
immediately preceding, but on states much older; the system would
satisfy equations of finite differences. It is to escape this derogation
of the general laws of mechanics that we have invented the ether.

That would still only oblige us to fill up, with the ether, the
interplanetary void, but not to make it penetrate the bosom of the
material media themselves. Fizeau's experiment goes further. By the
interference of rays which have traversed air or water in motion, it
seems to show us two different media interpenetrating and yet changing
place one with regard to the other.

We seem to touch the ether with the finger.

Yet experiments may be conceived which would make us touch it still more
nearly. Suppose Newton's principle, of the equality of action and
reaction, no longer true if applied to matter _alone_, and that we have
established it. The geometric sum of all the forces applied to all the
material molecules would no longer be null. It would be necessary then,
if we did not wish to change all mechanics, to introduce the ether, in
order that this action which matter appeared to experience should be
counterbalanced by the reaction of matter on something.

Or again, suppose we discover that optical and electrical phenomena are
influenced by the motion of the earth. We should be led to conclude that
these phenomena might reveal to us not only the relative motions of
material bodies, but what would seem to be their absolute motions.
Again, an ether would be necessary, that these so-called absolute
motions should not be their displacements with regard to a void space,
but their displacements with regard to something concrete.

Shall we ever arrive at that? I have not this hope, I shall soon say
why, and yet it is not so absurd, since others have had it.

For instance, if the theory of Lorentz, of which I shall speak in detail
further on in Chapter XIII., were true, Newton's principle would not
apply to matter _alone_, and the difference would not be very far from
being accessible to experiment.

On the other hand, many researches have been made on the influence of
the earth's motion. The results have always been negative. But these
experiments were undertaken because the outcome was not sure in advance,
and, indeed, according to the ruling theories, the compensation would be
only approximate, and one might expect to see precise methods give
positive results.

I believe that such a hope is illusory; it was none the less interesting
to show that a success of this sort would open to us, in some sort, a
new world.

And now I must be permitted a digression; I must explain, in fact, why I
do not believe, despite Lorentz, that more precise observations can ever
put in evidence anything else than the relative displacements of
material bodies. Experiments have been made which should have disclosed
the terms of the first order; the results have been negative; could that
be by chance? No one has assumed that; a general explanation has been
sought, and Lorentz has found it; he has shown that the terms of the
first order must destroy each other, but not those of the second. Then
more precise experiments were made; they also were negative; neither
could this be the effect of chance; an explanation was necessary; it was
found; they always are found; of hypotheses there is never lack.

But this is not enough; who does not feel that this is still to leave to
chance too great a rôle? Would not that also be a chance, this singular
coincidence which brought it about that a certain circumstance should
come just in the nick of time to destroy the terms of the first order,
and that another circumstance, wholly different, but just as opportune,
should take upon itself to destroy those of the second order? No, it is
necessary to find an explanation the same for the one as for the other,
and then everything leads us to think that this explanation will hold
good equally well for the terms of higher order, and that the mutual
destruction of these terms will be rigorous and absolute.

PRESENT STATE OF THE SCIENCE.--In the history of the development of
physics we distinguish two inverse tendencies.

On the one hand, new bonds are continually being discovered between
objects which had seemed destined to remain forever unconnected;
scattered facts cease to be strangers to one another; they tend to
arrange themselves in an imposing synthesis. Science advances toward
unity and simplicity.

On the other hand, observation reveals to us every day new phenomena;
they must long await their place and sometimes, to make one for them, a
corner of the edifice must be demolished. In the known phenomena
themselves, where our crude senses showed us uniformity, we perceive
details from day to day more varied; what we believed simple becomes
complex, and science appears to advance toward variety and complexity.

Of these two inverse tendencies, which seem to triumph turn about, which
will win? If it be the first, science is possible; but nothing proves
this _a priori_, and it may well be feared that after having made vain
efforts to bend nature in spite of herself to our ideal of unity,
submerged by the ever-rising flood of our new riches, we must renounce
classifying them, abandon our ideal, and reduce science to the
registration of innumerable recipes.

To this question we can not reply. All we can do is to observe the
science of to-day and compare it with that of yesterday. From this
examination we may doubtless draw some encouragement.

Half a century ago, hope ran high. The discovery of the conservation of
energy and of its transformations had revealed to us the unity of force.
Thus it showed that the phenomena of heat could be explained by
molecular motions. What was the nature of these motions was not exactly
known, but no one doubted that it soon would be. For light, the task
seemed completely accomplished. In what concerns electricity, things
were less advanced. Electricity had just annexed magnetism. This was a
considerable step toward unity, and a decisive step.

But how should electricity in its turn enter into the general unity, how
should it be reduced to the universal mechanism?

Of that no one had any idea. Yet the possibility of this reduction was
doubted by none, there was faith. Finally, in what concerns the
molecular properties of material bodies, the reduction seemed still
easier, but all the detail remained hazy. In a word, the hopes were vast
and animated, but vague. To-day, what do we see? First of all, a prime
progress, immense progress. The relations of electricity and light are
now known; the three realms, of light, of electricity and of magnetism,
previously separated, form now but one; and this annexation seems final.

This conquest, however, has cost us some sacrifices. The optical
phenomena subordinate themselves as particular cases under the
electrical phenomena; so long as they remained isolated, it was easy to
explain them by motions that were supposed to be known in all their
details, that was a matter of course; but now an explanation, to be
acceptable, must be easily capable of extension to the entire electric
domain. Now that is a matter not without difficulties.

The most satisfactory theory we have is that of Lorentz, which, as we
shall see in the last chapter, explains electric currents by the motions
of little electrified particles; it is unquestionably the one which best
explains the known facts, the one which illuminates the greatest number
of true relations, the one of which most traces will be found in the
final construction. Nevertheless, it still has a serious defect, which I
have indicated above; it is contrary to Newton's law of the equality of
action and reaction; or rather, this principle, in the eyes of Lorentz,
would not be applicable to matter alone; for it to be true, it would be
necessary to take account of the action of the ether on matter and of
the reaction of matter on the ether.

Now, from what we know at present, it seems probable that things do not
happen in this way.

However that may be, thanks to Lorentz, Fizeau's results on the optics
of moving bodies, the laws of normal and anomalous dispersion and of
absorption find themselves linked to one another and to the other
properties of the ether by bonds which beyond any doubt will never more
be broken. See the facility with which the new Zeeman effect has found
its place already and has even aided in classifying Faraday's magnetic
rotation which had defied Maxwell's efforts; this facility abundantly
proves that the theory of Lorentz is not an artificial assemblage
destined to fall asunder. It will probably have to be modified, but not
destroyed.

But Lorentz had no aim beyond that of embracing in one totality all the
optics and electrodynamics of moving bodies; he never pretended to give
a mechanical explanation of them. Larmor goes further; retaining the
theory of Lorentz in essentials, he grafts upon it, so to speak,
MacCullagh's ideas on the direction of the motions of the ether.

According to him, the velocity of the ether would have the same
direction and the same magnitude as the magnetic force. However
ingenious this attempt may be, the defect of the theory of Lorentz
remains and is even aggravated. With Lorentz, we do not know what are
the motions of the ether; thanks to this ignorance, we may suppose them
such that, compensating those of matter, they reestablish the equality
of action and reaction. With Larmor, we know the motions of the ether,
and we can ascertain that the compensation does not take place.

If Larmor has failed, as it seems to me he has, does that mean that a
mechanical explanation is impossible? Far from it: I have said above
that when a phenomenon obeys the two principles of energy and of least
action, it admits of an infinity of mechanical explanations; so it is,
therefore, with the optical and electrical phenomena.

But this is not enough: for a mechanical explanation to be good, it must
be simple; for choosing it among all which are possible, there should be
other reasons besides the necessity of making a choice. Well, we have
not as yet a theory satisfying this condition and consequently good for
something. Must we lament this? That would be to forget what is the goal
sought; this is not mechanism; the true, the sole aim is unity.

We must therefore set bounds to our ambition; let us not try to
formulate a mechanical explanation; let us be content with showing that
we could always find one if we wished to. In this regard we have been
successful; the principle of the conservation of energy has received
only confirmations; a second principle has come to join it, that of
least action, put under the form which is suitable for physics. It also
has always been verified, at least in so far as concerns reversible
phenomena which thus obey the equations of Lagrange, that is to say, the
most general laws of mechanics.

Irreversible phenomena are much more rebellious. Yet these also are
being coordinated, and tend to come into unity; the light which has
illuminated them has come to us from Carnot's principle. Long did
thermodynamics confine itself to the study of the dilatation of bodies
and their changes of state. For some time past it has been growing
bolder and has considerably extended its domain. We owe to it the theory
of the galvanic battery and that of the thermoelectric phenomena; there
is not in all physics a corner that it has not explored, and it has
attacked chemistry itself.

Everywhere the same laws reign; everywhere, under the diversity of
appearances, is found again Carnot's principle; everywhere also is found
that concept so prodigiously abstract of entropy, which is as universal
as that of energy and seems like it to cover a reality. Radiant heat
seemed destined to escape it; but recently we have seen that submit to
the same laws.

In this way fresh analogies are revealed to us, which may often be
followed into detail; ohmic resistance resembles the viscosity of
liquids; hysteresis would resemble rather the friction of solids. In all
cases, friction would appear to be the type which the most various
irreversible phenomena copy, and this kinship is real and profound.

Of these phenomena a mechanical explanation, properly so called, has
also been sought. They hardly lent themselves to it. To find it, it was
necessary to suppose that the irreversibility is only apparent, that the
elementary phenomena are reversible and obey the known laws of dynamics.
But the elements are extremely numerous and blend more and more, so that
to our crude sight all appears to tend toward uniformity, that is,
everything seems to go forward in the same sense without hope of
return. The apparent irreversibility is thus only an effect of the law
of great numbers. But, only a being with infinitely subtile senses, like
Maxwell's imaginary demon, could disentangle this inextricable skein and
turn back the course of the universe.

This conception, which attaches itself to the kinetic theory of gases,
has cost great efforts and has not, on the whole, been fruitful; but it
may become so. This is not the place to examine whether it does not lead
to contradictions and whether it is in conformity with the true nature
of things.

We signalize, however, M. Gouy's original ideas on the Brownian
movement. According to this scientist, this singular motion should
escape Carnot's principle. The particles which it puts in swing would be
smaller than the links of that so compacted skein; they would therefore
be fitted to disentangle them and hence to make the world go backward.
We should almost see Maxwell's demon at work.

To summarize, the previously known phenomena are better and better
classified, but new phenomena come to claim their place; most of these,
like the Zeeman effect, have at once found it.

But we have the cathode rays, the X-rays, those of uranium and of
radium. Herein is a whole world which no one suspected. How many
unexpected guests must be stowed away?

No one can yet foresee the place they will occupy. But I do not believe
they will destroy the general unity; I think they will rather complete
it. On the one hand, in fact, the new radiations seem connected with the
phenomena of luminescence; not only do they excite fluorescence, but
they sometimes take birth in the same conditions as it.

Nor are they without kinship with the causes which produce the electric
spark under the action of the ultra-violet light.

Finally, and above all, it is believed that in all these phenomena are
found true ions, animated, it is true, by velocities incomparably
greater than in the electrolytes.

That is all very vague, but it will all become more precise.

Phosphorescence, the action of light on the spark, these were regions
rather isolated and consequently somewhat neglected by investigators.
One may now hope that a new path will be constructed which will
facilitate their communications with the rest of science.

Not only do we discover new phenomena, but in those we thought we knew,
unforeseen aspects reveal themselves. In the free ether, the laws retain
their majestic simplicity; but matter, properly so called, seems more
and more complex; all that is said of it is never more than approximate,
and at each instant our formulas require new terms.

Nevertheless the frames are not broken; the relations that we have
recognized between objects we thought simple still subsist between these
same objects when we know their complexity, and it is that alone which
is of importance. Our equations become, it is true, more and more
complicated, in order to embrace more closely the complexity of nature;
but nothing is changed in the relations which permit the deducing of
these equations one from another. In a word, the form of these equations
has persisted.

Take, for example, the laws of reflection: Fresnel had established them
by a simple and seductive theory which experiment seemed to confirm.
Since then more precise researches have proved that this verification
was only approximate; they have shown everywhere traces of elliptic
polarization. But, thanks to the help that the first approximation gave
us, we found forthwith the cause of these anomalies, which is the
presence of a transition layer; and Fresnel's theory has subsisted in
its essentials.

But there is a reflection we can not help making: All these relations
would have remained unperceived if one had at first suspected the
complexity of the objects they connect. It has long been said: If Tycho
had had instruments ten times more precise neither Kepler, nor Newton,
nor astronomy would ever have been. It is a misfortune for a science to
be born too late, when the means of observation have become too perfect.
This is to-day the case with physical chemistry; its founders are
embarrassed in their general grasp by third and fourth decimals; happily
they are men of a robust faith.

The better one knows the properties of matter the more one sees
continuity reign. Since the labors of Andrews and of van der Waals, we
get an idea of how the passage is made from the liquid to the gaseous
state and that this passage is not abrupt. Similarly, there is no gap
between the liquid and solid states, and in the proceedings of a recent
congress is to be seen, alongside of a work on the rigidity of liquids,
a memoir on the flow of solids.

By this tendency no doubt simplicity loses; some phenomenon was formerly
represented by several straight lines, now these straights must be
joined by curves more or less complicated. In compensation unity gains
notably. Those cut-off categories quieted the mind, but they did not
satisfy it.

Finally the methods of physics have invaded a new domain, that of
chemistry; physical chemistry is born. It is still very young, but we
already see that it will enable us to connect such phenomena as
electrolysis, osmosis and the motions of ions.

From this rapid exposition, what shall we conclude?

Everything considered, we have approached unity; we have not been as
quick as was hoped fifty years ago, we have not always taken the
predicted way; but, finally, we have gained ever so much ground.



CHAPTER XI

THE CALCULUS OF PROBABILITIES


Doubtless it will be astonishing to find here thoughts about the
calculus of probabilities. What has it to do with the method of the
physical sciences? And yet the questions I shall raise without solving
present themselves naturally to the philosopher who is thinking about
physics. So far is this the case that in the two preceding chapters I
have often been led to use the words 'probability' and 'chance.'

'Predicted facts,' as I have said above, 'can only be probable.'
"However solidly founded a prediction may seem to us to be, we are never
absolutely sure that experiment will not prove it false. But the
probability is often so great that practically we may be satisfied with
it." And a little further on I have added: "See what a rôle the belief
in simplicity plays in our generalizations. We have verified a simple
law in a great number of particular cases; we refuse to admit that this
coincidence, so often repeated, can be a mere effect of chance...."

Thus in a multitude of circumstances the physicist is in the same
position as the gambler who reckons up his chances. As often as he
reasons by induction, he requires more or less consciously the calculus
of probabilities, and this is why I am obliged to introduce a
parenthesis, and interrupt our study of method in the physical sciences
in order to examine a little more closely the value of this calculus,
and what confidence it merits.

The very name calculus of probabilities is a paradox. Probability
opposed to certainty is what we do not know, and how can we calculate
what we do not know? Yet many eminent savants have occupied themselves
with this calculus, and it can not be denied that science has drawn
therefrom no small advantage.

How can we explain this apparent contradiction?

Has probability been defined? Can it even be defined? And if it can not,
how dare we reason about it? The definition, it will be said, is very
simple: the probability of an event is the ratio of the number of cases
favorable to this event to the total number of possible cases.

A simple example will show how incomplete this definition is. I throw
two dice. What is the probability that one of the two at least turns up
a six? Each die can turn up in six different ways; the number of
possible cases is 6 × 6 = 36; the number of favorable cases is 11; the
probability is 11/36.

That is the correct solution. But could I not just as well say: The
points which turn up on the two dice can form 6 × 7/2 = 21 different
combinations? Among these combinations 6 are favorable; the probability
is 6/21.

Now why is the first method of enumerating the possible cases more
legitimate than the second? In any case it is not our definition that
tells us.

We are therefore obliged to complete this definition by saying: '... to
the total number of possible cases provided these cases are equally
probable.' So, therefore, we are reduced to defining the probable by the
probable.

How can we know that two possible cases are equally probable? Will it be
by a convention? If we place at the beginning of each problem an
explicit convention, well and good. We shall then have nothing to do but
apply the rules of arithmetic and of algebra, and we shall complete our
calculation without our result leaving room for doubt. But if we wish to
make the slightest application of this result, we must prove our
convention was legitimate, and we shall find ourselves in the presence
of the very difficulty we thought to escape.

Will it be said that good sense suffices to show us what convention
should be adopted? Alas! M. Bertrand has amused himself by discussing
the following simple problem: "What is the probability that a chord of a
circle may be greater than the side of the inscribed equilateral
triangle?" The illustrious geometer successively adopted two conventions
which good sense seemed equally to dictate and with one he found 1/2,
with the other 1/3.

The conclusion which seems to follow from all this is that the calculus
of probabilities is a useless science, and that the obscure instinct
which we may call good sense, and to which we are wont to appeal to
legitimatize our conventions, must be distrusted.

But neither can we subscribe to this conclusion; we can not do without
this obscure instinct. Without it science would be impossible, without
it we could neither discover a law nor apply it. Have we the right, for
instance, to enunciate Newton's law? Without doubt, numerous
observations are in accord with it; but is not this a simple effect of
chance? Besides how do we know whether this law, true for so many
centuries, will still be true next year? To this objection, you will
find nothing to reply, except: 'That is very improbable.'

But grant the law. Thanks to it, I believe myself able to calculate the
position of Jupiter a year from now. Have I the right to believe this?
Who can tell if a gigantic mass of enormous velocity will not between
now and that time pass near the solar system, and produce unforeseen
perturbations? Here again the only answer is: 'It is very improbable.'

From this point of view, all the sciences would be only unconscious
applications of the calculus of probabilities. To condemn this calculus
would be to condemn the whole of science.

I shall dwell lightly on the scientific problems in which the
intervention of the calculus of probabilities is more evident. In the
forefront of these is the problem of interpolation, in which, knowing a
certain number of values of a function, we seek to divine the
intermediate values.

I shall likewise mention: the celebrated theory of errors of
observation, to which I shall return later; the kinetic theory of gases,
a well-known hypothesis, wherein each gaseous molecule is supposed to
describe an extremely complicated trajectory, but in which, through the
effect of great numbers, the mean phenomena, alone observable, obey the
simple laws of Mariotte and Gay-Lussac.

All these theories are based on the laws of great numbers, and the
calculus of probabilities would evidently involve them in its ruin. It
is true that they have only a particular interest and that, save as far
as interpolation is concerned, these are sacrifices to which we might
readily be resigned.

But, as I have said above, it would not be only these partial
sacrifices that would be in question; it would be the legitimacy of the
whole of science that would be challenged.

I quite see that it might be said: "We are ignorant, and yet we must
act. For action, we have not time to devote ourselves to an inquiry
sufficient to dispel our ignorance. Besides, such an inquiry would
demand an infinite time. We must therefore decide without knowing; we
are obliged to do so, hit or miss, and we must follow rules without
quite believing them. What I know is not that such and such a thing is
true, but that the best course for me is to act as if it were true." The
calculus of probabilities, and consequently science itself, would
thenceforth have merely a practical value.

Unfortunately the difficulty does not thus disappear. A gambler wants to
try a _coup_; he asks my advice. If I give it to him, I shall use the
calculus of probabilities, but I shall not guarantee success. This is
what I shall call _subjective probability_. In this case, we might be
content with the explanation of which I have just given a sketch. But
suppose that an observer is present at the game, that he notes all its
_coups_, and that the game goes on a long time. When he makes a summary
of his book, he will find that events have taken place in conformity
with the laws of the calculus of probabilities. This is what I shall
call _objective probability_, and it is this phenomenon which has to be
explained.

There are numerous insurance companies which apply the rules of the
calculus of probabilities, and they distribute to their shareholders
dividends whose objective reality can not be contested. To invoke our
ignorance and the necessity to act does not suffice to explain them.

Thus absolute skepticism is not admissible. We may distrust, but we can
not condemn _en bloc_. Discussion is necessary.

I. CLASSIFICATION OF THE PROBLEMS OF PROBABILITY.--In order to classify
the problems which present themselves _à propos_ of probabilities, we
may look at them from many different points of view, and, first, from
the _point of view of generality_. I have said above that probability is
the ratio of the number of favorable cases to the number of possible
cases. What for want of a better term I call the generality will
increase with the number of possible cases. This number may be finite,
as, for instance, if we take a throw of the dice in which the number of
possible cases is 36. That is the first degree of generality.

But if we ask, for example, what is the probability that a point within
a circle is within the inscribed square, there are as many possible
cases as there are points in the circle, that is to say, an infinity.
This is the second degree of generality. Generality can be pushed
further still. We may ask the probability that a function will satisfy a
given condition. There are then as many possible cases as one can
imagine different functions. This is the third degree of generality, to
which we rise, for instance, when we seek to find the most probable law
in conformity with a finite number of observations.

We may place ourselves at a point of view wholly different. If we were
not ignorant, there would be no probability, there would be room for
nothing but certainty. But our ignorance can not be absolute, for then
there would no longer be any probability at all, since a little light is
necessary to attain even this uncertain science. Thus the problems of
probability may be classed according to the greater or less depth of
this ignorance.

In mathematics even we may set ourselves problems of probability. What
is the probability that the fifth decimal of a logarithm taken at random
from a table is a '9'? There is no hesitation in answering that this
probability is 1/10; here we possess all the data of the problem. We can
calculate our logarithm without recourse to the table, but we do not
wish to give ourselves the trouble. This is the first degree of
ignorance.

In the physical sciences our ignorance becomes greater. The state of a
system at a given instant depends on two things: Its initial state, and
the law according to which that state varies. If we know both this law
and this initial state, we shall have then only a mathematical problem
to solve, and we fall back upon the first degree of ignorance.

But it often happens that we know the law, and do not know the initial
state. It may be asked, for instance, what is the present distribution
of the minor planets? We know that from all time they have obeyed the
laws of Kepler, but we do not know what was their initial distribution.

In the kinetic theory of gases, we assume that the gaseous molecules
follow rectilinear trajectories, and obey the laws of impact of elastic
bodies. But, as we know nothing of their initial velocities, we know
nothing of their present velocities.

The calculus of probabilities only enables us to predict the mean
phenomena which will result from the combination of these velocities.
This is the second degree of ignorance.

Finally it is possible that not only the initial conditions but the laws
themselves are unknown. We then reach the third degree of ignorance and
in general we can no longer affirm anything at all as to the probability
of a phenomenon.

It often happens that instead of trying to guess an event, by means of a
more or less imperfect knowledge of the law, the events may be known and
we want to find the law; or that instead of deducing effects from
causes, we wish to deduce the causes from the effects. These are the
problems called _probability of causes_, the most interesting from the
point of view of their scientific applications.

I play écarté with a gentleman I know to be perfectly honest. He is
about to deal. What is the probability of his turning up the king? It is
1/8. This is a problem of the probability of effects.

I play with a gentleman whom I do not know. He has dealt ten times, and
he has turned up the king six times. What is the probability that he is
a sharper? This is a problem in the probability of causes.

It may be said that this is the essential problem of the experimental
method. I have observed _n_ values of _x_ and the corresponding values
of _y_. I have found that the ratio of the latter to the former is
practically constant. There is the event, what is the cause?

Is it probable that there is a general law according to which _y_ would
be proportional to _x_, and that the small divergencies are due to
errors of observation? This is a type of question that one is ever
asking, and which we unconsciously solve whenever we are engaged in
scientific work.

I am now going to pass in review these different categories of
problems, discussing in succession what I have called above subjective
and objective probability.

II. PROBABILITY IN MATHEMATICS.--The impossibility of squaring the
circle has been proved since 1882; but even before that date all
geometers considered that impossibility as so 'probable,' that the
Academy of Sciences rejected without examination the alas! too numerous
memoirs on this subject, that some unhappy madmen sent in every year.

Was the Academy wrong? Evidently not, and it knew well that in acting
thus it did not run the least risk of stifling a discovery of moment.
The Academy could not have proved that it was right; but it knew quite
well that its instinct was not mistaken. If you had asked the
Academicians, they would have answered: "We have compared the
probability that an unknown savant should have found out what has been
vainly sought for so long, with the probability that there is one madman
the more on the earth; the second appears to us the greater." These are
very good reasons, but there is nothing mathematical about them; they
are purely psychological.

And if you had pressed them further they would have added: "Why do you
suppose a particular value of a transcendental function to be an
algebraic number; and if [pi] were a root of an algebraic equation, why
do you suppose this root to be a period of the function sin 2_x_, and
not the same about the other roots of this same equation?" To sum up,
they would have invoked the principle of sufficient reason in its
vaguest form.

But what could they deduce from it? At most a rule of conduct for the
employment of their time, more usefully spent at their ordinary work
than in reading a lucubration that inspired in them a legitimate
distrust. But what I call above objective probability has nothing in
common with this first problem.

It is otherwise with the second problem.

Consider the first 10,000 logarithms that we find in a table. Among
these 10,000 logarithms I take one at random. What is the probability
that its third decimal is an even number? You will not hesitate to
answer 1/2; and in fact if you pick out in a table the third decimals of
these 10,000 numbers, you will find nearly as many even digits as odd.

Or if you prefer, let us write 10,000 numbers corresponding to our
10,000 logarithms, each of these numbers being +1 if the third decimal
of the corresponding logarithm is even, and -1 if odd. Then take the
mean of these 10,000 numbers.

I do not hesitate to say that the mean of these 10,000 numbers is
probably 0, and if I were actually to calculate it I should verify that
it is extremely small.

But even this verification is needless. I might have rigorously proved
that this mean is less than 0.003. To prove this result, I should have
had to make a rather long calculation for which there is no room here,
and for which I confine myself to citing an article I published in the
_Revue générale des Sciences_, April 15, 1899. The only point to which I
wish to call attention is the following: in this calculation, I should
have needed only to rest my case on two facts, to wit, that the first
and second derivatives of the logarithm remain, in the interval
considered, between certain limits.

Hence this important consequence that the property is true not only of
the logarithm, but of any continuous function whatever, since the
derivatives of every continuous function are limited.

If I was certain beforehand of the result, it is first, because I had
often observed analogous facts for other continuous functions; and next,
because I made in my mind, in a more or less unconscious and imperfect
manner, the reasoning which led me to the preceding inequalities, just
as a skilled calculator before finishing his multiplication takes into
account what it should come to approximately.

And besides, since what I call my intuition was only an incomplete
summary of a piece of true reasoning, it is clear why observation has
confirmed my predictions, and why the objective probability has been in
agreement with the subjective probability.

As a third example I shall choose the following problem: A number _u_
is taken at random, and _n_ is a given very large integer. What is
the probable value of sin _nu_? This problem has no meaning by itself.
To give it one a convention is needed. We _shall agree_ that the
probability for the number _u_ to lie between _a_ and _a_+ is equal to
[phi](_a_)_da_; that it is therefore proportional to the infinitely
small interval _da_, and equal to this multiplied by _a_ function
[phi](_a_) depending only on _a_. As for this function, I choose it
arbitrarily, but I must assume it to be continuous. The value of sin
_nu_ remaining the same when _u_ increases by 2[pi], I may without loss
of generality assume that _u_ lies between 0 and 2[pi], and I shall thus
be led to suppose that [phi](_a_) is a periodic function whose period is
2[pi].

The probable value sought is readily expressed by a simple integral, and
it is easy to show that this integral is less than

  2[pi]M_{_k_}/_n_^{_k_},

M_{_k_} being the maximum value of the _k_th derivative of [phi](_u_).
We see then that if the _k_th derivative is finite, our probable value
will tend toward 0 when _n_ increases indefinitely, and that more
rapidly than 1/_n_^{_k_ - 1}.

The probable value of sin _nu_ when _n_ is very large is therefore
naught. To define this value I required a convention; but the result
remains the same _whatever that convention may be_. I have imposed upon
myself only slight restrictions in assuming that the function [phi](_a_)
is continuous and periodic, and these hypotheses are so natural that we
may ask ourselves how they can be escaped.

Examination of the three preceding examples, so different in all
respects, has already given us a glimpse, on the one hand, of the rôle
of what philosophers call the principle of sufficient reason, and, on
the other hand, of the importance of the fact that certain properties
are common to all continuous functions. The study of probability in the
physical sciences will lead us to the same result.

III. PROBABILITY IN THE PHYSICAL SCIENCES.--We come now to the problems
connected with what I have called the second degree of ignorance, those,
namely, in which we know the law, but do not know the initial state of
the system. I could multiply examples, but will take only one. What is
the probable present distribution of the minor planets on the zodiac?

We know they obey the laws of Kepler. We may even, without at all
changing the nature of the problem, suppose that their orbits are all
circular, and situated in the same plane, and that we know this plane.
On the other hand, we are in absolute ignorance as to what was their
initial distribution. However, we do not hesitate to affirm that their
distribution is now nearly uniform. Why?

Let _b_ be the longitude of a minor planet in the initial epoch, that is
to say, the epoch zero. Let _a_ be its mean motion. Its longitude at the
present epoch, that is to say at the epoch _t_, will be _at_ + _b_. To
say that the present distribution is uniform is to say that the mean
value of the sines and cosines of multiples of _at_ + _b_ is zero. Why
do we assert this?

Let us represent each minor planet by a point in a plane, to wit, by a
point whose coordinates are precisely _a_ and _b_. All these
representative points will be contained in a certain region of the
plane, but as they are very numerous this region will appear dotted with
points. We know nothing else about the distribution of these points.

What do we do when we wish to apply the calculus of probabilities to
such a question? What is the probability that one or more representative
points may be found in a certain portion of the plane? In our ignorance,
we are reduced to making an arbitrary hypothesis. To explain the nature
of this hypothesis, allow me to use, in lieu of a mathematical formula,
a crude but concrete image. Let us suppose that over the surface of our
plane has been spread an imaginary substance, whose density is variable,
but varies continuously. We shall then agree to say that the probable
number of representative points to be found on a portion of the plane is
proportional to the quantity of fictitious matter found there. If we
have then two regions of the plane of the same extent, the probabilities
that a representative point of one of our minor planets is found in one
or the other of these regions will be to one another as the mean
densities of the fictitious matter in the one and the other region.

Here then are two distributions, one real, in which the representative
points are very numerous, very close together, but discrete like the
molecules of matter in the atomic hypothesis; the other remote from
reality, in which our representative points are replaced by continuous
fictitious matter. We know that the latter can not be real, but our
ignorance forces us to adopt it.

If again we had some idea of the real distribution of the representative
points, we could arrange it so that in a region of some extent the
density of this imaginary continuous matter would be nearly proportional
to the number of the representative points, or, if you wish, to the
number of atoms which are contained in that region. Even that is
impossible, and our ignorance is so great that we are forced to choose
arbitrarily the function which defines the density of our imaginary
matter. Only we shall be forced to a hypothesis from which we can hardly
get away, we shall suppose that this function is continuous. That is
sufficient, as we shall see, to enable us to reach a conclusion.

What is at the instant _t_ the probable distribution of the minor
planets? Or rather what is the probable value of the sine of the
longitude at the instant _t_, that is to say of sin (_at_ + _b_)? We
made at the outset an arbitrary convention, but if we adopt it, this
probable value is entirely defined. Divide the plane into elements of
surface. Consider the value of sin (_at_ + _b_) at the center of each of
these elements; multiply this value by the surface of the element, and
by the corresponding density of the imaginary matter. Take then the sum
for all the elements of the plane. This sum, by definition, will be the
probable mean value we seek, which will thus be expressed by a double
integral. It may be thought at first that this mean value depends on the
choice of the function which defines the density of the imaginary
matter, and that, as this function [phi] is arbitrary, we can, according
to the arbitrary choice which we make, obtain any mean value. This is
not so.

A simple calculation shows that our double integral decreases very
rapidly when _t_ increases. Thus I could not quite tell what hypothesis
to make as to the probability of this or that initial distribution; but
whatever the hypothesis made, the result will be the same, and this gets
me out of my difficulty.

Whatever be the function [phi], the mean value tends toward zero as _t_
increases, and as the minor planets have certainly accomplished a very
great number of revolutions, I may assert that this mean value is very
small.

I may choose [phi] as I wish, save always one restriction: this function
must be continuous; and, in fact, from the point of view of subjective
probability, the choice of a discontinuous function would have been
unreasonable. For instance, what reason could I have for supposing that
the initial longitude might be exactly 0°, but that it could not lie
between 0° and 1°?

But the difficulty reappears if we take the point of view of objective
probability, if we pass from our imaginary distribution in which the
fictitious matter was supposed continuous to the real distribution in
which our representative points form, as it were, discrete atoms.

The mean value of sin (_at_ + _b_) will be represented quite simply by

  (1/_n_){[Sigma] sin (_at_ + _b_)},

_n_ being the number of minor planets. In lieu of a double integral
referring to a continuous function, we shall have a sum of discrete
terms. And yet no one will seriously doubt that this mean value is
practically very small.

Our representative points being very close together, our discrete sum
will in general differ very little from an integral.

An integral is the limit toward which a sum of terms tends when the
number of these terms is indefinitely increased. If the terms are very
numerous, the sum will differ very little from its limit, that is to say
from the integral, and what I said of this latter will still be true of
the sum itself.

Nevertheless, there are exceptions. If, for instance, for all the minor
planets,

  _b_ = [pi]/2 - _at_,

the longitude for all the planets at the time t would be [pi]/2, and the
mean value would evidently be equal to unity. For this to be the case,
it would be necessary that at the epoch 0, the minor planets must have
all been lying on a spiral of peculiar form, with its spires very close
together. Every one will admit that such an initial distribution is
extremely improbable (and, even supposing it realized, the distribution
would not be uniform at the present time, for example, on January 1,
1913, but it would become so a few years later).

Why then do we think this initial distribution improbable? This must be
explained, because if we had no reason for rejecting as improbable this
absurd hypothesis everything would break down, and we could no longer
make any affirmation about the probability of this or that present
distribution.

Once more we shall invoke the principle of sufficient reason to which we
must always recur. We might admit that at the beginning the planets were
distributed almost in a straight line. We might admit that they were
irregularly distributed. But it seems to us that there is no sufficient
reason for the unknown cause that gave them birth to have acted along a
curve so regular and yet so complicated, which would appear to have been
expressly chosen so that the present distribution would not be uniform.

IV. ROUGE ET NOIR.--The questions raised by games of chance, such as
roulette, are, fundamentally, entirely analogous to those we have just
treated. For example, a wheel is partitioned into a great number of
equal subdivisions, alternately red and black. A needle is whirled with
force, and after having made a great number of revolutions, it stops
before one of these subdivisions. The probability that this division is
red is evidently 1/2. The needle describes an angle [theta], including
several complete revolutions. I do not know what is the probability that
the needle may be whirled with a force such that this angle should lie
between [theta] and [theta]+_d_[theta]; but I can make a convention. I
can suppose that this probability is [phi]([theta])_d_[theta]. As for
the function [phi]([theta]), I can choose it in an entirely arbitrary
manner. There is nothing that can guide me in my choice, but I am
naturally led to suppose this function continuous.

Let [epsilon] be the length (measured on the circumference of radius 1)
of each red and black subdivision. We have to calculate the integral of
[phi]([theta])_d_[theta], extending it, on the one hand, to all the red
divisions and, on the other hand, to all the black divisions, and to
compare the results.

Consider an interval 2[epsilon], comprising a red division and a black
division which follows it. Let M and _m_ be the greatest and least
values of the function [phi]([theta]) in this interval. The integral
extended to the red divisions will be smaller than [Sigma]M[epsilon];
the integral extended to the black divisions will be greater than
[Sigma]_m_[epsilon]; the difference will therefore be less than
[Sigma](M - _m_)[epsilon]. But, if the function [theta] is supposed
continuous; if, besides, the interval [epsilon] is very small with
respect to the total angle described by the needle, the difference
M - _m_ will be very small. The difference of the two integrals will
therefore be very small, and the probability will be very nearly 1/2.

We see that without knowing anything of the function [theta], I must act
as if the probability were 1/2. We understand, on the other hand, why,
if, placing myself at the objective point of view, I observe a certain
number of coups, observation will give me about as many black coups as
red.

All players know this objective law; but it leads them into a remarkable
error, which has been often exposed, but into which they always fall
again. When the red has won, for instance, six times running, they bet
on the black, thinking they are playing a safe game; because, say they,
it is very rare that red wins seven times running.

In reality their probability of winning remains 1/2. Observation shows,
it is true, that series of seven consecutive reds are very rare, but
series of six reds followed by a black are just as rare.

They have noticed the rarity of the series of seven reds; if they have
not remarked the rarity of six reds and a black, it is only because such
series strike the attention less.

V. THE PROBABILITY OF CAUSES.--We now come to the problems of the
probability of causes, the most important from the point of view of
scientific applications. Two stars, for instance, are very close
together on the celestial sphere. Is this apparent contiguity a mere
effect of chance? Are these stars, although on almost the same visual
ray, situated at very different distances from the earth, and
consequently very far from one another? Or, perhaps, does the apparent
correspond to a real contiguity? This is a problem on the probability of
causes.

I recall first that at the outset of all problems of the probability of
effects that have hitherto occupied us, we have always had to make a
convention, more or less justified. And if in most cases the result was,
in a certain measure, independent of this convention, this was only
because of certain hypotheses which permitted us to reject _a priori_
discontinuous functions, for example, or certain absurd conventions.

We shall find something analogous when we deal with the probability of
causes. An effect may be produced by the cause _A_ or by the cause _B_.
The effect has just been observed. We ask the probability that it is due
to the cause _A_. This is an _a posteriori_ probability of cause. But I
could not calculate it, if a convention more or less justified did not
tell me _in advance_ what is the _a priori_ probability for the cause
_A_ to come into play; I mean the probability of this event for some one
who had not observed the effect.

The better to explain myself I go back to the example of the game of
écarté mentioned above. My adversary deals for the first time and he
turns up a king. What is the probability that he is a sharper? The
formulas ordinarily taught give 8/9, a result evidently rather
surprising. If we look at it closer, we see that the calculation is made
as if, _before sitting down at the table_, I had considered that there
was one chance in two that my adversary was not honest. An absurd
hypothesis, because in that case I should have certainly not played with
him, and this explains the absurdity of the conclusion.

The convention about the _a priori_ probability was unjustified, and
that is why the calculation of the _a posteriori_ probability led me to
an inadmissible result. We see the importance of this preliminary
convention. I shall even add that if none were made, the problem of the
_a posteriori_ probability would have no meaning. It must always be made
either explicitly or tacitly.

Pass to an example of a more scientific character. I wish to determine
an experimental law. This law, when I know it, can be represented by a
curve. I make a certain number of isolated observations; each of these
will be represented by a point. When I have obtained these different
points, I draw a curve between them, striving to pass as near to them as
possible and yet preserve for my curve a regular form, without angular
points, or inflections too accentuated, or brusque variation of the
radius of curvature. This curve will represent for me the probable law,
and I assume not only that it will tell me the values of the function
intermediate between those which have been observed, but also that it
will give me the observed values themselves more exactly than direct
observation. This is why I make it pass near the points, and not through
the points themselves.

Here is a problem in the probability of causes. The effects are the
measurements I have recorded; they depend on a combination of two
causes: the true law of the phenomenon and the errors of observation.
Knowing the effects, we have to seek the probability that the phenomenon
obeys this law or that, and that the observations have been affected by
this or that error. The most probable law then corresponds to the curve
traced, and the most probable error of an observation is represented by
the distance of the corresponding point from this curve.

But the problem would have no meaning if, before any observation, I had
not fashioned an _a priori_ idea of the probability of this or that law,
and of the chances of error to which I am exposed.

If my instruments are good (and that I knew before making the
observations), I shall not permit my curve to depart much from the
points which represent the rough measurements. If they are bad, I may go
a little further away from them in order to obtain a less sinuous curve;
I shall sacrifice more to regularity.

Why then is it that I seek to trace a curve without sinuosities? It is
because I consider _a priori_ a law represented by a continuous function
(or by a function whose derivatives of high order are small), as more
probable than a law not satisfying these conditions. Without this
belief, the problem of which we speak would have no meaning;
interpolation would be impossible; no law could be deduced from a finite
number of observations; science would not exist.

Fifty years ago physicists considered, other things being equal, a
simple law as more probable than a complicated law. They even invoked
this principle in favor of Mariotte's law as against the experiments of
Regnault. To-day they have repudiated this belief; and yet, how many
times are they compelled to act as though they still held it! However
that may be, what remains of this tendency is the belief in continuity,
and we have just seen that if this belief were to disappear in its turn,
experimental science would become impossible.

VI. THE THEORY OF ERRORS.--We are thus led to speak of the theory of
errors, which is directly connected with the problem of the probability
of causes. Here again we find _effects_, to wit, a certain number of
discordant observations, and we seek to divine the _causes_, which are,
on the one hand, the real value of the quantity to be measured; on the
other hand, the error made in each isolated observation. It is necessary
to calculate what is _a posteriori_ the probable magnitude of each
error, and consequently the probable value of the quantity to be
measured.

But as I have just explained, we should not know how to undertake this
calculation if we did not admit _a priori_, that is to say, before all
observation, a law of probability of errors. Is there a law of errors?

The law of errors admitted by all calculators is Gauss's law, which is
represented by a certain transcendental curve known under the name of
'the bell.'

But first it is proper to recall the classic distinction between
systematic and accidental errors. If we measure a length with too long a
meter, we shall always find too small a number, and it will be of no use
to measure several times; this is a systematic error. If we measure with
an accurate meter, we may, however, make a mistake; but we go wrong, now
too much, now too little, and when we take the mean of a great number of
measurements, the error will tend to grow small. These are accidental
errors.

It is evident from the first that systematic errors can not satisfy
Gauss's law; but do the accidental errors satisfy it? A great number of
demonstrations have been attempted; almost all are crude paralogisms.
Nevertheless, we may demonstrate Gauss's law by starting from the
following hypotheses: the error committed is the result of a great
number of partial and independent errors; each of the partial errors is
very little and besides, obeys any law of probability, provided that the
probability of a positive error is the same as that of an equal negative
error. It is evident that these conditions will be often but not always
fulfilled, and we may reserve the name of accidental for errors which
satisfy them.

We see that the method of least squares is not legitimate in every case;
in general the physicists are more distrustful of it than the
astronomers. This is, no doubt, because the latter, besides the
systematic errors to which they and the physicists are subject alike,
have to control with an extremely important source of error which is
wholly accidental; I mean atmospheric undulations. So it is very
curious to hear a physicist discuss with an astronomer about a method of
observation. The physicist, persuaded that one good measurement is worth
more than many bad ones, is before all concerned with eliminating by
dint of precautions the least systematic errors, and the astronomer says
to him: 'But thus you can observe only a small number of stars; the
accidental errors will not disappear.'

What should we conclude? Must we continue to use the method of least
squares? We must distinguish. We have eliminated all the systematic
errors we could suspect; we know well there are still others, but we can
not detect them; yet it is necessary to make up our mind and adopt a
definitive value which will be regarded as the probable value; and for
that it is evident the best thing to do is to apply Gauss's method. We
have only applied a practical rule referring to subjective probability.
There is nothing more to be said.

But we wish to go farther and affirm that not only is the probable value
so much, but that the probable error in the result is so much. _This is
absolutely illegitimate_; it would be true only if we were sure that all
the systematic errors were eliminated, and of that we know absolutely
nothing. We have two series of observations; by applying the rule of
least squares, we find that the probable error in the first series is
twice as small as in the second. The second series may, however, be
better than the first, because the first perhaps is affected by a large
systematic error. All we can say is that the first series is _probably_
better than the second, since its accidental error is smaller, and we
have no reason to affirm that the systematic error is greater for one of
the series than for the other, our ignorance on this point being
absolute.

VII. CONCLUSIONS.--In the lines which precede, I have set many problems
without solving any of them. Yet I do not regret having written them,
because they will perhaps invite the reader to reflect on these delicate
questions.

However that may be, there are certain points which seem well
established. To undertake any calculation of probability, and even for
that calculation to have any meaning, it is necessary to admit, as
point of departure, a hypothesis or convention which has always
something arbitrary about it. In the choice of this convention, we can
be guided only by the principle of sufficient reason. Unfortunately this
principle is very vague and very elastic, and in the cursory examination
we have just made, we have seen it take many different forms. The form
under which we have met it most often is the belief in continuity, a
belief which it would be difficult to justify by apodeictic reasoning,
but without which all science would be impossible. Finally the problems
to which the calculus of probabilities may be applied with profit are
those in which the result is independent of the hypothesis made at the
outset, provided only that this hypothesis satisfies the condition of
continuity.



CHAPTER XII

OPTICS AND ELECTRICITY


FRESNEL'S THEORY.--The best example[5] that can be chosen of physics in
the making is the theory of light and its relations to the theory of
electricity. Thanks to Fresnel, optics is the best developed part of
physics; the so-called wave-theory forms a whole truly satisfying to the
mind. We must not, however, ask of it what it can not give us.

  [5] This chapter is a partial reproduction of the prefaces of two
      of my works: _Théorie mathématique de la lumière_ (Paris, Naud,
      1889), and _Électricité et optique_ (Paris, Naud, 1901).

The object of mathematical theories is not to reveal to us the true
nature of things; this would be an unreasonable pretension. Their sole
aim is to coordinate the physical laws which experiment reveals to us,
but which, without the help of mathematics, we should not be able even
to state.

It matters little whether the ether really exists; that is the affair of
metaphysicians. The essential thing for us is that everything happens as
if it existed, and that this hypothesis is convenient for the
explanation of phenomena. After all, have we any other reason to believe
in the existence of material objects? That, too, is only a convenient
hypothesis; only this will never cease to be so, whereas, no doubt, some
day the ether will be thrown aside as useless. But even at that day, the
laws of optics and the equations which translate them analytically will
remain true, at least as a first approximation. It will always be
useful, then, to study a doctrine that unites all these equations.

The undulatory theory rests on a molecular hypothesis. For those who
think they have thus discovered the cause under the law, this is an
advantage. For the others it is a reason for distrust. But this distrust
seems to me as little justified as the illusion of the former.

These hypotheses play only a secondary part. They might be sacrificed.
They usually are not, because then the explanation would lose in
clearness; but that is the only reason.

In fact, if we looked closer we should see that only two things are
borrowed from the molecular hypotheses: the principle of the
conservation of energy and the linear form of the equations, which is
the general law of small movements, as of all small variations.

This explains why most of Fresnel's conclusions remain unchanged when we
adopt the electromagnetic theory of light.

MAXWELL'S THEORY.--Maxwell, we know, connected by a close bond two parts
of physics until then entirely foreign to one another, optics and
electricity. By blending thus in a vaster whole, in a higher harmony,
the optics of Fresnel has not ceased to be alive. Its various parts
subsist, and their mutual relations are still the same. Only the
language we used to express them has changed; and, on the other hand,
Maxwell has revealed to us other relations, before unsuspected, between
the different parts of optics and the domain of electricity.

When a French reader first opens Maxwell's book, a feeling of uneasiness
and often even of mistrust mingles at first with his admiration. Only
after a prolonged acquaintance and at the cost of many efforts does this
feeling disappear. There are even some eminent minds that never lose it.

Why are the English scientist's ideas with such difficulty acclimatized
among us? It is, no doubt, because the education received by the
majority of enlightened Frenchmen predisposes them to appreciate
precision and logic above every other quality.

The old theories of mathematical physics gave us in this respect
complete satisfaction. All our masters, from Laplace to Cauchy, have
proceeded in the same way. Starting from clearly stated hypotheses, they
deduced all their consequences with mathematical rigor, and then
compared them with experiment. It seemed their aim to give every branch
of physics the same precision as celestial mechanics.

A mind accustomed to admire such models is hard to suit with a theory.
Not only will it not tolerate the least appearance of contradiction, but
it will demand that the various parts be logically connected with one
another, and that the number of distinct hypotheses be reduced to
minimum.

This is not all; it will have still other demands, which seem to me
less reasonable. Behind the matter which our senses can reach, and which
experiment tells us of, it will desire to see another, and in its eyes
the only real, matter, which will have only purely geometric properties,
and whose atoms will be nothing but mathematical points, subject to the
laws of dynamics alone. And yet these atoms, invisible and without
color, it will seek by an unconscious contradiction to represent to
itself and consequently to identify as closely as possible with common
matter.

Then only will it be fully satisfied and imagine that it has penetrated
the secret of the universe. If this satisfaction is deceitful, it is
none the less difficult to renounce.

Thus, on opening Maxwell, a Frenchman expects to find a theoretical
whole as logical and precise as the physical optics based on the
hypothesis of the ether; he thus prepares for himself a disappointment
which I should like to spare the reader by informing him immediately of
what he must look for in Maxwell, and what he can not find there.

Maxwell does not give a mechanical explanation of electricity and
magnetism; he confines himself to demonstrating that such an explanation
is possible.

He shows also that optical phenomena are only a special case of
electromagnetic phenomena. From every theory of electricity, one can
therefore deduce immediately a theory of light.

The converse unfortunately is not true; from a complete explanation of
light, it is not always easy to derive a complete explanation of
electric phenomena. This is not easy, in particular, if we wish to start
from Fresnel's theory. Doubtless it would not be impossible; but
nevertheless we must ask whether we are not going to be forced to
renounce admirable results that we thought definitely acquired. That
seems a step backward; and many good minds are not willing to submit to
it.

When the reader shall have consented to limit his hopes, he will still
encounter other difficulties. The English scientist does not try to
construct a single edifice, final and well ordered; he seems rather to
erect a great number of provisional and independent constructions,
between which communication is difficult and sometimes impossible.

Take as example the chapter in which he explains electrostatic
attractions by pressures and tensions in the dielectric medium. This
chapter might be omitted without making thereby the rest of the book
less clear or complete; and, on the other hand, it contains a theory
complete in itself which one could understand without having read a
single line that precedes or follows. But it is not only independent of
the rest of the work; it is difficult to reconcile with the fundamental
ideas of the book. Maxwell does not even attempt this reconciliation; he
merely says: "I have not been able to make the next step, namely, to
account by mechanical considerations for these stresses in the
dielectric."

This example will suffice to make my thought understood; I could cite
many others. Thus who would suspect, in reading the pages devoted to
magnetic rotary polarization, that there is an identity between optical
and magnetic phenomena?

One must not then flatter himself that he can avoid all contradiction;
to that it is necessary to be resigned. In fact, two contradictory
theories, provided one does not mingle them, and if one does not seek in
them the basis of things, may both be useful instruments of research;
and perhaps the reading of Maxwell would be less suggestive if he had
not opened up to us so many new and divergent paths.

The fundamental idea, however, is thus a little obscured. So far is this
the case that in the majority of popularized versions it is the only
point completely left aside.

I feel, then, that the better to make its importance stand out, I ought
to explain in what this fundamental idea consists. But for that a short
digression is necessary.

THE MECHANICAL EXPLANATION OF PHYSICAL PHENOMENA.--There is in every
physical phenomenon a certain number of parameters which experiment
reaches directly and allows us to measure. I shall call these the
parameters _q_.

Observation then teaches us the laws of the variations of these
parameters; and these laws can generally be put in the form of
differential equations, which connect the parameters _q_ with the time.

What is it necessary to do to give a mechanical interpretation of such a
phenomenon?

One will try to explain it either by the motions of ordinary matter, or
by those of one or more hypothetical fluids.

These fluids will be considered as formed of a very great number of
isolated molecules _m_.

When shall we say, then, that we have a complete mechanical explanation
of the phenomenon? It will be, on the one hand, when we know the
differential equations satisfied by the coordinates of these
hypothetical molecules _m_, equations which, moreover, must conform to
the principles of dynamics; and, on the other hand, when we know the
relations that define the coordinates of the molecules _m_ as functions
of the parameters _q_ accessible to experiment.

These equations, as I have said, must conform to the principles of
dynamics, and, in particular, to the principle of the conservation of
energy and the principle of least action.

The first of these two principles teaches us that the total energy is
constant and that this energy is divided into two parts:

1º The kinetic energy, or _vis viva_, which depends on the masses of the
hypothetical molecules _m_, and their velocities, and which I shall call
_T_.

2º The potential energy, which depends only on the coordinates of these
molecules and which I shall call _U_. It is the _sum_ of the two
energies _T_ and _U_ which is constant.

What now does the principle of least action tell us? It tells us that to
pass from the initial position occupied at the instant t_{0} to the
final position occupied at the instant t_{1}, the system must take such
a path that, in the interval of time that elapses between the two
instants t_{0} and t_{1}, the average value of 'the action' (that is to
say, of the _difference_ between the two energies _T_ and _U_) shall be
as small as possible.

If the two functions _T_ and _U_ are known, this principle suffices to
determine the equations of motion.

Among all the possible ways of passing from one position to another,
there is evidently one for which the average value of the action is less
than for any other. There is, moreover, only one; and it results from
this that the principle of least action suffices to determine the path
followed and consequently the equations of motion.

Thus we obtain what are called the equations of Lagrange.

In these equations, the independent variables are the coordinates of the
hypothetical molecules _m_; but I now suppose that one takes as
variables the parameters _q_ directly accessible to experiment.

The two parts of the energy must then be expressed as functions of the
parameters _q_ and of their derivatives. They will evidently appear
under this form to the experimenter. The latter will naturally try to
define the potential and the kinetic energy by the aid of quantities
that he can directly observe.[6]

  [6]  We add that _U_ will depend only on the parameters _q_, that _T_
       will depend on the parameters _q_ and their derivatives with
       respect to the time and will be a homogeneous polynomial of the
       second degree with respect to these derivatives.

That granted, the system will always go from one position to another by
a path such that the average action shall be a minimum.

It matters little that _T_ and _U_ are now expressed by the aid of the
parameters _q_ and their derivatives; it matters little that it is also
by means of these parameters that we define the initial and final
positions; the principle of least action remains always true.

Now here again, of all the paths that lead from one position to another,
there is one for which the average action is a minimum, and there is
only one. The principle of least action suffices, then, to determine the
differential equations which define the variations of the parameters
_q_.

The equations thus obtained are another form of the equations of
Lagrange.

To form these equations we need to know neither the relations that
connect the parameters _q_ with the coordinates of the hypothetical
molecules, nor the masses of these molecules, nor the expression of _U_
as a function of the coordinates of these molecules.

All we need to know is the expression of _U_ as a function of the
parameters, and that of _T_ as a function of the parameters _q_ and
their derivatives, that is, the expressions of the kinetic and of the
potential energy as functions of the experimental data.

Then we shall have one of two things: either for a suitable choice of
the functions _T_ and _U_, the equations of Lagrange, constructed as we
have just said, will be identical with the differential equations
deduced from experiments; or else there will exist no functions _T_ and
_U_, for which this agreement takes place. In the latter case it is
clear that no mechanical explanation is possible.

The _necessary_ condition for a mechanical explanation to be possible is
therefore that we can choose the functions _T_ and _U_ in such a way as
to satisfy the principle of least action, which involves that of the
conservation of energy.

This condition, moreover, is _sufficient_. Suppose, in fact, that we
have found a function _U_ of the parameters _q_, which represents one of
the parts of the energy; that another part of the energy, which we shall
represent by _T_, is a function of the parameters _q_ and their
derivatives, and that it is a homogeneous polynomial of the second
degree with respect to these derivatives; and finally that the equations
of Lagrange, formed by means of these two functions, _T_ and _U_,
conform to the data of the experiment.

What is necessary in order to deduce from this a mechanical explanation?
It is necessary that _U_ can be regarded as the potential energy of a
system and _T_ as the _vis viva_ of the same system.

There is no difficulty as to _U_, but can _T_ be regarded as the _vis
viva_ of a material system?

It is easy to show that this is always possible, and even in an infinity
of ways. I will confine myself to referring for more details to the
preface of my work, 'Électricité et optique.'

Thus if the principle of least action can not be satisfied, no
mechanical explanation is possible; if it can be satisfied, there is not
only one, but an infinity, whence it follows that as soon as there is
one there is an infinity of others.

One more observation.

Among the quantities that experiment gives us directly, we shall regard
some as functions of the coordinates of our hypothetical molecules;
these are our parameters _q_. We shall look upon the others as dependent
not only on the coordinates, but on the velocities, or, what comes to
the same thing, on the derivatives of the parameters _q_, or as
combinations of these parameters and their derivatives.

And then a question presents itself: among all these quantities measured
experimentally, which shall we choose to represent the parameters _q_?
Which shall we prefer to regard as the derivatives of these parameters?
This choice remains arbitrary to a very large extent; but, for a
mechanical explanation to be possible, it suffices if we can make the
choice in such a way as to accord with the principle of least action.

And then Maxwell asked himself whether he could make this choice and
that of the two energies _T_ and _U_, in such a way that the electrical
phenomena would satisfy this principle. Experiment shows us that the
energy of an electromagnetic field is decomposed into two parts, the
electrostatic energy and the electrodynamic energy. Maxwell observed
that if we regard the first as representing the potential energy _U_,
the second as representing the kinetic energy _T_; if, moreover, the
electrostatic charges of the conductors are considered as parameters _q_
and the intensities of the currents as the derivatives of other
parameters _q_; under these conditions, I say, Maxwell observed that the
electric phenomena satisfy the principle of least action. Thenceforth he
was certain of the possibility of a mechanical explanation.

If he had explained this idea at the beginning of his book instead of
relegating it to an obscure part of the second volume, it would not have
escaped the majority of readers.

If, then, a phenomenon admits of a complete mechanical explanation, it
will admit of an infinity of others, that will render an account equally
well of all the particulars revealed by experiment.

And this is confirmed by the history of every branch of physics; in
optics, for instance, Fresnel believed vibration to be perpendicular to
the plane of polarization; Neumann regarded it as parallel to this
plane. An 'experimentum crucis' has long been sought which would enable
us to decide between these two theories, but it has not been found.

In the same way, without leaving the domain of electricity, we may
ascertain that the theory of two fluids and that of the single fluid
both account in a fashion equally satisfactory for all the observed laws
of electrostatics.

All these facts are easily explicable, thanks to the properties of the
equations of Lagrange which I have just recalled.

It is easy now to comprehend what is Maxwell's fundamental idea.

To demonstrate the possibility of a mechanical explanation of
electricity, we need not preoccupy ourselves with finding this
explanation itself; it suffices us to know the expression of the two
functions _T_ and _U_, which are the two parts of energy, to form with
these two functions the equations of Lagrange and then to compare these
equations with the experimental laws.

Among all these possible explanations, how make a choice for which the
aid of experiment fails us? A day will come perhaps when physicists will
not interest themselves in these questions, inaccessible to positive
methods, and will abandon them to the metaphysicians. This day has not
yet arrived; man does not resign himself so easily to be forever
ignorant of the foundation of things.

Our choice can therefore be further guided only by considerations where
the part of personal appreciation is very great; there are, however,
solutions that all the world will reject because of their whimsicality,
and others that all the world will prefer because of their simplicity.

In what concerns electricity and magnetism, Maxwell abstains from making
any choice. It is not that he systematically disdains all that is
unattainable by positive methods; the time he has devoted to the kinetic
theory of gases sufficiently proves that. I will add that if, in his
great work, he develops no complete explanation, he had previously
attempted to give one in an article in the _Philosophical Magazine_. The
strangeness and the complexity of the hypotheses he had been obliged to
make had led him afterwards to give this up.

The same spirit is found throughout the whole work. What is essential,
that is to say what must remain common to all theories, is made
prominent; all that would only be suitable to a particular theory is
nearly always passed over in silence. Thus the reader finds himself in
the presence of a form almost devoid of matter, which he is at first
tempted to take for a fugitive shadow not to be grasped. But the efforts
to which he is thus condemned force him to think and he ends by
comprehending what was often rather artificial in the theoretic
constructs he had previously only wondered at.



CHAPTER XIII

ELECTRODYNAMICS


The history of electrodynamics is particularly instructive from our
point of view.

Ampère entitled his immortal work, 'Théorie des phénomènes
électrodynamiques, _uniquement_ fondée sur l'expérience.' He therefore
imagined that he had made _no_ hypothesis, but he had made them, as we
shall soon see; only he made them without being conscious of it.

His successors, on the other hand, perceived them, since their attention
was attracted by the weak points in Ampère's solution. They made new
hypotheses, of which this time they were fully conscious; but how many
times it was necessary to change them before arriving at the classic
system of to-day which is perhaps not yet final; this we shall see.

I. AMPERE'S THEORY.--When Ampère studied experimentally the mutual
actions of currents, he operated and he only could operate with closed
currents.

It was not that he denied the possibility of open currents. If two
conductors are charged with positive and negative electricity and
brought into communication by a wire, a current is established going
from one to the other, which continues until the two potentials are
equal. According to the ideas of Ampère's time this was an open current;
the current was known to go from the first conductor to the second, it
was not seen to return from the second to the first.

So Ampère considered as open currents of this nature, for example, the
currents of discharge of condensers; but he could not make them the
objects of his experiments because their duration is too short.

Another sort of open current may also be imagined. I suppose two
conductors, _A_ and _B_, connected by a wire _AMB_. Small conducting
masses in motion first come in contact with the conductor _B_, take
from it an electric charge, leave contact with _B_ and move along the
path _BNA_, and, transporting with them their charge, come into contact
with _A_ and give to it their charge, which returns then to _B_ along
the wire _AMB_.

Now there we have in a sense a closed circuit, since the electricity
describes the closed circuit _BNAMB_; but the two parts of this current
are very different. In the wire _AMB_, the electricity is displaced
through a fixed conductor, like a voltaic current, overcoming an ohmic
resistance and developing heat; we say that it is displaced by
conduction. In the part _BNA_, the electricity is carried by a moving
conductor; it is said to be displaced by convection.

If then the current of convection is considered as altogether analogous
to the current of conduction, the circuit _BNAMB_ is closed; if, on the
contrary, the convection current is not 'a true current' and, for
example, does not act on the magnet, there remains only the conduction
current _AMB_, which is open.

For example, if we connect by a wire the two poles of a Holtz machine,
the charged rotating disc transfers the electricity by convection from
one pole to the other, and it returns to the first pole by conduction
through the wire.

But currents of this sort are very difficult to produce with appreciable
intensity. With the means at Ampère's disposal, we may say that this was
impossible.

To sum up, Ampère could conceive of the existence of two kinds of open
currents, but he could operate on neither because they were not strong
enough or because their duration was too short.

Experiment therefore could only show him the action of a closed current
on a closed current, or, more accurately, the action of a closed current
on a portion of a current, because a current can be made to describe a
closed circuit composed of a moving part and a fixed part. It is
possible then to study the displacements of the moving part under the
action of another closed current.

On the other hand, Ampère had no means of studying the action of an open
current, either on a closed current or another open current.

1. _The Case of Closed Currents._--In the case of the mutual action of
two closed currents, experiment revealed to Ampère remarkably simple
laws.

I recall rapidly here those which will be useful to us in the sequel:

1º _If the intensity of the currents is kept constant_, and if the two
circuits, after having undergone any deformations and displacements
whatsoever, return finally to their initial positions, the total work of
the electrodynamic actions will be null.

In other words, there is an _electrodynamic potential_ of the two
circuits, proportional to the product of the intensities, and depending
on the form and relative position of the circuits; the work of the
electrodynamic actions is equal to the variation of this potential.

2º The action of a closed solenoid is null.

3º The action of a circuit _C_ on another voltaic circuit _C'_ depends
only on the 'magnetic field' developed by this circuit. At each point in
space we can in fact define in magnitude and direction a certain force
called _magnetic force_, which enjoys the following properties:

(_a_) The force exercised by _C_ on a magnetic pole is applied to that
pole and is equal to the magnetic force multiplied by the magnetic mass
of that pole;

(_b_) A very short magnetic needle tends to take the direction of the
magnetic force, and the couple to which it tends to reduce is
proportional to the magnetic force, the magnetic moment of the needle
and the sine of the dip of the needle;

(_c_) If the circuit _C_ is displaced, the work of the electrodynamic
action exercised by _C_ on _C'_ will be equal to the increment of the
'flow of magnetic force' which passes through the circuit.

2. _Action of a Closed Current on a Portion of Current._--Ampère not
having been able to produce an open current, properly so called, had
only one way of studying the action of a closed current on a portion of
current.

This was by operating on a circuit _C_ composed of two parts, the one
fixed, the other movable. The movable part was, for instance, a movable
wire [alpha][beta] whose extremities [alpha] and [beta] could slide
along a fixed wire. In one of the positions of the movable wire, the end
[alpha] rested on the _A_ of the fixed wire and the extremity [beta] on
the point _B_ of the fixed wire. The current circulated from [alpha] to
[beta], that is to say, from _A_ to _B_ along the movable wire, and then
it returned from _B_ to _A_ along the fixed wire. _This current was
therefore closed._

In a second position, the movable wire having slipped, the extremity
[alpha] rested on another point _A'_ of the fixed wire, and the
extremity [beta] on another point _B'_ of the fixed wire. The current
circulated then from [alpha] to [beta], that is to say from _A'_ to _B'_
along the movable wire, and it afterwards returned from _B'_ to _B_,
then from _B_ to _A_, then finally from _A_ to _A'_, always following
the fixed wire. The current was therefore also closed.

If a like current is subjected to the action of a closed current _C_,
the movable part will be displaced just as if it were acted upon by a
force. Ampère _assumes_ that the apparent force to which this movable
part _AB_ seems thus subjected, representing the action of the _C_ on
the portion [alpha][beta] of the current, is the same as if
[alpha][beta] were traversed by an open current, stopping at [alpha] and
[beta], in place of being traversed by a closed current which after
arriving at [beta] returns to [alpha] through the fixed part of the
circuit.

This hypothesis seems natural enough, and Ampère made it unconsciously;
nevertheless _it is not necessary_, since we shall see further on that
Helmholtz rejected it. However that may be, it permitted Ampère, though
he had never been able to produce an open current, to enunciate the laws
of the action of a closed current on an open current, or even on an
element of current.

The laws are simple:

1º The force which acts on an element of current is applied to this
element; it is normal to the element and to the magnetic force, and
proportional to the component of this magnetic force which is normal to
the element.

2º The action of a closed solenoid on an element of current is null.

But the electrodynamic potential has disappeared, that is to say that,
when a closed current and an open current, whose intensities have been
maintained constant, return to their initial positions, the total work
is not null.

3. _Continuous Rotations._--Among electrodynamic experiments, the most
remarkable are those in which continuous rotations are produced and
which are sometimes called _unipolar induction_ experiments. A magnet
may turn about its axis; a current passes first through a fixed wire,
enters the magnet by the pole _N_, for example, passes through half the
magnet, emerges by a sliding contact and reenters the fixed wire.

The magnet then begins to rotate continuously without being able ever to
attain equilibrium; this is Faraday's experiment.

How is it possible? If it were a question of two circuits of invariable
form, the one _C_ fixed, the other _C'_ movable about an axis, this
latter could never take on continuous rotation; in fact there is an
electrodynamic potential; there must therefore be necessarily a position
of equilibrium when this potential is a maximum.

Continuous rotations are therefore possible only when the circuit _C'_
is composed of two parts: one fixed, the other movable about an axis, as
is the case in Faraday's experiment. Here again it is convenient to draw
a distinction. The passage from the fixed to the movable part, or
inversely, may take place either by simple contact (the same point of
the movable part remaining constantly in contact with the same point of
the fixed part), or by a sliding contact (the same point of the movable
part coming successively in contact with diverse points of the fixed
part).

It is only in the second case that there can be continuous rotation.
This is what then happens: The system tends to take a position of
equilibrium; but, when at the point of reaching that position, the
sliding contact puts the movable part in communication with a new point
of the fixed part; it changes the connections, it changes therefore the
conditions of equilibrium, so that the position of equilibrium fleeing,
so to say, before the system which seeks to attain it, rotation may take
place indefinitely.

Ampère assumes that the action of the circuit on the movable part of
_C'_ is the same as if the fixed part of _C'_ did not exist, and
therefore as if the current passing through the movable part were open.

He concludes therefore that the action of a closed on an open current,
or inversely that of an open current on a closed current, may give rise
to a continuous rotation.

But this conclusion depends on the hypothesis I have enunciated and
which, as I said above, is not admitted by Helmholtz.

4. _Mutual Action of Two Open Currents._--In what concerns the mutual
actions of two open currents, and in particular that of two elements of
current, all experiment breaks down. Ampère has recourse to hypothesis.
He supposes:

1º That the mutual action of two elements reduces to a force acting
along their join;

2º That the action of two closed currents is the resultant of the mutual
actions of their diverse elements, which are besides the same as if
these elements were isolated.

What is remarkable is that here again Ampère makes these hypotheses
unconsciously.

However that may be, these two hypotheses, together with the experiments
on closed currents, suffice to determine completely the law of the
mutual action of two elements. But then most of the simple laws we have
met in the case of closed currents are no longer true.

In the first place, there is no electrodynamic potential; nor was there
any, as we have seen, in the case of a closed current acting on an open
current.

Next there is, properly speaking, no magnetic force.

And, in fact, we have given above three different definitions of this
force:

1º By the action on a magnetic pole;

2º By the director couple which orientates the magnetic needle;

3º By the action on an element of current.

But in the case which now occupies us, not only these three definitions
are no longer in harmony, but each has lost its meaning, and in fact:

1º A magnetic pole is no longer acted upon simply by a single force
applied to this pole. We have seen in fact that the force due to the
action of an element of current on a pole is not applied to the pole,
but to the element; it may moreover be replaced by a force applied to
the pole and by a couple;

2º The couple which acts on the magnetic needle is no longer a simple
director couple, for its moment with respect to the axis of the needle
is not null. It breaks up into a director couple, properly so called,
and a supplementary couple which tends to produce the continuous
rotation of which we have above spoken;

3º Finally the force acting on an element of current is not normal to
this element.

In other words, _the unity of the magnetic force has disappeared_.

Let us see in what this unity consists. Two systems which exercise the
same action on a magnetic pole will exert also the same action on an
indefinitely small magnetic needle, or on an element of current placed
at the same point of space as this pole.

Well, this is true if these two systems contain only closed currents;
this would no longer be true if these two systems contained open
currents.

It suffices to remark, for instance, that, if a magnetic pole is placed
at _A_ and an element at _B_, the direction of the element being along
the prolongation of the sect _AB_, this element which will exercise no
action on this pole will, on the other hand, exercise an action either
on a magnetic needle placed at the point _A_, or on an element of
current placed at the point _A_.

5. _Induction._--We know that the discovery of electrodynamic induction
soon followed the immortal work of Ampère.

As long as it is only a question of closed currents there is no
difficulty, and Helmholtz has even remarked that the principle of the
conservation of energy is sufficient for deducing the laws of induction
from the electrodynamic laws of Ampère. But always on one condition, as
Bertrand has well shown; that we make besides a certain number of
hypotheses.

The same principle again permits this deduction in the case of open
currents, although of course we can not submit the result to the test of
experiment, since we can not produce such currents.

If we try to apply this mode of analysis to Ampère's theory of open
currents, we reach results calculated to surprise us.

In the first place, induction can not be deduced from the variation of
the magnetic field by the formula well known to savants and practicians,
and, in fact, as we have said, properly speaking there is no longer a
magnetic field.

But, further, if a circuit _C_ is subjected to the induction of a
variable voltaic system _S_, if this system _S_ be displaced and
deformed in any way whatever, so that the intensity of the currents of
this system varies according to any law whatever, but that after these
variations the system finally returns to its initial situation, it seems
natural to suppose that the _mean_ electromotive force induced in the
circuit _C_ is null.

This is true if the circuit _C_ is closed and if the system _S_ contains
only closed currents. This would no longer be true, if one accepts the
theory of Ampère, if there were open currents. So that not only
induction will no longer be the variation of the flow of magnetic force,
in any of the usual senses of the word, but it can not be represented by
the variation of anything whatever.

II. THEORY OF HELMHOLTZ.--I have dwelt upon the consequences of Ampère's
theory, and of his method of explaining open currents.

It is difficult to overlook the paradoxical and artificial character of
the propositions to which we are thus led. One can not help thinking
'that can not be so.'

We understand therefore why Helmholtz was led to seek something else.

Helmholtz rejects Ampère's fundamental hypothesis, to wit, that the
mutual action of two elements of current reduces to a force along their
join. He assumes that an element of current is not subjected to a single
force, but to a force and a couple. It is just this which gave rise to
the celebrated polemic between Bertrand and Helmholtz.

Helmholtz replaces Ampère's hypothesis by the following: two elements
always admit of an electrodynamic potential depending solely on their
position and orientation; and the work of the forces that they exercise,
one on the other, is equal to the variation of this potential. Thus
Helmholtz can no more do without hypothesis than Ampère; but at least he
does not make one without explicitly announcing it.

In the case of closed currents, which are alone accessible to
experiment, the two theories agree.

In all other cases they differ.

In the first place, contrary to what Ampère supposed, the force which
seems to act on the movable portion of a closed current is not the same
as would act upon this movable portion if it were isolated and
constituted an open current.

Let us return to the circuit _C'_, of which we spoke above, and which
was formed of a movable wire [alpha][beta] sliding on a fixed wire. In
the only experiment that can be made, the movable portion [alpha][beta]
is not isolated, but is part of a closed circuit. When it passes from
_AB_ to _A'B'_, the total electrodynamic potential varies for two
reasons:

1º It undergoes a first increase because the potential of _A'B'_ with
respect to the circuit _C_ is not the same as that of _AB_;

2º It takes a second increment because it must be increased by the
potentials of the elements _AA'_, _BB'_ with respect to _C_.

It is this _double_ increment which represents the work of the force to
which the portion _AB_ seems subjected.

If, on the contrary, [alpha][beta] were isolated, the potential would
undergo only the first increase, and this first increment alone would
measure the work of the force which acts on _AB_.

In the second place, there could be no continuous rotation without
sliding contact, and, in fact, that, as we have seen _à propos_ of
closed currents, is an immediate consequence of the existence of an
electrodynamic potential.

In Faraday's experiment, if the magnet is fixed and if the part of the
current exterior to the magnet runs along a movable wire, that movable
part may undergo a continuous rotation. But this does not mean to say
that if the contacts of the wire with the magnet were suppressed, and an
_open_ current were to run along the wire, the wire would still take a
movement of continuous rotation.

I have just said in fact that an _isolated_ element is not acted upon in
the same way as a movable element making part of a closed circuit.

Another difference: The action of a closed solenoid on a closed current
is null according to experiment and according to the two theories. Its
action on an open current would be null according to Ampère; it would
not be null according to Helmholtz. From this follows an important
consequence. We have given above three definitions of magnetic force.
The third has no meaning here since an element of current is no longer
acted upon by a single force. No more has the first any meaning. What,
in fact, is a magnetic pole? It is the extremity of an indefinite linear
magnet. This magnet may be replaced by an indefinite solenoid. For the
definition of magnetic force to have any meaning, it would be necessary
that the action exercised by an open current on an indefinite solenoid
should depend only on the position of the extremity of this solenoid,
that is to say, that the action on a closed solenoid should be null. Now
we have just seen that such is not the case.

On the other hand, nothing prevents our adopting the second definition,
which is founded on the measurement of the director couple which tends
to orientate the magnetic needle.

But if it is adopted, neither the effects of induction nor the
electrodynamic effects will depend solely on the distribution of the
lines of force in this magnetic field.

III. DIFFICULTIES RAISED BY THESE THEORIES.--The theory of Helmholtz is
in advance of that of Ampère; it is necessary, however, that all the
difficulties should be smoothed away. In the one as in the other, the
phrase 'magnetic field' has no meaning, or, if we give it one, by a more
or less artificial convention, the ordinary laws so familiar to all
electricians no longer apply; thus the electromotive force induced in a
wire is no longer measured by the number of lines of force met by this
wire.

And our repugnance does not come alone from the difficulty of renouncing
inveterate habits of language and of thought. There is something more.
If we do not believe in action at a distance, electrodynamic phenomena
must be explained by a modification of the medium. It is precisely this
modification that we call 'magnetic field.' And then the electrodynamic
effects must depend only on this field.

All these difficulties arise from the hypothesis of open currents.

IV. MAXWELL'S THEORY.--Such were the difficulties raised by the dominant
theories when Maxwell appeared, who with a stroke of the pen made them
all vanish. To his mind, in fact, all currents are closed currents.
Maxwell assumes that if in a dielectric the electric field happens to
vary, this dielectric becomes the seat of a particular phenomenon,
acting on the galvanometer like a current, and which he calls _current
of displacement_.

If then two conductors bearing contrary charges are put in communication
by a wire, in this wire during the discharge there is an open current of
conduction; but there are produced at the same time in the surrounding
dielectric, currents of displacement which close this current of
conduction.

We know that Maxwell's theory leads to the explanation of optical
phenomena, which would be due to extremely rapid electrical
oscillations.

At that epoch such a conception was only a bold hypothesis, which could
be supported by no experiment.

At the end of twenty years, Maxwell's ideas received the confirmation of
experiment. Hertz succeeded in producing systems of electric
oscillations which reproduce all the properties of light, and only
differ from it by the length of their wave; that is to say as violet
differs from red. In some measure he made the synthesis of light.

It might be said that Hertz has not demonstrated directly Maxwell's
fundamental idea, the action of the current of displacement on the
galvanometer. This is true in a sense. What he has shown in sum is that
electromagnetic induction is not propagated instantaneously as was
supposed; but with the speed of light.

But to suppose there is no current of displacement, and induction is
propagated with the speed of light; or to suppose that the currents of
displacement produce effects of induction, and that the induction is
propagated instantaneously, _comes to the same thing_.

This can not be seen at the first glance, but it is proved by an
analysis of which I must not think of giving even a summary here.

V. ROWLAND'S EXPERIMENT.--But as I have said above, there are two kinds
of open conduction currents. There are first the currents of discharge
of a condenser or of any conductor whatever.

There are also the cases in which electric discharges describe a closed
contour, being displaced by conduction in one part of the circuit and by
convection in the other part.

For open currents of the first sort, the question might be considered as
solved; they were closed by the currents of displacement.

For open currents of the second sort, the solution appeared still more
simple. It seemed that if the current were closed, it could only be by
the current of convection itself. For that it sufficed to assume that a
'convection current,' that is to say a charged conductor in motion,
could act on the galvanometer.

But experimental confirmation was lacking. It appeared difficult in fact
to obtain a sufficient intensity even by augmenting as much as possible
the charge and the velocity of the conductors. It was Rowland, an
extremely skillful experimenter, who first triumphed over these
difficulties. A disc received a strong electrostatic charge and a very
great speed of rotation. An astatic magnetic system placed beside the
disc underwent deviations.

The experiment was made twice by Rowland, once in Berlin, once in
Baltimore. It was afterwards repeated by Himstedt. These physicists even
announced that they had succeeded in making quantitative measurements.

In fact, for twenty years Rowland's law was admitted without objection
by all physicists. Besides everything seemed to confirm it. The spark
certainly does produce a magnetic effect. Now does it not seem probable
that the discharge by spark is due to particles taken from one of the
electrodes and transferred to the other electrode with their charge? Is
not the very spectrum of the spark, in which we recognize the lines of
the metal of the electrode, a proof of it? The spark would then be a
veritable current of convection.

On the other hand, it is also admitted that in an electrolyte the
electricity is carried by the ions in motion. The current in an
electrolyte would therefore be also a current of convection; now, it
acts on the magnetic needle.

The same for cathode rays. Crookes attributed these rays to a very
subtile matter charged with electricity and moving with a very great
velocity. He regarded them, in other words, as currents of convection.
Now these cathode rays are deviated by the magnet. In virtue of the
principle of action and reaction, they should in turn deviate the
magnetic needle. It is true that Hertz believed he had demonstrated that
the cathode rays do not carry electricity, and that they do not act on
the magnetic needle. But Hertz was mistaken. First of all, Perrin
succeeded in collecting the electricity carried by these rays,
electricity of which Hertz denied the existence; the German scientist
appears to have been deceived by effects due to the action of X-rays,
which were not yet discovered. Afterwards, and quite recently, the
action of the cathode rays on the magnetic needle has been put in
evidence.

Thus all these phenomena regarded as currents of convection, sparks,
electrolytic currents, cathode rays, act in the same manner on the
galvanometer and in conformity with Rowland's law.

VI. THEORY OF LORENTZ.--We soon went farther. According to the theory of
Lorentz, currents of conduction themselves would be true currents of
convection. Electricity would remain inseparably connected with certain
material particles called _electrons_. The circulation of these
electrons through bodies would produce voltaic currents. And what would
distinguish conductors from insulators would be that the one could be
traversed by these electrons while the others would arrest their
movements.

The theory of Lorentz is very attractive. It gives a very simple
explanation of certain phenomena which the earlier theories, even
Maxwell's in its primitive form, could not explain in a satisfactory
way; for example, the aberration of light, the partial carrying away of
luminous waves, magnetic polarization and the Zeeman effect.

Some objections still remained. The phenomena of an electric system
seemed to depend on the absolute velocity of translation of the center
of gravity of this system, which is contrary to the idea we have of the
relativity of space. Supported by M. Crémieu, M. Lippmann has presented
this objection in a striking form. Imagine two charged conductors with
the same velocity of translation; they are relatively at rest. However,
each of them being equivalent to a current of convection, they ought to
attract one another, and by measuring this attraction we could measure
their absolute velocity.

"No!" replied the partisans of Lorentz. "What we could measure in that
way is not their absolute velocity, but their relative velocity _with
respect to the ether_, so that the principle of relativity is safe."

Whatever there may be in these latter objections, the edifice of
electrodynamics, at least in its broad lines, seemed definitively
constructed. Everything was presented under the most satisfactory
aspect. The theories of Ampère and of Helmholtz, made for open currents
which no longer existed, seemed to have no longer anything but a purely
historic interest, and the inextricable complications to which these
theories led were almost forgotten.

This quiescence has been recently disturbed by the experiments of M.
Crémieu, which for a moment seemed to contradict the result previously
obtained by Rowland.

But fresh researches have not confirmed them, and the theory of Lorentz
has victoriously stood the test.

The history of these variations will be none the less instructive; it
will teach us to what pitfalls the scientist is exposed, and how he may
hope to escape them.


       *       *       *       *       *



THE VALUE OF SCIENCE



       *       *       *       *       *



TRANSLATOR'S INTRODUCTION


1. _Does the Scientist create Science?_--Professor Rados of Budapest in
his report to the Hungarian Academy of Science on the award to Poincaré
of the Bolyai prize of ten thousand crowns, speaking of him as
unquestionably the most powerful investigator in the domain of
mathematics and mathematical physics, characterized him as the intuitive
genius drawing the inspiration for his wide-reaching researches from the
exhaustless fountain of geometric and physical intuition, yet working
this inspiration out in detail with marvelous logical keenness. With his
brilliant creative genius was combined the capacity for sharp and
successful generalization, pushing far out the boundaries of thought in
the most widely different domains, so that his works must be ranked with
the greatest mathematical achievements of all time. "Finally," says
Rados, "permit me to make especial mention of his intensely interesting
book, 'The Value of Science,' in which he in a way has laid down the
scientist's creed." Now what is this creed?

Sense may act as stimulus, as suggestive, yet not to awaken a dormant
depiction, or to educe the conception of an archetypal form, but rather
to strike the hour for creation, to summon to work a sculptor capable of
smoothing a Venus of Milo out of the formless clay. Knowledge is not a
gift of bare experience, nor even made solely out of experience. The
creative activity of mind is in mathematics particularly clear. The
axioms of geometry are conventions, disguised definitions or unprovable
hypotheses precreated by auto-active animal and human minds. Bertrand
Russell says of projective geometry: "It takes nothing from experience,
and has, like arithmetic, a creature of the pure intellect for its
object. It deals with an object whose properties are logically deduced
from its definition, not empirically discovered from data." Then does
the scientist create science? This is a question Poincaré here dissects
with a master hand.

The physiologic-psychologic investigation of the space problem must
give the meaning of the words _geometric fact_, _geometric reality_.
Poincaré here subjects to the most successful analysis ever made the
tridimensionality of our space.

2. _The Mind Dispelling Optical Illusions._--Actual perception of
spatial properties is accompanied by movements corresponding to its
character. In the case of optical illusions, with the so-called false
perceptions eye-movements are closely related. But though the perceived
object and its environment remain constant, the sufficiently powerful
mind can, as we say, dispel these illusions, the perception itself being
creatively changed. Photo-graphs taken at intervals during the presence
of these optical illusions, during the change, perhaps gradual and
unconscious, in the perception, and after these illusions have, as the
phrase is, finally disappeared, show quite clearly that changes in
eye-movements corresponding to those internally created in perception
itself successively occur. What is called accuracy of movement is
created by what is called correctness of perception. The higher creation
in the perception is the determining cause of an improvement, a
precision in the motion. Thus we see correct perception in the
individual helping to make that cerebral organization and accurate motor
adjustment on which its possibility and permanence seem in so far to
depend. So-called correct perception is connected with a long-continued
process of perceptual education motived and initiated from within. How
this may take place is here illustrated at length by our author.

3. _Euclid not Necessary._--Geometry is a construction of the intellect,
in application not certain but convenient. As Schiller says, when we see
these facts as clearly as the development of metageometry has compelled
us to see them, we must surely confess that the Kantian account of space
is hopelessly and demonstrably antiquated. As Royce says in 'Kant's
Doctrine of the Basis of Mathematics,' "That very use of intuition which
Kant regarded as geometrically ideal, the modern geometer regards as
scientifically defective, because surreptitious. No mathematical
exactness without explicit proof from assumed principles--such is the
motto of the modern geometer. But suppose the reasoning of Euclid
purified of this comparatively surreptitious appeal to intuition.
Suppose that the principles of geometry are made quite explicit at the
outset of the treatise, as Pieri and Hilbert or Professor Halsted or Dr.
Veblen makes his principles explicit in his recent treatment of
geometry. Then, indeed, geometry becomes for the modern mathematician a
purely rational science. But very few students of the logic of
mathematics at the present time can see any warrant in the analysis of
geometrical truth for regarding just the Euclidean system of principles
as possessing any discoverable necessity." Yet the environmental and
perhaps hereditary premiums on Euclid still make even the scientist
think Euclid most convenient.

4. _Without Hypotheses, no Science._--Nobody ever observed an
equidistantial, but also nobody ever observed a straight line.
Emerson's Uriel

  "Gave his sentiment divine
  Against the being of a line.
  Line in Nature is not found."

Clearly not, being an eject from man's mind. What is called 'a knowledge
of facts' is usually merely a subjective realization that the old
hypotheses are still sufficiently elastic to serve in some domain; that
is, with a sufficiency of conscious or unconscious omissions and
doctorings and fudgings more or less wilful. In the present book we see
the very foundation rocks of science, the conservation of energy and the
indestructibility of matter, beating against the bars of their cages,
seemingly anxious to take wing away into the empyrean, to chase the once
divine parallel postulate broken loose from Euclid and Kant.

5. _What Outcome?_--What now is the definite, the permanent outcome?
What new islets raise their fronded palms in air within thought's
musical domain? Over what age-gray barriers rise the fragrant floods of
this new spring-tide, redolent of the wolf-haunted forest of
Transylvania, of far Erdély's plunging river, Maros the bitter, or broad
mother Volga at Kazan? What victory heralded the great rocket for which
young Lobachevski, the widow's son, was cast into prison? What severing
of age-old mental fetters symbolized young Bolyai's cutting-off with
his Damascus blade the spikes driven into his door-post, and strewing
over the sod the thirteen Austrian cavalry officers? This book by the
greatest mathematician of our time gives weightiest and most charming
answer.

  GEORGE BRUCE HALSTED.



INTRODUCTION


The search for truth should be the goal of our activities; it is the
sole end worthy of them. Doubtless we should first bend our efforts to
assuage human suffering, but why? Not to suffer is a negative ideal more
surely attained by the annihilation of the world. If we wish more and
more to free man from material cares, it is that he may be able to
employ the liberty obtained in the study and contemplation of truth.

But sometimes truth frightens us. And in fact we know that it is
sometimes deceptive, that it is a phantom never showing itself for a
moment except to ceaselessly flee, that it must be pursued further and
ever further without ever being attained. Yet to work one must stop, as
some Greek, Aristotle or another, has said. We also know how cruel the
truth often is, and we wonder whether illusion is not more consoling,
yea, even more bracing, for illusion it is which gives confidence. When
it shall have vanished, will hope remain and shall we have the courage
to achieve? Thus would not the horse harnessed to his treadmill refuse
to go, were his eyes not bandaged? And then to seek truth it is
necessary to be independent, wholly independent. If, on the contrary, we
wish to act, to be strong, we should be united. This is why many of us
fear truth; we consider it a cause of weakness. Yet truth should not be
feared, for it alone is beautiful.

When I speak here of truth, assuredly I refer first to scientific truth;
but I also mean moral truth, of which what we call justice is only one
aspect. It may seem that I am misusing words, that I combine thus under
the same name two things having nothing in common; that scientific
truth, which is demonstrated, can in no way be likened to moral truth,
which is felt. And yet I can not separate them, and whosoever loves the
one can not help loving the other. To find the one, as well as to find
the other, it is necessary to free the soul completely from prejudice
and from passion; it is necessary to attain absolute sincerity. These
two sorts of truth when discovered give the same joy; each when
perceived beams with the same splendor, so that we must see it or close
our eyes. Lastly, both attract us and flee from us; they are never
fixed: when we think to have reached them, we find that we have still to
advance, and he who pursues them is condemned never to know repose. It
must be added that those who fear the one will also fear the other; for
they are the ones who in everything are concerned above all with
consequences. In a word, I liken the two truths, because the same
reasons make us love them and because the same reasons make us fear
them.

If we ought not to fear moral truth, still less should we dread
scientific truth. In the first place it can not conflict with ethics.
Ethics and science have their own domains, which touch but do not
interpenetrate. The one shows us to what goal we should aspire, the
other, given the goal, teaches us how to attain it. So they can never
conflict since they can never meet. There can no more be immoral science
than there can be scientific morals.

But if science is feared, it is above all because it can not give us
happiness. Of course it can not. We may even ask whether the beast does
not suffer less than man. But can we regret that earthly paradise where
man brute-like was really immortal in knowing not that he must die? When
we have tasted the apple, no suffering can make us forget its savor. We
always come back to it. Could it be otherwise? As well ask if one who
has seen and is blind will not long for the light. Man, then, can not be
happy through science, but to-day he can much less be happy without it.

But if truth be the sole aim worth pursuing, may we hope to attain it?
It may well be doubted. Readers of my little book 'Science and
Hypothesis' already know what I think about the question. The truth we
are permitted to glimpse is not altogether what most men call by that
name. Does this mean that our most legitimate, most imperative
aspiration is at the same time the most vain? Or can we, despite all,
approach truth on some side? This it is which must be investigated.

In the first place, what instrument have we at our disposal for this
conquest? Is not human intelligence, more specifically the intelligence
of the scientist, susceptible of infinite variation? Volumes could be
written without exhausting this subject; I, in a few brief pages, have
only touched it lightly. That the geometer's mind is not like the
physicist's or the naturalist's, all the world would agree; but
mathematicians themselves do not resemble each other; some recognize
only implacable logic, others appeal to intuition and see in it the only
source of discovery. And this would be a reason for distrust. To minds
so unlike can the mathematical theorems themselves appear in the same
light? Truth which is not the same for all, is it truth? But looking at
things more closely, we see how these very different workers collaborate
in a common task which could not be achieved without their cooperation.
And that already reassures us.

Next must be examined the frames in which nature seems enclosed and
which are called time and space. In 'Science and Hypothesis' I have
already shown how relative their value is; it is not nature which
imposes them upon us, it is we who impose them upon nature because we
find them convenient. But I have spoken of scarcely more than space, and
particularly quantitative space, so to say, that is of the mathematical
relations whose aggregate constitutes geometry. I should have shown that
it is the same with time as with space and still the same with
'qualitative space'; in particular, I should have investigated why we
attribute three dimensions to space. I may be pardoned then for taking
up again these important questions.

Is mathematical analysis, then, whose principal object is the study of
these empty frames, only a vain play of the mind? It can give to the
physicist only a convenient language; is this not a mediocre service,
which, strictly speaking, could be done without; and even is it not to
be feared that this artificial language may be a veil interposed between
reality and the eye of the physicist? Far from it; without this language
most of the intimate analogies of things would have remained forever
unknown to us; and we should forever have been ignorant of the internal
harmony of the world, which is, we shall see, the only true objective
reality.

The best expression of this harmony is law. Law is one of the most
recent conquests of the human mind; there still are people who live in
the presence of a perpetual miracle and are not astonished at it. On the
contrary, we it is who should be astonished at nature's regularity. Men
demand of their gods to prove their existence by miracles; but the
eternal marvel is that there are not miracles without cease. The world
is divine because it is a harmony. If it were ruled by caprice, what
could prove to us it was not ruled by chance?

This conquest of law we owe to astronomy, and just this makes the
grandeur of the science rather than the material grandeur of the objects
it considers. It was altogether natural, then, that celestial mechanics
should be the first model of mathematical physics; but since then this
science has developed; it is still developing, even rapidly developing.
And it is already necessary to modify in certain points the scheme from
which I drew two chapters of 'Science and Hypothesis.' In an address at
the St. Louis exposition, I sought to survey the road traveled; the
result of this investigation the reader shall see farther on.

The progress of science has seemed to imperil the best established
principles, those even which were regarded as fundamental. Yet nothing
shows they will not be saved; and if this comes about only imperfectly,
they will still subsist even though they are modified. The advance of
science is not comparable to the changes of a city, where old edifices
are pitilessly torn down to give place to new, but to the continuous
evolution of zoologic types which develop ceaselessly and end by
becoming unrecognizable to the common sight, but where an expert eye
finds always traces of the prior work of the centuries past. One must
not think then that the old-fashioned theories have been sterile and
vain.

Were we to stop there, we should find in these pages some reasons for
confidence in the value of science, but many more for distrusting it; an
impression of doubt would remain; it is needful now to set things to
rights.

Some people have exaggerated the rôle of convention in science; they
have even gone so far as to say that law, that scientific fact itself,
was created by the scientist. This is going much too far in the
direction of nominalism. No, scientific laws are not artificial
creations; we have no reason to regard them as accidental, though it be
impossible to prove they are not.

Does the harmony the human intelligence thinks it discovers in nature
exist outside of this intelligence? No, beyond doubt a reality
completely independent of the mind which conceives it, sees or feels it,
is an impossibility. A world as exterior as that, even if it existed,
would for us be forever inaccessible. But what we call objective reality
is, in the last analysis, what is common to many thinking beings, and
could be common to all; this common part, we shall see, can only be the
harmony expressed by mathematical laws. It is this harmony then which is
the sole objective reality, the only truth we can attain; and when I add
that the universal harmony of the world is the source of all beauty, it
will be understood what price we should attach to the slow and difficult
progress which little by little enables us to know it better.



PART I


THE MATHEMATICAL SCIENCES



CHAPTER I

INTUITION AND LOGIC IN MATHEMATICS


I

It is impossible to study the works of the great mathematicians, or even
those of the lesser, without noticing and distinguishing two opposite
tendencies, or rather two entirely different kinds of minds. The one
sort are above all preoccupied with logic; to read their works, one is
tempted to believe they have advanced only step by step, after the
manner of a Vauban who pushes on his trenches against the place
besieged, leaving nothing to chance. The other sort are guided by
intuition and at the first stroke make quick but sometimes precarious
conquests, like bold cavalrymen of the advance guard.

The method is not imposed by the matter treated. Though one often says
of the first that they are _analysts_ and calls the others _geometers_,
that does not prevent the one sort from remaining analysts even when
they work at geometry, while the others are still geometers even when
they occupy themselves with pure analysis. It is the very nature of
their mind which makes them logicians or intuitionalists, and they can
not lay it aside when they approach a new subject.

Nor is it education which has developed in them one of the two
tendencies and stifled the other. The mathematician is born, not made,
and it seems he is born a geometer or an analyst. I should like to cite
examples and there are surely plenty; but to accentuate the contrast I
shall begin with an extreme example, taking the liberty of seeking it in
two living mathematicians.

M. Méray wants to prove that a binomial equation always has a root, or,
in ordinary words, that an angle may always be subdivided. If there is
any truth that we think we know by direct intuition, it is this. Who
could doubt that an angle may always be divided into any number of equal
parts? M. Méray does not look at it that way; in his eyes this
proposition is not at all evident and to prove it he needs several
pages.

On the other hand, look at Professor Klein: he is studying one of the
most abstract questions of the theory of functions: to determine whether
on a given Riemann surface there always exists a function admitting of
given singularities. What does the celebrated German geometer do? He
replaces his Riemann surface by a metallic surface whose electric
conductivity varies according to certain laws. He connects two of its
points with the two poles of a battery. The current, says he, must pass,
and the distribution of this current on the surface will define a
function whose singularities will be precisely those called for by the
enunciation.

Doubtless Professor Klein well knows he has given here only a sketch;
nevertheless he has not hesitated to publish it; and he would probably
believe he finds in it, if not a rigorous demonstration, at least a kind
of moral certainty. A logician would have rejected with horror such a
conception, or rather he would not have had to reject it, because in his
mind it would never have originated.

Again, permit me to compare two men, the honor of French science, who
have recently been taken from us, but who both entered long ago into
immortality. I speak of M. Bertrand and M. Hermite. They were scholars
of the same school at the same time; they had the same education, were
under the same influences; and yet what a difference! Not only does it
blaze forth in their writings; it is in their teaching, in their way of
speaking, in their very look. In the memory of all their pupils these
two faces are stamped in deathless lines; for all who have had the
pleasure of following their teaching, this remembrance is still fresh;
it is easy for us to evoke it.

While speaking, M. Bertrand is always in motion; now he seems in combat
with some outside enemy, now he outlines with a gesture of the hand the
figures he studies. Plainly he sees and he is eager to paint, this is
why he calls gesture to his aid. With M. Hermite, it is just the
opposite; his eyes seem to shun contact with the world; it is not
without, it is within he seeks the vision of truth.

Among the German geometers of this century, two names above all are
illustrious, those of the two scientists who founded the general theory
of functions, Weierstrass and Riemann. Weierstrass leads everything back
to the consideration of series and their analytic transformations; to
express it better, he reduces analysis to a sort of prolongation of
arithmetic; you may turn through all his books without finding a figure.
Riemann, on the contrary, at once calls geometry to his aid; each of his
conceptions is an image that no one can forget, once he has caught its
meaning.

More recently, Lie was an intuitionalist; this might have been doubted
in reading his books, no one could doubt it after talking with him; you
saw at once that he thought in pictures. Madame Kovalevski was a
logician.

Among our students we notice the same differences; some prefer to treat
their problems 'by analysis,' others 'by geometry.' The first are
incapable of 'seeing in space,' the others are quickly tired of long
calculations and become perplexed.

The two sorts of minds are equally necessary for the progress of
science; both the logicians and the intuitionalists have achieved great
things that others could not have done. Who would venture to say whether
he preferred that Weierstrass had never written or that there had never
been a Riemann? Analysis and synthesis have then both their legitimate
rôles. But it is interesting to study more closely in the history of
science the part which belongs to each.


II

Strange! If we read over the works of the ancients we are tempted to
class them all among the intuitionalists. And yet nature is always the
same; it is hardly probable that it has begun in this century to create
minds devoted to logic. If we could put ourselves into the flow of ideas
which reigned in their time, we should recognize that many of the old
geometers were in tendency analysts. Euclid, for example, erected a
scientific structure wherein his contemporaries could find no fault. In
this vast construction, of which each piece however is due to intuition,
we may still to-day, without much effort, recognize the work of a
logician.

It is not minds that have changed, it is ideas; the intuitional minds
have remained the same; but their readers have required of them greater
concessions.

What is the cause of this evolution? It is not hard to find. Intuition
can not give us rigor, nor even certainty; this has been recognized more
and more. Let us cite some examples. We know there exist continuous
functions lacking derivatives. Nothing is more shocking to intuition
than this proposition which is imposed upon us by logic. Our fathers
would not have failed to say: "It is evident that every continuous
function has a derivative, since every curve has a tangent."

How can intuition deceive us on this point? It is because when we seek
to imagine a curve we can not represent it to ourselves without width;
just so, when we represent to ourselves a straight line, we see it under
the form of a rectilinear band of a certain breadth. We well know these
lines have no width; we try to imagine them narrower and narrower and
thus to approach the limit; so we do in a certain measure, but we shall
never attain this limit. And then it is clear we can always picture
these two narrow bands, one straight, one curved, in a position such
that they encroach slightly one upon the other without crossing. We
shall thus be led, unless warned by a rigorous analysis, to conclude
that a curve always has a tangent.

I shall take as second example Dirichlet's principle on which rest so
many theorems of mathematical physics; to-day we establish it by
reasoning very rigorous but very long; heretofore, on the contrary, we
were content with a very summary proof. A certain integral depending on
an arbitrary function can never vanish. Hence it is concluded that it
must have a minimum. The flaw in this reasoning strikes us immediately,
since we use the abstract term _function_ and are familiar with all the
singularities functions can present when the word is understood in the
most general sense.

But it would not be the same had we used concrete images, had we, for
example, considered this function as an electric potential; it would
have been thought legitimate to affirm that electrostatic equilibrium
can be attained. Yet perhaps a physical comparison would have awakened
some vague distrust. But if care had been taken to translate the
reasoning into the language of geometry, intermediate between that of
analysis and that of physics, doubtless this distrust would not have
been produced, and perhaps one might thus, even to-day, still deceive
many readers not forewarned.

Intuition, therefore, does not give us certainty. This is why the
evolution had to happen; let us now see how it happened.

It was not slow in being noticed that rigor could not be introduced in
the reasoning unless first made to enter into the definitions. For the
most part the objects treated of by mathematicians were long ill
defined; they were supposed to be known because represented by means of
the senses or the imagination; but one had only a crude image of them
and not a precise idea on which reasoning could take hold. It was there
first that the logicians had to direct their efforts.

So, in the case of incommensurable numbers. The vague idea of
continuity, which we owe to intuition, resolved itself into a
complicated system of inequalities referring to whole numbers.

By that means the difficulties arising from passing to the limit, or
from the consideration of infinitesimals, are finally removed. To-day in
analysis only whole numbers are left or systems, finite or infinite, of
whole numbers bound together by a net of equality or inequality
relations. Mathematics, as they say, is arithmetized.


III

A first question presents itself. Is this evolution ended? Have we
finally attained absolute rigor? At each stage of the evolution our
fathers also thought they had reached it. If they deceived themselves,
do we not likewise cheat ourselves?

We believe that in our reasonings we no longer appeal to intuition; the
philosophers will tell us this is an illusion. Pure logic could never
lead us to anything but tautologies; it could create nothing new; not
from it alone can any science issue. In one sense these philosophers are
right; to make arithmetic, as to make geometry, or to make any science,
something else than pure logic is necessary. To designate this something
else we have no word other than _intuition_. But how many different
ideas are hidden under this same word?

Compare these four axioms: (1) Two quantities equal to a third are equal
to one another; (2) if a theorem is true of the number 1 and if we prove
that it is true of _n_ + 1 if true for _n_, then will it be true of all
whole numbers; (3) if on a straight the point _C_ is between _A_ and _B_
and the point _D_ between _A_ and _C_, then the point _D_ will be
between _A_ and _B_; (4) through a given point there is not more than
one parallel to a given straight.

All four are attributed to intuition, and yet the first is the
enunciation of one of the rules of formal logic; the second is a real
synthetic _a priori_ judgment, it is the foundation of rigorous
mathematical induction; the third is an appeal to the imagination; the
fourth is a disguised definition.

Intuition is not necessarily founded on the evidence of the senses; the
senses would soon become powerless; for example, we can not represent to
ourselves a chiliagon, and yet we reason by intuition on polygons in
general, which include the chiliagon as a particular case.

You know what Poncelet understood by the _principle of continuity_. What
is true of a real quantity, said Poncelet, should be true of an
imaginary quantity; what is true of the hyperbola whose asymptotes are
real, should then be true of the ellipse whose asymptotes are imaginary.
Poncelet was one of the most intuitive minds of this century; he was
passionately, almost ostentatiously, so; he regarded the principle of
continuity as one of his boldest conceptions, and yet this principle did
not rest on the evidence of the senses. To assimilate the hyperbola to
the ellipse was rather to contradict this evidence. It was only a sort
of precocious and instinctive generalization which, moreover, I have no
desire to defend.

We have then many kinds of intuition; first, the appeal to the senses
and the imagination; next, generalization by induction, copied, so to
speak, from the procedures of the experimental sciences; finally, we
have the intuition of pure number, whence arose the second of the axioms
just enunciated, which is able to create the real mathematical
reasoning. I have shown above by examples that the first two can not
give us certainty; but who will seriously doubt the third, who will
doubt arithmetic?

Now in the analysis of to-day, when one cares to take the trouble to be
rigorous, there can be nothing but syllogisms or appeals to this
intuition of pure number, the only intuition which can not deceive us.
It may be said that to-day absolute rigor is attained.


IV

The philosophers make still another objection: "What you gain in rigor,"
they say, "you lose in objectivity. You can rise toward your logical
ideal only by cutting the bonds which attach you to reality. Your
science is infallible, but it can only remain so by imprisoning itself
in an ivory tower and renouncing all relation with the external world.
From this seclusion it must go out when it would attempt the slightest
application."

For example, I seek to show that some property pertains to some object
whose concept seems to me at first indefinable, because it is intuitive.
At first I fail or must content myself with approximate proofs; finally
I decide to give to my object a precise definition, and this enables me
to establish this property in an irreproachable manner.

"And then," say the philosophers, "it still remains to show that the
object which corresponds to this definition is indeed the same made
known to you by intuition; or else that some real and concrete object
whose conformity with your intuitive idea you believe you immediately
recognize corresponds to your new definition. Only then could you affirm
that it has the property in question. You have only displaced the
difficulty."

That is not exactly so; the difficulty has not been displaced, it has
been divided. The proposition to be established was in reality composed
of two different truths, at first not distinguished. The first was a
mathematical truth, and it is now rigorously established. The second was
an experimental verity. Experience alone can teach us that some real and
concrete object corresponds or does not correspond to some abstract
definition. This second verity is not mathematically demonstrated, but
neither can it be, no more than can the empirical laws of the physical
and natural sciences. It would be unreasonable to ask more.

Well, is it not a great advance to have distinguished what long was
wrongly confused? Does this mean that nothing is left of this objection
of the philosophers? That I do not intend to say; in becoming rigorous,
mathematical science takes a character so artificial as to strike every
one; it forgets its historical origins; we see how the questions can be
answered, we no longer see how and why they are put.

This shows us that logic is not enough; that the science of
demonstration is not all science and that intuition must retain its rôle
as complement, I was about to say as counterpoise or as antidote of
logic.

I have already had occasion to insist on the place intuition should hold
in the teaching of the mathematical sciences. Without it young minds
could not make a beginning in the understanding of mathematics; they
could not learn to love it and would see in it only a vain logomachy;
above all, without intuition they would never become capable of applying
mathematics. But now I wish before all to speak of the rôle of intuition
in science itself. If it is useful to the student it is still more so to
the creative scientist.


V

We seek reality, but what is reality? The physiologists tell us that
organisms are formed of cells; the chemists add that cells themselves
are formed of atoms. Does this mean that these atoms or these cells
constitute reality, or rather the sole reality? The way in which these
cells are arranged and from which results the unity of the individual,
is not it also a reality much more interesting than that of the isolated
elements, and should a naturalist who had never studied the elephant
except by means of the microscope think himself sufficiently acquainted
with that animal?

Well, there is something analogous to this in mathematics. The logician
cuts up, so to speak, each demonstration into a very great number of
elementary operations; when we have examined these operations one after
the other and ascertained that each is correct, are we to think we have
grasped the real meaning of the demonstration? Shall we have understood
it even when, by an effort of memory, we have become able to repeat this
proof by reproducing all these elementary operations in just the order
in which the inventor had arranged them? Evidently not; we shall not yet
possess the entire reality; that I know not what, which makes the unity
of the demonstration, will completely elude us.

Pure analysis puts at our disposal a multitude of procedures whose
infallibility it guarantees; it opens to us a thousand different ways on
which we can embark in all confidence; we are assured of meeting there
no obstacles; but of all these ways, which will lead us most promptly to
our goal? Who shall tell us which to choose? We need a faculty which
makes us see the end from afar, and intuition is this faculty. It is
necessary to the explorer for choosing his route; it is not less so to
the one following his trail who wants to know why he chose it.

If you are present at a game of chess, it will not suffice, for the
understanding of the game, to know the rules for moving the pieces. That
will only enable you to recognize that each move has been made
conformably to these rules, and this knowledge will truly have very
little value. Yet this is what the reader of a book on mathematics would
do if he were a logician only. To understand the game is wholly another
matter; it is to know why the player moves this piece rather than that
other which he could have moved without breaking the rules of the game.
It is to perceive the inward reason which makes of this series of
successive moves a sort of organized whole. This faculty is still more
necessary for the player himself, that is, for the inventor.

Let us drop this comparison and return to mathematics. For example, see
what has happened to the idea of continuous function. At the outset this
was only a sensible image, for example, that of a continuous mark traced
by the chalk on a blackboard. Then it became little by little more
refined; ere long it was used to construct a complicated system of
inequalities, which reproduced, so to speak, all the lines of the
original image; this construction finished, the centering of the arch,
so to say, was removed, that crude representation which had temporarily
served as support and which was afterward useless was rejected; there
remained only the construction itself, irreproachable in the eyes of the
logician. And yet if the primitive image had totally disappeared from
our recollection, how could we divine by what caprice all these
inequalities were erected in this fashion one upon another?

Perhaps you think I use too many comparisons; yet pardon still another.
You have doubtless seen those delicate assemblages of silicious needles
which form the skeleton of certain sponges. When the organic matter has
disappeared, there remains only a frail and elegant lace-work. True,
nothing is there except silica, but what is interesting is the form this
silica has taken, and we could not understand it if we did not know the
living sponge which has given it precisely this form. Thus it is that
the old intuitive notions of our fathers, even when we have abandoned
them, still imprint their form upon the logical constructions we have
put in their place.

This view of the aggregate is necessary for the inventor; it is equally
necessary for whoever wishes really to comprehend the inventor. Can
logic give it to us? No; the name mathematicians give it would suffice
to prove this. In mathematics logic is called _analysis_ and analysis
means _division_, _dissection_. It can have, therefore, no tool other
than the scalpel and the microscope.

Thus logic and intuition have each their necessary rôle. Each is
indispensable. Logic, which alone can give certainty, is the instrument
of demonstration; intuition is the instrument of invention.


VI

But at the moment of formulating this conclusion I am seized with
scruples. At the outset I distinguished two kinds of mathematical minds,
the one sort logicians and analysts, the others intuitionalists and
geometers. Well, the analysts also have been inventors. The names I have
just cited make my insistence on this unnecessary.

Here is a contradiction, at least apparently, which needs explanation.
And first, do you think these logicians have always proceeded from the
general to the particular, as the rules of formal logic would seem to
require of them? Not thus could they have extended the boundaries of
science; scientific conquest is to be made only by generalization.

In one of the chapters of 'Science and Hypothesis,' I have had occasion
to study the nature of mathematical reasoning, and I have shown how this
reasoning, without ceasing to be absolutely rigorous, could lift us from
the particular to the general by a procedure I have called _mathematical
induction_. It is by this procedure that the analysts have made science
progress, and if we examine the detail itself of their demonstrations,
we shall find it there at each instant beside the classic syllogism of
Aristotle. We, therefore, see already that the analysts are not simply
makers of syllogisms after the fashion of the scholastics.

Besides, do you think they have always marched step by step with no
vision of the goal they wished to attain? They must have divined the way
leading thither, and for that they needed a guide. This guide is, first,
analogy. For example, one of the methods of demonstration dear to
analysts is that founded on the employment of dominant functions. We
know it has already served to solve a multitude of problems; in what
consists then the rôle of the inventor who wishes to apply it to a new
problem? At the outset he must recognize the analogy of this question
with those which have already been solved by this method; then he must
perceive in what way this new question differs from the others, and
thence deduce the modifications necessary to apply to the method.

But how does one perceive these analogies and these differences? In the
example just cited they are almost always evident, but I could have
found others where they would have been much more deeply hidden; often a
very uncommon penetration is necessary for their discovery. The
analysts, not to let these hidden analogies escape them, that is, in
order to be inventors, must, without the aid of the senses and
imagination, have a direct sense of what constitutes the unity of a
piece of reasoning, of what makes, so to speak, its soul and inmost
life.

When one talked with M. Hermite, he never evoked a sensuous image, and
yet you soon perceived that the most abstract entities were for him like
living beings. He did not see them, but he perceived that they are not
an artificial assemblage and that they have some principle of internal
unity.

But, one will say, that still is intuition. Shall we conclude that the
distinction made at the outset was only apparent, that there is only one
sort of mind and that all the mathematicians are intuitionalists, at
least those who are capable of inventing?

No, our distinction corresponds to something real. I have said above
that there are many kinds of intuition. I have said how much the
intuition of pure number, whence comes rigorous mathematical induction,
differs from sensible intuition to which the imagination, properly so
called, is the principal contributor.

Is the abyss which separates them less profound than it at first
appeared? Could we recognize with a little attention that this pure
intuition itself could not do without the aid of the senses? This is the
affair of the psychologist and the metaphysician and I shall not discuss
the question. But the thing's being doubtful is enough to justify me in
recognizing and affirming an essential difference between the two kinds
of intuition; they have not the same object and seem to call into play
two different faculties of our soul; one would think of two
search-lights directed upon two worlds strangers to one another.

It is the intuition of pure number, that of pure logical forms, which
illumines and directs those we have called _analysts_. This it is which
enables them not alone to demonstrate, but also to invent. By it they
perceive at a glance the general plan of a logical edifice, and that too
without the senses appearing to intervene. In rejecting the aid of the
imagination, which, as we have seen, is not always infallible, they can
advance without fear of deceiving themselves. Happy, therefore, are
those who can do without this aid! We must admire them; but how rare
they are!

Among the analysts there will then be inventors, but they will be few.
The majority of us, if we wished to see afar by pure intuition alone,
would soon feel ourselves seized with vertigo. Our weakness has need of
a staff more solid, and, despite the exceptions of which we have just
spoken, it is none the less true that sensible intuition is in
mathematics the most usual instrument of invention.

Apropos of these reflections, a question comes up that I have not the
time either to solve or even to enunciate with the developments it would
admit of. Is there room for a new distinction, for distinguishing among
the analysts those who above all use pure intuition and those who are
first of all preoccupied with formal logic?

M. Hermite, for example, whom I have just cited, can not be classed
among the geometers who make use of the sensible intuition; but neither
is he a logician, properly so called. He does not conceal his aversion
to purely deductive procedures which start from the general and end in
the particular.



CHAPTER II

THE MEASURE OF TIME


I

So long as we do not go outside the domain of consciousness, the notion
of time is relatively clear. Not only do we distinguish without
difficulty present sensation from the remembrance of past sensations or
the anticipation of future sensations, but we know perfectly well what
we mean when we say that of two conscious phenomena which we remember,
one was anterior to the other; or that, of two foreseen conscious
phenomena, one will be anterior to the other.

When we say that two conscious facts are simultaneous, we mean that they
profoundly interpenetrate, so that analysis can not separate them
without mutilating them.

The order in which we arrange conscious phenomena does not admit of any
arbitrariness. It is imposed upon us and of it we can change nothing.

I have only a single observation to add. For an aggregate of sensations
to have become a remembrance capable of classification in time, it must
have ceased to be actual, we must have lost the sense of its infinite
complexity, otherwise it would have remained present. It must, so to
speak, have crystallized around a center of associations of ideas which
will be a sort of label. It is only when they thus have lost all life
that we can classify our memories in time as a botanist arranges dried
flowers in his herbarium.

But these labels can only be finite in number. On that score,
psychologic time should be discontinuous. Whence comes the feeling that
between any two instants there are others? We arrange our recollections
in time, but we know that there remain empty compartments. How could
that be, if time were not a form pre-existent in our minds? How could we
know there were empty compartments, if these compartments were revealed
to us only by their content?


II

But that is not all; into this form we wish to put not only the
phenomena of our own consciousness, but those of which other
consciousnesses are the theater. But more, we wish to put there physical
facts, these I know not what with which we people space and which no
consciousness sees directly. This is necessary because without it
science could not exist. In a word, psychologic time is given to us and
must needs create scientific and physical time. There the difficulty
begins, or rather the difficulties, for there are two.

Think of two consciousnesses, which are like two worlds impenetrable one
to the other. By what right do we strive to put them into the same mold,
to measure them by the same standard? Is it not as if one strove to
measure length with a gram or weight with a meter? And besides, why do
we speak of measuring? We know perhaps that some fact is anterior to
some other, but not _by how much_ it is anterior.

Therefore two difficulties: (1) Can we transform psychologic time, which
is qualitative, into a quantitative time? (2) Can we reduce to one and
the same measure facts which transpire in different worlds?


III

The first difficulty has long been noticed; it has been the subject of
long discussions and one may say the question is settled. _We have not a
direct intuition of the equality of two intervals of time._ The persons
who believe they possess this intuition are dupes of an illusion. When I
say, from noon to one the same time passes as from two to three, what
meaning has this affirmation?

The least reflection shows that by itself it has none at all. It will
only have that which I choose to give it, by a definition which will
certainly possess a certain degree of arbitrariness. Psychologists could
have done without this definition; physicists and astronomers could not;
let us see how they have managed.

To measure time they use the pendulum and they suppose by definition
that all the beats of this pendulum are of equal duration. But this is
only a first approximation; the temperature, the resistance of the air,
the barometric pressure, make the pace of the pendulum vary. If we
could escape these sources of error, we should obtain a much closer
approximation, but it would still be only an approximation. New causes,
hitherto neglected, electric, magnetic or others, would introduce minute
perturbations.

In fact, the best chronometers must be corrected from time to time, and
the corrections are made by the aid of astronomic observations;
arrangements are made so that the sidereal clock marks the same hour
when the same star passes the meridian. In other words, it is the
sidereal day, that is, the duration of the rotation of the earth, which
is the constant unit of time. It is supposed, by a new definition
substituted for that based on the beats of the pendulum, that two
complete rotations of the earth about its axis have the same duration.

However, the astronomers are still not content with this definition.
Many of them think that the tides act as a check on our globe, and that
the rotation of the earth is becoming slower and slower. Thus would be
explained the apparent acceleration of the motion of the moon, which
would seem to be going more rapidly than theory permits because our
watch, which is the earth, is going slow.


IV

All this is unimportant, one will say; doubtless our instruments of
measurement are imperfect, but it suffices that we can conceive a
perfect instrument. This ideal can not be reached, but it is enough to
have conceived it and so to have put rigor into the definition of the
unit of time.

The trouble is that there is no rigor in the definition. When we use the
pendulum to measure time, what postulate do we implicitly admit? _It is
that the duration of two identical phenomena is the same_; or, if you
prefer, that the same causes take the same time to produce the same
effects.

And at first blush, this is a good definition of the equality of two
durations. But take care. Is it impossible that experiment may some day
contradict our postulate?

Let me explain myself. I suppose that at a certain place in the world
the phenomenon [alpha] happens, causing as consequence at the end of a
certain time the effect [alpha]'. At another place in the world very
far away from the first, happens the phenomenon [beta], which causes as
consequence the effect [beta]'. The phenomena [alpha] and [beta] are
simultaneous, as are also the effects [alpha]' and [beta]'.

Later, the phenomenon [alpha] is reproduced under approximately the same
conditions as before, and _simultaneously_ the phenomenon [beta] is also
reproduced at a very distant place in the world and almost under the
same circumstances. The effects [alpha]' and [beta]' also take place.
Let us suppose that the effect [alpha]' happens perceptibly before the
effect [beta]'.

If experience made us witness such a sight, our postulate would be
contradicted. For experience would tell us that the first duration
[alpha][alpha]' is equal to the first duration [beta][beta]' and that
the second duration [alpha][alpha]' is less than the second duration
[beta][beta]'. On the other hand, our postulate would require that the
two durations [alpha][alpha]' should be equal to each other, as likewise
the two durations [beta][beta]'. The equality and the inequality deduced
from experience would be incompatible with the two equalities deduced
from the postulate.

Now can we affirm that the hypotheses I have just made are absurd? They
are in no wise contrary to the principle of contradiction. Doubtless
they could not happen without the principle of sufficient reason seeming
violated. But to justify a definition so fundamental I should prefer
some other guarantee.


V

But that is not all. In physical reality one cause does not produce a
given effect, but a multitude of distinct causes contribute to produce
it, without our having any means of discriminating the part of each of
them.

Physicists seek to make this distinction; but they make it only
approximately, and, however they progress, they never will make it
except approximately. It is approximately true that the motion of the
pendulum is due solely to the earth's attraction; but in all rigor every
attraction, even of Sirius, acts on the pendulum.

Under these conditions, it is clear that the causes which have produced
a certain effect will never be reproduced except approximately. Then we
should modify our postulate and our definition. Instead of saying: 'The
same causes take the same time to produce the same effects,' we should
say: 'Causes almost identical take almost the same time to produce
almost the same effects.'

Our definition therefore is no longer anything but approximate. Besides,
as M. Calinon very justly remarks in a recent memoir:[7]

     One of the circumstances of any phenomenon is the velocity of
     the earth's rotation; if this velocity of rotation varies, it
     constitutes in the reproduction of this phenomenon a
     circumstance which no longer remains the same. But to suppose
     this velocity of rotation constant is to suppose that we know
     how to measure time.

  [7] _Etude sur les diverses grandeurs_, Paris, Gauthier-Villars, 1897.

Our definition is therefore not yet satisfactory; it is certainly not
that which the astronomers of whom I spoke above implicitly adopt, when
they affirm that the terrestrial rotation is slowing down.

What meaning according to them has this affirmation? We can only
understand it by analyzing the proofs they give of their proposition.
They say first that the friction of the tides producing heat must
destroy _vis viva_. They invoke therefore the principle of _vis viva_,
or of the conservation of energy.

They say next that the secular acceleration of the moon, calculated
according to Newton's law, would be less than that deduced from
observations unless the correction relative to the slowing down of the
terrestrial rotation were made. They invoke therefore Newton's law. In
other words, they define duration in the following way: time should be
so defined that Newton's law and that of _vis viva_ may be verified.
Newton's law is an experimental truth; as such it is only approximate,
which shows that we still have only a definition by approximation.

If now it be supposed that another way of measuring time is adopted, the
experiments on which Newton's law is founded would none the less have
the same meaning. Only the enunciation of the law would be different,
because it would be translated into another language; it would evidently
be much less simple. So that the definition implicitly adopted by the
astronomers may be summed up thus: Time should be so defined that the
equations of mechanics may be as simple as possible. In other words,
there is not one way of measuring time more true than another; that
which is generally adopted is only more _convenient_. Of two watches, we
have no right to say that the one goes true, the other wrong; we can
only say that it is advantageous to conform to the indications of the
first.

The difficulty which has just occupied us has been, as I have said,
often pointed out; among the most recent works in which it is
considered, I may mention, besides M. Calinon's little book, the
treatise on mechanics of Andrade.


VI

The second difficulty has up to the present attracted much less
attention; yet it is altogether analogous to the preceding; and even,
logically, I should have spoken of it first.

Two psychological phenomena happen in two different consciousnesses;
when I say they are simultaneous, what do I mean? When I say that a
physical phenomenon, which happens outside of every consciousness, is
before or after a psychological phenomenon, what do I mean?

In 1572, Tycho Brahe noticed in the heavens a new star. An immense
conflagration had happened in some far distant heavenly body; but it had
happened long before; at least two hundred years were necessary for the
light from that star to reach our earth. This conflagration therefore
happened before the discovery of America. Well, when I say that; when,
considering this gigantic phenomenon, which perhaps had no witness,
since the satellites of that star were perhaps uninhabited, I say this
phenomenon is anterior to the formation of the visual image of the isle
of Española in the consciousness of Christopher Columbus, what do I
mean?

A little reflection is sufficient to understand that all these
affirmations have by themselves no meaning. They can have one only as
the outcome of a convention.


VII

We should first ask ourselves how one could have had the idea of putting
into the same frame so many worlds impenetrable to one another. We
should like to represent to ourselves the external universe, and only by
so doing could we feel that we understood it. We know we never can
attain this representation: our weakness is too great. But at least we
desire the ability to conceive an infinite intelligence for which this
representation could be possible, a sort of great consciousness which
should see all, and which should classify all _in its time_, as we
classify, _in our time_, the little we see.

This hypothesis is indeed crude and incomplete, because this supreme
intelligence would be only a demigod; infinite in one sense, it would be
limited in another, since it would have only an imperfect recollection
of the past; and it could have no other, since otherwise all
recollections would be equally present to it and for it there would be
no time. And yet when we speak of time, for all which happens outside of
us, do we not unconsciously adopt this hypothesis; do we not put
ourselves in the place of this imperfect god; and do not even the
atheists put themselves in the place where god would be if he existed?

What I have just said shows us, perhaps, why we have tried to put all
physical phenomena into the same frame. But that can not pass for a
definition of simultaneity, since this hypothetical intelligence, even
if it existed, would be for us impenetrable. It is therefore necessary
to seek something else.


VIII

The ordinary definitions which are proper for psychologic time would
suffice us no more. Two simultaneous psychologic facts are so closely
bound together that analysis can not separate without mutilating them.
Is it the same with two physical facts? Is not my present nearer my past
of yesterday than the present of Sirius?

It has also been said that two facts should be regarded as simultaneous
when the order of their succession may be inverted at will. It is
evident that this definition would not suit two physical facts which
happen far from one another, and that, in what concerns them, we no
longer even understand what this reversibility would be; besides,
succession itself must first be defined.


IX

Let us then seek to give an account of what is understood by
simultaneity or antecedence, and for this let us analyze some examples.

I write a letter; it is afterward read by the friend to whom I have
addressed it. There are two facts which have had for their theater two
different consciousnesses. In writing this letter I have had the visual
image of it, and my friend has had in his turn this same visual image in
reading the letter. Though these two facts happen in impenetrable
worlds, I do not hesitate to regard the first as anterior to the second,
because I believe it is its cause.

I hear thunder, and I conclude there has been an electric discharge; I
do not hesitate to consider the physical phenomenon as anterior to the
auditory image perceived in my consciousness, because I believe it is
its cause.

Behold then the rule we follow, and the only one we can follow: when a
phenomenon appears to us as the cause of another, we regard it as
anterior. It is therefore by cause that we define time; but most often,
when two facts appear to us bound by a constant relation, how do we
recognize which is the cause and which the effect? We assume that the
anterior fact, the antecedent, is the cause of the other, of the
consequent. It is then by time that we define cause. How save ourselves
from this _petitio principii_?

We say now _post hoc, ergo propter hoc_; now _propter hoc, ergo post
hoc_; shall we escape from this vicious circle?


X

Let us see, not how we succeed in escaping, for we do not completely
succeed, but how we try to escape.

I execute a voluntary act _A_ and I feel afterward a sensation _D_,
which I regard as a consequence of the act _A_; on the other hand, for
whatever reason, I infer that this consequence is not immediate, but
that outside my consciousness two facts _B_ and _C_, which I have not
witnessed, have happened, and in such a way that _B_ is the effect of
_A_, that _C_ is the effect of _B_, and _D_ of _C_.

But why? If I think I have reason to regard the four facts _A_, _B_,
_C_, _D_, as bound to one another by a causal connection, why range
them in the causal order _A B C D_, and at the same time in the
chronologic order _A B C D_, rather than in any other order?

I clearly see that in the act _A_ I have the feeling of having been
active, while in undergoing the sensation _D_ I have that of having been
passive. This is why I regard _A_ as the initial cause and _D_ as the
ultimate effect; this is why I put _A_ at the beginning of the chain and
_D_ at the end; but why put _B_ before _C_ rather than _C_ before _B_?

If this question is put, the reply ordinarily is: we know that it is _B_
which is the cause of _C_ because we always see _B_ happen before _C_.
These two phenomena, when witnessed, happen in a certain order; when
analogous phenomena happen without witness, there is no reason to invert
this order.

Doubtless, but take care; we never know directly the physical phenomena
_B_ and _C_. What we know are sensations _B'_ and _C'_ produced
respectively by _B_ and _C_. Our consciousness tells us immediately that
_B'_ precedes _C'_ and we suppose that _B_ and _C_ succeed one another
in the same order.

This rule appears in fact very natural, and yet we are often led to
depart from it. We hear the sound of the thunder only some seconds after
the electric discharge of the cloud. Of two flashes of lightning, the
one distant, the other near, can not the first be anterior to the
second, even though the sound of the second comes to us before that of
the first?


XI

Another difficulty; have we really the right to speak of the cause of a
phenomenon? If all the parts of the universe are interchained in a
certain measure, any one phenomenon will not be the effect of a single
cause, but the resultant of causes infinitely numerous; it is, one often
says, the consequence of the state of the universe a moment before. How
enunciate rules applicable to circumstances so complex? And yet it is
only thus that these rules can be general and rigorous.

Not to lose ourselves in this infinite complexity, let us make a simpler
hypothesis. Consider three stars, for example, the sun, Jupiter and
Saturn; but, for greater simplicity, regard them as reduced to material
points and isolated from the rest of the world. The positions and the
velocities of three bodies at a given instant suffice to determine their
positions and velocities at the following instant, and consequently
at any instant. Their positions at the instant t determine their
positions at the instant _t_ + _h_ as well as their positions at the
instant _t_ - _h_.

Even more; the position of Jupiter at the instant _t_, together with
that of Saturn at the instant _t_ + _a_, determines the position of
Jupiter at any instant and that of Saturn at any instant.

The aggregate of positions occupied by Jupiter at the instant _t_ + _e_
and Saturn at the instant _t_ + _a_ + _e_ is bound to the aggregate of
positions occupied by Jupiter at the instant _t_ and Saturn at the
instant _t_ + _a_, by laws as precise as that of Newton, though more
complicated. Then why not regard one of these aggregates as the cause of
the other, which would lead to considering as simultaneous the instant
_t_ of Jupiter and the instant _t_ + _a_ of Saturn?

In answer there can only be reasons, very strong, it is true, of
convenience and simplicity.


XII

But let us pass to examples less artificial; to understand the
definition implicitly supposed by the savants, let us watch them at work
and look for the rules by which they investigate simultaneity.

I will take two simple examples, the measurement of the velocity of
light and the determination of longitude.

When an astronomer tells me that some stellar phenomenon, which his
telescope reveals to him at this moment, happened, nevertheless, fifty
years ago, I seek his meaning, and to that end I shall ask him first how
he knows it, that is, how he has measured the velocity of light.

He has begun by _supposing_ that light has a constant velocity, and in
particular that its velocity is the same in all directions. That is a
postulate without which no measurement of this velocity could be
attempted. This postulate could never be verified directly by
experiment; it might be contradicted by it if the results of different
measurements were not concordant. We should think ourselves fortunate
that this contradiction has not happened and that the slight
discordances which may happen can be readily explained.

The postulate, at all events, resembling the principle of sufficient
reason, has been accepted by everybody; what I wish to emphasize is that
it furnishes us with a new rule for the investigation of simultaneity,
entirely different from that which we have enunciated above.

This postulate assumed, let us see how the velocity of light has been
measured. You know that Roemer used eclipses of the satellites of
Jupiter, and sought how much the event fell behind its prediction. But
how is this prediction made? It is by the aid of astronomic laws; for
instance Newton's law.

Could not the observed facts be just as well explained if we attributed
to the velocity of light a little different value from that adopted, and
supposed Newton's law only approximate? Only this would lead to
replacing Newton's law by another more complicated. So for the velocity
of light a value is adopted, such that the astronomic laws compatible
with this value may be as simple as possible. When navigators or
geographers determine a longitude, they have to solve just the problem
we are discussing; they must, without being at Paris, calculate Paris
time. How do they accomplish it? They carry a chronometer set for Paris.
The qualitative problem of simultaneity is made to depend upon the
quantitative problem of the measurement of time. I need not take up the
difficulties relative to this latter problem, since above I have
emphasized them at length.

Or else they observe an astronomic phenomenon, such as an eclipse of the
moon, and they suppose that this phenomenon is perceived simultaneously
from all points of the earth. That is not altogether true, since the
propagation of light is not instantaneous; if absolute exactitude were
desired, there would be a correction to make according to a complicated
rule.

Or else finally they use the telegraph. It is clear first that the
reception of the signal at Berlin, for instance, is after the sending of
this same signal from Paris. This is the rule of cause and effect
analyzed above. But how much after? In general, the duration of the
transmission is neglected and the two events are regarded as
simultaneous. But, to be rigorous, a little correction would still have
to be made by a complicated calculation; in practise it is not made,
because it would be well within the errors of observation; its theoretic
necessity is none the less from our point of view, which is that of a
rigorous definition. From this discussion, I wish to emphasize two
things: (1) The rules applied are exceedingly various. (2) It is
difficult to separate the qualitative problem of simultaneity from the
quantitative problem of the measurement of time; no matter whether a
chronometer is used, or whether account must be taken of a velocity of
transmission, as that of light, because such a velocity could not be
measured without _measuring_ a time.


XIII

To conclude: We have not a direct intuition of simultaneity, nor of the
equality of two durations. If we think we have this intuition, this is
an illusion. We replace it by the aid of certain rules which we apply
almost always without taking count of them.

But what is the nature of these rules? No general rule, no rigorous
rule; a multitude of little rules applicable to each particular case.

These rules are not imposed upon us and we might amuse ourselves in
inventing others; but they could not be cast aside without greatly
complicating the enunciation of the laws of physics, mechanics and
astronomy.

We therefore choose these rules, not because they are true, but because
they are the most convenient, and we may recapitulate them as follows:
"The simultaneity of two events, or the order of their succession, the
equality of two durations, are to be so defined that the enunciation of
the natural laws may be as simple as possible. In other words, all these
rules, all these definitions are only the fruit of an unconscious
opportunism."



CHAPTER III

THE NOTION OF SPACE


1. _Introduction_

In the articles I have heretofore devoted to space I have above all
emphasized the problems raised by non-Euclidean geometry, while leaving
almost completely aside other questions more difficult of approach, such
as those which pertain to the number of dimensions. All the geometries I
considered had thus a common basis, that tridimensional continuum which
was the same for all and which differentiated itself only by the figures
one drew in it or when one aspired to measure it.

In this continuum, primitively amorphous, we may imagine a network of
lines and surfaces, we may then convene to regard the meshes of this net
as equal to one another, and it is only after this convention that this
continuum, become measurable, becomes Euclidean or non-Euclidean space.
From this amorphous continuum can therefore arise indifferently one or
the other of the two spaces, just as on a blank sheet of paper may be
traced indifferently a straight or a circle.

In space we know rectilinear triangles the sum of whose angles is equal
to two right angles; but equally we know curvilinear triangles the sum
of whose angles is less than two right angles. The existence of the one
sort is not more doubtful than that of the other. To give the name of
straights to the sides of the first is to adopt Euclidean geometry; to
give the name of straights to the sides of the latter is to adopt the
non-Euclidean geometry. So that to ask what geometry it is proper to
adopt is to ask, to what line is it proper to give the name straight?

It is evident that experiment can not settle such a question; one would
not ask, for instance, experiment to decide whether I should call _AB_
or _CD_ a straight. On the other hand, neither can I say that I have not
the right to give the name of straights to the sides of non-Euclidean
triangles because they are not in conformity with the eternal idea of
straight which I have by intuition. I grant, indeed, that I have the
intuitive idea of the side of the Euclidean triangle, but I have equally
the intuitive idea of the side of the non-Euclidean triangle. Why should
I have the right to apply the name of straight to the first of these
ideas and not to the second? Wherein does this syllable form an
integrant part of this intuitive idea? Evidently when we say that the
Euclidean straight is a _true_ straight and that the non-Euclidean
straight is not a true straight, we simply mean that the first intuitive
idea corresponds to a _more noteworthy_ object than the second. But how
do we decide that this object is more noteworthy? This question I have
investigated in 'Science and Hypothesis.'

It is here that we saw experience come in. If the Euclidean straight is
more noteworthy than the non-Euclidean straight, it is so chiefly
because it differs little from certain noteworthy natural objects from
which the non-Euclidean straight differs greatly. But, it will be said,
the definition of the non-Euclidean straight is artificial; if we for a
moment adopt it, we shall see that two circles of different radius both
receive the name of non-Euclidean straights, while of two circles of the
same radius one can satisfy the definition without the other being able
to satisfy it, and then if we transport one of these so-called straights
without deforming it, it will cease to be a straight. But by what right
do we consider as equal these two figures which the Euclidean geometers
call two circles with the same radius? It is because by transporting one
of them without deforming it we can make it coincide with the other. And
why do we say this transportation is effected without deformation? It is
impossible to give a good reason for it. Among all the motions
conceivable, there are some of which the Euclidean geometers say that
they are not accompanied by deformation; but there are others of which
the non-Euclidean geometers would say that they are not accompanied by
deformation. In the first, called Euclidean motions, the Euclidean
straights remain Euclidean straights and the non-Euclidean straights do
not remain non-Euclidean straights; in the motions of the second sort,
or non-Euclidean motions, the non-Euclidean straights remain
non-Euclidean straights and the Euclidean straights do not remain
Euclidean straights. It has, therefore, not been demonstrated that it
was unreasonable to call straights the sides of non-Euclidean triangles;
it has only been shown that that would be unreasonable if one continued
to call the Euclidean motions motions without deformation; but it has at
the same time been shown that it would be just as unreasonable to call
straights the sides of Euclidean triangles if the non-Euclidean motions
were called motions without deformation.

Now when we say that the Euclidean motions are the _true_ motions
without deformation, what do we mean? We simply mean that they are _more
noteworthy_ than the others. And why are they more noteworthy? It is
because certain noteworthy natural bodies, the solid bodies, undergo
motions almost similar.

And then when we ask: Can one imagine non-Euclidean space? That means:
Can we imagine a world where there would be noteworthy natural objects
affecting almost the form of non-Euclidean straights, and noteworthy
natural bodies frequently undergoing motions almost similar to the
non-Euclidean motions? I have shown in 'Science and Hypothesis' that to
this question we must answer yes.

It has often been observed that if all the bodies in the universe were
dilated simultaneously and in the same proportion, we should have no
means of perceiving it, since all our measuring instruments would grow
at the same time as the objects themselves which they serve to measure.
The world, after this dilatation, would continue on its course without
anything apprising us of so considerable an event. In other words, two
worlds similar to one another (understanding the word similitude in the
sense of Euclid, Book VI.) would be absolutely indistinguishable. But
more; worlds will be indistinguishable not only if they are equal or
similar, that is, if we can pass from one to the other by changing the
axes of coordinates, or by changing the scale to which lengths are
referred; but they will still be indistinguishable if we can pass from
one to the other by any 'point-transformation' whatever. I will explain
my meaning. I suppose that to each point of one corresponds one point of
the other and only one, and inversely; and besides that the coordinates
of a point are continuous functions, _otherwise altogether arbitrary_,
of the corresponding point. I suppose besides that to each object of the
first world corresponds in the second an object of the same nature
placed precisely at the corresponding point. I suppose finally that this
correspondence fulfilled at the initial instant is maintained
indefinitely. We should have no means of distinguishing these two worlds
one from the other. The relativity of space is not ordinarily understood
in so broad a sense; it is thus, however, that it would be proper to
understand it.

If one of these universes is our Euclidean world, what its inhabitants
will call straight will be our Euclidean straight; but what the
inhabitants of the second world will call straight will be a curve which
will have the same properties in relation to the world they inhabit and
in relation to the motions that they will call motions without
deformation. Their geometry will, therefore, be Euclidean geometry, but
their straight will not be our Euclidean straight. It will be its
transform by the point-transformation which carries over from our world
to theirs. The straights of these men will not be our straights, but
they will have among themselves the same relations as our straights to
one another. It is in this sense I say their geometry will be ours. If
then we wish after all to proclaim that they deceive themselves, that
their straight is not the true straight, if we still are unwilling to
admit that such an affirmation has no meaning, at least we must confess
that these people have no means whatever of recognizing their error.


2. _Qualitative Geometry_

All that is relatively easy to understand, and I have already so often
repeated it that I think it needless to expatiate further on the matter.
Euclidean space is not a form imposed upon our sensibility, since we can
imagine non-Euclidean space; but the two spaces, Euclidean and
non-Euclidean, have a common basis, that amorphous continuum of which I
spoke in the beginning. From this continuum we can get either Euclidean
space or Lobachevskian space, just as we can, by tracing upon it a
proper graduation, transform an ungraduated thermometer into a
Fahrenheit or a Réaumur thermometer.

And then comes a question: Is not this amorphous continuum, that our
analysis has allowed to survive, a form imposed upon our sensibility? If
so, we should have enlarged the prison in which this sensibility is
confined, but it would always be a prison.

This continuum has a certain number of properties, exempt from all idea
of measurement. The study of these properties is the object of a science
which has been cultivated by many great geometers and in particular by
Riemann and Betti and which has received the name of analysis situs. In
this science abstraction is made of every quantitative idea and, for
example, if we ascertain that on a line the point _B_ is between the
points _A_ and _C_, we shall be content with this ascertainment and
shall not trouble to know whether the line _ABC_ is straight or curved,
nor whether the length _AB_ is equal to the length _BC_, or whether it
is twice as great.

The theorems of analysis situs have, therefore, this peculiarity, that
they would remain true if the figures were copied by an inexpert
draftsman who should grossly change all the proportions and replace the
straights by lines more or less sinuous. In mathematical terms, they are
not altered by any 'point-transformation' whatsoever. It has often been
said that metric geometry was quantitative, while projective geometry
was purely qualitative. That is not altogether true. The straight is
still distinguished from other lines by properties which remain
quantitative in some respects. The real qualitative geometry is,
therefore, analysis situs.

The same questions which came up apropos of the truths of Euclidean
geometry, come up anew apropos of the theorems of analysis situs. Are
they obtainable by deductive reasoning? Are they disguised conventions?
Are they experimental verities? Are they the characteristics of a form
imposed either upon our sensibility or upon our understanding?

I wish simply to observe that the last two solutions exclude each other.
We can not admit at the same time that it is impossible to imagine space
of four dimensions and that experience proves to us that space has three
dimensions. The experimenter puts to nature a question: Is it this or
that? and he can not put it without imagining the two terms of the
alternative. If it were impossible to imagine one of these terms, it
would be futile and besides impossible to consult experience. There is
no need of observation to know that the hand of a watch is not marking
the hour 15 on the dial, because we know beforehand that there are only
12, and we could not look at the mark 15 to see if the hand is there,
because this mark does not exist.

Note likewise that in analysis situs the empiricists are disembarrassed
of one of the gravest objections that can be leveled against them, of
that which renders absolutely vain in advance all their efforts to apply
their thesis to the verities of Euclidean geometry. These verities are
rigorous and all experimentation can only be approximate. In analysis
situs approximate experiments may suffice to give a rigorous theorem
and, for instance, if it is seen that space can not have either two or
less than two dimensions, nor four or more than four, we are certain
that it has exactly three, since it could not have two and a half or
three and a half.

Of all the theorems of analysis situs, the most important is that which
is expressed in saying that space has three dimensions. This it is that
we are about to consider, and we shall put the question in these terms:
When we say that space has three dimensions, what do we mean?


3. _The Physical Continuum of Several Dimensions_

I have explained in 'Science and Hypothesis' whence we derive the notion
of physical continuity and how that of mathematical continuity has
arisen from it. It happens that we are capable of distinguishing two
impressions one from the other, while each is indistinguishable from a
third. Thus we can readily distinguish a weight of 12 grams from a
weight of 10 grams, while a weight of 11 grams could be distinguished
from neither the one nor the other. Such a statement, translated into
symbols, may be written:

  _A_ = _B_,   _B_ = _C_,   _A_ < _C_.

This would be the formula of the physical continuum, as crude experience
gives it to us, whence arises an intolerable contradiction that has
been obviated by the introduction of the mathematical continuum. This is
a scale of which the steps (commensurable or incommensurable numbers)
are infinite in number but are exterior to one another, instead of
encroaching on one another as do the elements of the physical continuum,
in conformity with the preceding formula.

The physical continuum is, so to speak, a nebula not resolved; the most
perfect instruments could not attain to its resolution. Doubtless if we
measured the weights with a good balance instead of judging them by the
hand, we could distinguish the weight of 11 grams from those of 10 and
12 grams, and our formula would become:

  _A_ < _B_,   _B_ < _C_,   _A_ < _C_.

But we should always find between _A_ and _B_ and between _B_ and _C_
new elements _D_ and _E_, such that

  _A_ = _D_,   _D_ = _B_,   _A_ < _B_;
  _B_ = _E_,   _E_ = _C_,   _B_ < _C_,

and the difficulty would only have receded and the nebula would always
remain unresolved; the mind alone can resolve it and the mathematical
continuum it is which is the nebula resolved into stars.

Yet up to this point we have not introduced the notion of the number of
dimensions. What is meant when we say that a mathematical continuum or
that a physical continuum has two or three dimensions?

First we must introduce the notion of cut, studying first physical
continua. We have seen what characterizes the physical continuum. Each
of the elements of this continuum consists of a manifold of impressions;
and it may happen either that an element can not be discriminated from
another element of the same continuum, if this new element corresponds
to a manifold of impressions not sufficiently different, or, on the
contrary, that the discrimination is possible; finally it may happen
that two elements indistinguishable from a third may, nevertheless, be
distinguished one from the other.

That postulated, if _A_ and _B_ are two distinguishable elements of a
continuum _C_, a series of elements may be found, E_{1}, E_{2}, ...,
E_{_n_}, all belonging to this same continuum _C_ and such that
each of them is indistinguishable from the preceding, that E_{1} is
indistinguishable from _A_, and E_{_n_} indistinguishable from _B_.
Therefore we can go from _A_ to _B_ by a continuous route and without
quitting _C_. If this condition is fulfilled for any two elements _A_
and _B_ of the continuum _C_, we may say that this continuum _C_ is all
in one piece. Now let us distinguish certain of the elements of _C_
which may either be all distinguishable from one another, or themselves
form one or several continua. The assemblage of the elements thus chosen
arbitrarily among all those of _C_ will form what I shall call the _cut_
or the _cuts_.

Take on _C_ any two elements _A_ and _B_. Either we can also find a
series of elements E_{1}, E_{2}, ..., E_{_n_}, such: (1) that they all
belong to _C_; (2) that each of them is indistinguishable from the
following, E_{1} indistinguishable from _A_ and E_{_n_} from _B_; (3)
_and besides that none of the elements _E_ is indistinguishable from any
element of the cut_. Or else, on the contrary, in each of the series
E_{1}, E_{2}, ..., E_{_n_} satisfying the first two conditions, there
will be an element _E_ indistinguishable from one of the elements of the
cut. In the first case we can go from _A_ to _B_ by a continuous route
without quitting _C_ and _without meeting the cuts_; in the second case
that is impossible.

If then for any two elements _A_ and _B_ of the continuum _C_, it is
always the first case which presents itself, we shall say that _C_
remains all in one piece despite the cuts.

Thus, if we choose the cuts in a certain way, otherwise arbitrary, it
may happen either that the continuum remains all in one piece or that it
does not remain all in one piece; in this latter hypothesis we shall
then say that it is _divided_ by the cuts.

It will be noticed that all these definitions are constructed in setting
out solely from this very simple fact, that two manifolds of impressions
sometimes can be discriminated, sometimes can not be. That postulated,
if, to _divide_ a continuum, it suffices to consider as cuts a certain
number of elements all distinguishable from one another, we say that
this continuum _is of one dimension_; if, on the contrary, to divide a
continuum, it is necessary to consider as cuts a system of elements
themselves forming one or several continua, we shall say that this
continuum is _of several dimensions_.

If to divide a continuum _C_, cuts forming one or several continua of
one dimension suffice, we shall say that _C_ is a continuum _of two
dimensions_; if cuts suffice which form one or several continua of two
dimensions at most, we shall say that _C_ is a continuum _of three
dimensions_; and so on.

To justify this definition it is proper to see whether it is in this way
that geometers introduce the notion of three dimensions at the beginning
of their works. Now, what do we see? Usually they begin by defining
surfaces as the boundaries of solids or pieces of space, lines as the
boundaries of surfaces, points as the boundaries of lines, and they
affirm that the same procedure can not be pushed further.

This is just the idea given above: to divide space, cuts that are called
surfaces are necessary; to divide surfaces, cuts that are called lines
are necessary; to divide lines, cuts that are called points are
necessary; we can go no further, the point can not be divided, so the
point is not a continuum. Then lines which can be divided by cuts which
are not continua will be continua of one dimension; surfaces which can
be divided by continuous cuts of one dimension will be continua of two
dimensions; finally, space which can be divided by continuous cuts of
two dimensions will be a continuum of three dimensions.

Thus the definition I have just given does not differ essentially from
the usual definitions; I have only endeavored to give it a form
applicable not to the mathematical continuum, but to the physical
continuum, which alone is susceptible of representation, and yet to
retain all its precision. Moreover, we see that this definition applies
not alone to space; that in all which falls under our senses we find the
characteristics of the physical continuum, which would allow of the same
classification; that it would be easy to find there examples of continua
of four, of five, dimensions, in the sense of the preceding definition;
such examples occur of themselves to the mind.

I should explain finally, if I had the time, that this science, of which
I spoke above and to which Riemann gave the name of analysis situs,
teaches us to make distinctions among continua of the same number of
dimensions and that the classification of these continua rests also on
the consideration of cuts.

From this notion has arisen that of the mathematical continuum of
several dimensions in the same way that the physical continuum of one
dimension engendered the mathematical continuum of one dimension. The
formula

  _A_ > _C_,   _A_ = _B_,   _B_ = _C_,

which summed up the data of crude experience, implied an intolerable
contradiction. To get free from it, it was necessary to introduce a new
notion while still respecting the essential characteristics of the
physical continuum of several dimensions. The mathematical continuum of
one dimension admitted of a scale whose divisions, infinite in number,
corresponded to the different values, commensurable or not, of one same
magnitude. To have the mathematical continuum of _n_ dimensions, it will
suffice to take _n_ like scales whose divisions correspond to different
values of _n_ independent magnitudes called coordinates. We thus shall
have an image of the physical continuum of _n_ dimensions, and this
image will be as faithful as it can be after the determination not to
allow the contradiction of which I spoke above.


4. _The Notion of Point_

It seems now that the question we put to ourselves at the start is
answered. When we say that space has three dimensions, it will be said,
we mean that the manifold of points of space satisfies the definition we
have just given of the physical continuum of three dimensions. To be
content with that would be to suppose that we know what is the manifold
of points of space, or even one point of space.

Now that is not as simple as one might think. Every one believes he
knows what a point is, and it is just because we know it too well that
we think there is no need of defining it. Surely we can not be required
to know how to define it, because in going back from definition to
definition a time must come when we must stop. But at what moment should
we stop?

We shall stop first when we reach an object which falls under our senses
or that we can represent to ourselves; definition then will become
useless; we do not define the sheep to a child; we say to him: _See_ the
sheep.

So, then, we should ask ourselves if it is possible to represent to
ourselves a point of space. Those who answer yes do not reflect that
they represent to themselves in reality a white spot made with the chalk
on a blackboard or a black spot made with a pen on white paper, and that
they can represent to themselves only an object or rather the
impressions that this object made on their senses.

When they try to represent to themselves a point, they represent the
impressions that very little objects made them feel. It is needless to
add that two different objects, though both very little, may produce
extremely different impressions, but I shall not dwell on this
difficulty, which would still require some discussion.

But it is not a question of that; it does not suffice to represent _one_
point, it is necessary to represent _a certain_ point and to have the
means of distinguishing it from an _other_ point. And in fact, that we
may be able to apply to a continuum the rule I have above expounded and
by which one may recognize the number of its dimensions, we must rely
upon the fact that two elements of this continuum sometimes can and
sometimes can not be distinguished. It is necessary therefore that we
should in certain cases know how to represent to ourselves _a specific_
element and to distinguish it from an _other_ element.

The question is to know whether the point that I represented to myself
an hour ago is the same as this that I now represent to myself, or
whether it is a different point. In other words, how do we know whether
the point occupied by the object _A_ at the instant [alpha] is the same
as the point occupied by the object _B_ at the instant [beta], or still
better, what this means?

I am seated in my room; an object is placed on my table; during a second
I do not move, no one touches the object. I am tempted to say that the
point _A_ which this object occupied at the beginning of this second is
identical with the point _B_ which it occupies at its end. Not at all;
from the point _A_ to the point _B_ is 30 kilometers, because the object
has been carried along in the motion of the earth. We can not know
whether an object, be it large or small, has not changed its absolute
position in space, and not only can we not affirm it, but this
affirmation has no meaning and in any case can not correspond to any
representation.

But then we may ask ourselves if the relative position of an object with
regard to other objects has changed or not, and first whether the
relative position of this object with regard to our body has changed. If
the impressions this object makes upon us have not changed, we shall be
inclined to judge that neither has this relative position changed; if
they have changed, we shall judge that this object has changed either in
state or in relative position. It remains to decide which of the _two_.
I have explained in 'Science and Hypothesis' how we have been led to
distinguish the changes of position. Moreover, I shall return to that
further on. We come to know, therefore, whether the relative position of
an object with regard to our body has or has not remained the same.

If now we see that two objects have retained their relative position
with regard to our body, we conclude that the relative position of these
two objects with regard to one another has not changed; but we reach
this conclusion only by indirect reasoning. The only thing that we know
directly is the relative position of the objects with regard to our
body. _A fortiori_ it is only by indirect reasoning that we think we
know (and, moreover, this belief is delusive) whether the absolute
position of the object has changed.

In a word, the system of coordinate axes to which we naturally refer all
exterior objects is a system of axes invariably bound to our body, and
carried around with us.

It is impossible to represent to oneself absolute space; when I try to
represent to myself simultaneously objects and myself in motion in
absolute space, in reality I represent to myself my own self motionless
and seeing move around me different objects and a man that is exterior
to me, but that I convene to call me.

Will the difficulty be solved if we agree to refer everything to these
axes bound to our body? Shall we know then what is a point thus defined
by its relative position with regard to ourselves? Many persons will
answer yes and will say that they 'localize' exterior objects.

What does this mean? To localize an object simply means to represent to
oneself the movements that would be necessary to reach it. I will
explain myself. It is not a question of representing the movements
themselves in space, but solely of representing to oneself the muscular
sensations which accompany these movements and which do not presuppose
the preexistence of the notion of space.

If we suppose two different objects which successively occupy the same
relative position with regard to ourselves, the impressions that these
two objects make upon us will be very different; if we localize them at
the same point, this is simply because it is necessary to make the same
movements to reach them; apart from that, one can not just see what they
could have in common.

But, given an object, we can conceive many different series of movements
which equally enable us to reach it. If then we represent to ourselves a
point by representing to ourselves the series of muscular sensations
which accompany the movements which enable us to reach this point, there
will be many ways entirely different of representing to oneself the same
point. If one is not satisfied with this solution, but wishes, for
instance, to bring in the visual sensations along with the muscular
sensations, there will be one or two more ways of representing to
oneself this same point and the difficulty will only be increased. In
any case the following question comes up: Why do we think that all these
representations so different from one another still represent the same
point?

Another remark: I have just said that it is to our own body that we
naturally refer exterior objects; that we carry about everywhere with us
a system of axes to which we refer all the points of space and that this
system of axes seems to be invariably bound to our body. It should be
noticed that rigorously we could not speak of axes invariably bound to
the body unless the different parts of this body were themselves
invariably bound to one another. As this is not the case, we ought,
before referring exterior objects to these fictitious axes, to suppose
our body brought back to the initial attitude.


5. _The Notion of Displacement_

I have shown in 'Science and Hypothesis' the preponderant rôle played by
the movements of our body in the genesis of the notion of space. For a
being completely immovable there would be neither space nor geometry; in
vain would exterior objects be displaced about him, the variations which
these displacements would make in his impressions would not be
attributed by this being to changes of position, but to simple changes
of state; this being would have no means of distinguishing these two
sorts of changes, and this distinction, fundamental for us, would have
no meaning for him.

The movements that we impress upon our members have as effect the
varying of the impressions produced on our senses by external objects;
other causes may likewise make them vary; but we are led to distinguish
the changes produced by our own motions and we easily discriminate them
for two reasons: (1) because they are voluntary; (2) because they are
accompanied by muscular sensations.

So we naturally divide the changes that our impressions may undergo into
two categories to which perhaps I have given an inappropriate
designation: (1) the internal changes, which are voluntary and
accompanied by muscular sensations; (2) the external changes, having the
opposite characteristics.

We then observe that among the external changes are some which can be
corrected, thanks to an internal change which brings everything back to
the primitive state; others can not be corrected in this way (it is thus
that, when an exterior object is displaced, we may then by changing our
own position replace ourselves as regards this object in the same
relative position as before, so as to reestablish the original aggregate
of impressions; if this object was not displaced, but changed its state,
that is impossible). Thence comes a new distinction among external
changes: those which may be so corrected we call changes of position;
and the others, changes of state.

Think, for example, of a sphere with one hemisphere blue and the other
red; it first presents to us the blue hemisphere, then it so revolves as
to present the red hemisphere. Now think of a spherical vase containing
a blue liquid which becomes red in consequence of a chemical reaction.
In both cases the sensation of red has replaced that of blue; our senses
have experienced the same impressions which have succeeded each other in
the same order, and yet these two changes are regarded by us as very
different; the first is a displacement, the second a change of state.
Why? Because in the first case it is sufficient for me to go around the
sphere to place myself opposite the blue hemisphere and reestablish the
original blue sensation.

Still more; if the two hemispheres, in place of being red and blue, had
been yellow and green, how should I have interpreted the revolution of
the sphere? Before, the red succeeded the blue, now the green succeeds
the yellow; and yet I say that the two spheres have undergone the same
revolution, that each has turned about its axis; yet I can not say that
the green is to yellow as the red is to blue; how then am I led to
decide that the two spheres have undergone the _same_ displacement?
Evidently because, in one case as in the other, I am able to reestablish
the original sensation by going around the sphere, by making the same
movements, and I know that I have made the same movements because I have
felt the same muscular sensations; to know it, I do not need, therefore,
to know geometry in advance and to represent to myself the movements of
my body in geometric space.

Another example: An object is displaced before my eye; its image was
first formed at the center of the retina; then it is formed at the
border; the old sensation was carried to me by a nerve fiber ending at
the center of the retina; the new sensation is carried to me by
_another_ nerve fiber starting from the border of the retina; these two
sensations are qualitatively different; otherwise, how could I
distinguish them?

Why then am I led to decide that these two sensations, qualitatively
different, represent the same image, which has been displaced? It is
because I _can follow the object with the eye_ and by a displacement of
the eye, voluntary and accompanied by muscular sensations, bring back
the image to the center of the retina and reestablish the primitive
sensation.

I suppose that the image of a red object has gone from the center _A_ to
the border _B_ of the retina, then that the image of a blue object goes
in its turn from the center _A_ to the border _B_ of the retina; I shall
decide that these two objects have undergone the _same_ displacement.
Why? Because in both cases I shall have been able to reestablish the
primitive sensation, and that to do it I shall have had to execute the
_same_ movement of the eye, and I shall know that my eye has executed
the same movement because I shall have felt the _same_ muscular
sensations.

If I could not move my eye, should I have any reason to suppose that the
sensation of red at the center of the retina is to the sensation of red
at the border of the retina as that of blue at the center is to that of
blue at the border? I should only have four sensations qualitatively
different, and if I were asked if they are connected by the proportion I
have just stated, the question would seem to me ridiculous, just as if I
were asked if there is an analogous proportion between an auditory
sensation, a tactile sensation and an olfactory sensation.

Let us now consider the internal changes, that is, those which are
produced by the voluntary movements of our body and which are
accompanied by muscular changes. They give rise to the two following
observations, analogous to those we have just made on the subject of
external changes.

1. I may suppose that my body has moved from one point to another, but
that the same _attitude_ is retained; all the parts of the body have
therefore retained or resumed the same _relative_ situation, although
their absolute situation in space may have varied. I may suppose that
not only has the position of my body changed, but that its attitude is
no longer the same, that, for instance, my arms which before were folded
are now stretched out.

I should therefore distinguish the simple changes of position without
change of attitude, and the changes of attitude. Both would appear to me
under form of muscular sensations. How then am I led to distinguish
them? It is that the first may serve to correct an external change, and
that the others can not, or at least can only give an imperfect
correction.

This fact I proceed to explain as I would explain it to some one who
already knew geometry, but it need not thence be concluded that it is
necessary already to know geometry to make this distinction; before
knowing geometry I ascertain the fact (experimentally, so to speak),
without being able to explain it. But merely to make the distinction
between the two kinds of change, I do not need to _explain_ the fact, it
suffices me _to ascertain_ it.

However that may be, the explanation is easy. Suppose that an exterior
object is displaced; if we wish the different parts of our body to
resume with regard to this object their initial relative position, it is
necessary that these different parts should have resumed likewise their
initial relative position with regard to one another. Only the internal
changes which satisfy this latter condition will be capable of
correcting the external change produced by the displacement of that
object. If, therefore, the relative position of my eye with regard to my
finger has changed, I shall still be able to replace the eye in its
initial relative situation with regard to the object and reestablish
thus the primitive visual sensations, but then the relative position of
the finger with regard to the object will have changed and the tactile
sensations will not be reestablished.

2. We ascertain likewise that the same external change may be corrected
by two internal changes corresponding to different muscular sensations.
Here again I can ascertain this without knowing geometry; and I have no
need of anything else; but I proceed to give the explanation of the
fact, employing geometrical language. To go from the position _A_ to the
position _B_ I may take several routes. To the first of these routes
will correspond a series _S_ of muscular sensations; to a second route
will correspond another series _S''_, of muscular sensations which
generally will be completely different, since other muscles will be
used.

How am I led to regard these two series _S_ and _S''_ as corresponding
to the same displacement _AB_? It is because these two series are
capable of correcting the same external change. Apart from that, they
have nothing in common.

Let us now consider two external changes: [alpha] and [beta], which
shall be, for instance, the rotation of a sphere half blue, half red,
and that of a sphere half yellow, half green; these two changes have
nothing in common, since the one is for us the passing of blue into red
and the other the passing of yellow into green. Consider, on the other
hand, two series of internal changes _S_ and _S''_; like the others,
they will have nothing in common. And yet I say that [alpha] and [beta]
correspond to the same displacement, and that _S_ and _S''_ correspond
also to the same displacement. Why? Simply because _S_ can correct
[alpha] as well as [beta] and because [alpha] can be corrected by _S''_
as well as by _S_. And then a question suggests itself:

If I have ascertained that _S_ corrects [alpha] and [beta] and that
_S''_ corrects [alpha], am I certain that _S''_ likewise corrects
[beta]? Experiment alone can teach us whether this law is verified. If
it were not verified, at least approximately, there would be no
geometry, there would be no space, because we should have no more
interest in classifying the internal and external changes as I have just
done, and, for instance, in distinguishing changes of state from changes
of position.

It is interesting to see what has been the rôle of experience in all
this. It has shown me that a certain law is approximately verified. It
has not told me _how_ space is, and that it satisfies the condition in
question. I knew, in fact, before all experience, that space satisfied
this condition or that it would not be; nor have I any right to say that
experience told me that geometry is possible; I very well see that
geometry is possible, since it does not imply contradiction; experience
only tells me that geometry is useful.


6. _Visual Space_

Although motor impressions have had, as I have just explained, an
altogether preponderant influence in the genesis of the notion of space,
which never would have taken birth without them, it will not be without
interest to examine also the rôle of visual impressions and to
investigate how many dimensions 'visual space' has, and for that purpose
to apply to these impressions the definition of § 3.

A first difficulty presents itself: consider a red color sensation
affecting a certain point of the retina; and on the other hand a blue
color sensation affecting the same point of the retina. It is necessary
that we have some means of recognizing that these two sensations,
qualitatively different, have something in common. Now, according to the
considerations expounded in the preceding paragraph, we have been able
to recognize this only by the movements of the eye and the observations
to which they have given rise. If the eye were immovable, or if we were
unconscious of its movements, we should not have been able to recognize
that these two sensations, of different quality, had something in
common; we should not have been able to disengage from them what gives
them a geometric character. The visual sensations, without the muscular
sensations, would have nothing geometric, so that it may be said there
is no pure visual space.

To do away with this difficulty, consider only sensations of the same
nature, red sensations, for instance, differing one from another only as
regards the point of the retina that they affect. It is clear that I
have no reason for making such an arbitrary choice among all the
possible visual sensations, for the purpose of uniting in the same class
all the sensations of the same color, whatever may be the point of the
retina affected. I should never have dreamt of it, had I not before
learned, by the means we have just seen, to distinguish changes of state
from changes of position, that is, if my eye were immovable. Two
sensations of the same color affecting two different parts of the retina
would have appeared to me as qualitatively distinct, just as two
sensations of different color.

In restricting myself to red sensations, I therefore impose upon myself
an artificial limitation and I neglect systematically one whole side of
the question; but it is only by this artifice that I am able to analyze
visual space without mingling any motor sensation.

Imagine a line traced on the retina and dividing in two its surface; and
set apart the red sensations affecting a point of this line, or those
differing from them too little to be distinguished from them. The
aggregate of these sensations will form a sort of cut that I shall call
_C_, and it is clear that this cut suffices to divide the manifold of
possible red sensations, and that if I take two red sensations affecting
two points situated on one side and the other of the line, I can not
pass from one of these sensations to the other in a continuous way
without passing at a certain moment through a sensation belonging to the
cut.

If, therefore, the cut has _n_ dimensions, the total manifold of my red
sensations, or if you wish, the whole visual space, will have _n_ + 1.

Now, I distinguish the red sensations affecting a point of the cut _C_.
The assemblage of these sensations will form a new cut _C'_. It is clear
that this will divide the cut _C_, always giving to the word divide the
same meaning.

If, therefore, the cut _C'_ has _n_ dimensions, the cut _C_ will have
_n_ + 1 and the whole of visual space _n_ + 2.

If all the red sensations affecting the same point of the retina were
regarded as identical, the cut _C'_ reducing to a single element would
have 0 dimensions, and visual space would have 2.

And yet most often it is said that the eye gives us the sense of a third
dimension, and enables us in a certain measure to recognize the distance
of objects. When we seek to analyze this feeling, we ascertain that it
reduces either to the consciousness of the convergence of the eyes, or
to that of the effort of accommodation which the ciliary muscle makes to
focus the image.

Two red sensations affecting the same point of the retina will therefore
be regarded as identical only if they are accompanied by the same
sensation of convergence and also by the same sensation of effort of
accommodation or at least by sensations of convergence and accommodation
so slightly different as to be indistinguishable.

On this account the cut _C'_ is itself a continuum and the cut _C_ has
more than one dimension.

But it happens precisely that experience teaches us that when two visual
sensations are accompanied by the same sensation of convergence, they
are likewise accompanied by the same sensation of accommodation. If then
we form a new cut _C''_ with all those of the sensations of the cut
_C'_, which are accompanied by a certain sensation of convergence, in
accordance with the preceding law they will all be indistinguishable and
may be regarded as identical. Therefore _C''_ will not be a continuum
and will have 0 dimension; and as _C''_ divides _C'_ it will thence
result that _C'_ has one, _C_ two and _the whole visual space three
dimensions_.

But would it be the same if experience had taught us the contrary and if
a certain sensation of convergence were not always accompanied by the
same sensation of accommodation? In this case two sensations affecting
the same point of the retina and accompanied by the same sense of
convergence, two sensations which consequently would both appertain to
the cut _C''_, could nevertheless be distinguished since they would be
accompanied by two different sensations of accommodation. Therefore
_C''_ would be in its turn a continuum and would have one dimension (at
least); then _C'_ would have two, _C_ three and _the whole visual space
would have four dimensions_.

Will it then be said that it is experience which teaches us that space
has three dimensions, since it is in setting out from an experimental
law that we have come to attribute three to it? But we have therein
performed, so to speak, only an experiment in physiology; and as also it
would suffice to fit over the eyes glasses of suitable construction to
put an end to the accord between the feelings of convergence and of
accommodation, are we to say that putting on spectacles is enough to
make space have four dimensions and that the optician who constructed
them has given one more dimension to space? Evidently not; all we can
say is that experience has taught us that it is convenient to attribute
three dimensions to space.

But visual space is only one part of space, and in even the notion of
this space there is something artificial, as I have explained at the
beginning. The real space is motor space and this it is that we shall
examine in the following chapter.



CHAPTER IV

SPACE AND ITS THREE DIMENSIONS


1. _The Group of Displacements_

Let us sum up briefly the results obtained. We proposed to investigate
what was meant in saying that space has three dimensions and we have
asked first what is a physical continuum and when it may be said to have
_n_ dimensions. If we consider different systems of impressions and
compare them with one another, we often recognize that two of these
systems of impressions are indistinguishable (which is ordinarily
expressed in saying that they are too close to one another, and that our
senses are too crude, for us to distinguish them) and we ascertain
besides that two of these systems can sometimes be discriminated from
one another though indistinguishable from a third system. In that case
we say the manifold of these systems of impressions forms a physical
continuum _C_. And each of these systems is called an _element_ of the
continuum _C_.

How many dimensions has this continuum? Take first two elements _A_ and
_B_ of _C_, and suppose there exists a series [Sigma] of elements, all
belonging to the continuum _C_, of such a sort that _A_ and _B_ are the
two extreme terms of this series and that each term of the series is
indistinguishable from the preceding. If such a series [Sigma] can be
found, we say that _A_ and _B_ are joined to one another; and if any two
elements of _C_ are joined to one another, we say that _C_ is all of one
piece.

Now take on the continuum _C_ a certain number of elements in a way
altogether arbitrary. The aggregate of these elements will be called a
_cut_. Among the various series [Sigma] which join _A_ to _B_, we shall
distinguish those of which an element is indistinguishable from one of
the elements of the cut (we shall say that these are they which _cut_
the cut) and those of which _all_ the elements are distinguishable from
all those of the cut. If _all_ the series [Sigma] which join _A_ to _B_
cut the cut, we shall say that _A_ and _B_ are _separated_ by the cut,
and that the cut _divides_ _C_. If we can not find on _C_ two elements
which are separated by the cut, we shall say that the cut _does not
divide_ _C_.

These definitions laid down, if the continuum _C_ can be divided by cuts
which do not themselves form a continuum, this continuum _C_ has only
one dimension; in the contrary case it has several. If a cut forming a
continuum of 1 dimension suffices to divide _C_, _C_ will have 2
dimensions; if a cut forming a continuum of 2 dimensions suffices, _C_
will have 3 dimensions, etc. Thanks to these definitions, we can always
recognize how many dimensions any physical continuum has. It only
remains to find a physical continuum which is, so to speak, equivalent
to space, of such a sort that to every point of space corresponds an
element of this continuum, and that to points of space very near one
another correspond indistinguishable elements. Space will have then as
many dimensions as this continuum.

The intermediation of this physical continuum, capable of
representation, is indispensable; because we can not represent space to
ourselves, and that for a multitude of reasons. Space is a mathematical
continuum, it is infinite, and we can represent to ourselves only
physical continua and finite objects. The different elements of space,
which we call points, are all alike, and, to apply our definition, it is
necessary that we know how to distinguish the elements from one another,
at least if they are not too close. Finally absolute space is nonsense,
and it is necessary for us to begin by referring space to a system of
axes invariably bound to our body (which we must always suppose put back
in the initial attitude).

Then I have sought to form with our visual sensations a physical
continuum equivalent to space; that certainly is easy and this example
is particularly appropriate for the discussion of the number of
dimensions; this discussion has enabled us to see in what measure it is
allowable to say that 'visual space' has three dimensions. Only this
solution is incomplete and artificial. I have explained why, and it is
not on visual space but on motor space that it is necessary to bring our
efforts to bear. I have then recalled what is the origin of the
distinction we make between changes of position and changes of state.
Among the changes which occur in our impressions, we distinguish, first
the _internal_ changes, voluntary and accompanied by muscular
sensations, and the _external_ changes, having opposite characteristics.
We ascertain that it may happen that an external change may be
_corrected_ by an internal change which reestablishes the primitive
sensations. The external changes, capable of being corrected by an
internal change are called _changes of position_, those not capable of
it are called _changes of state_. The internal changes capable of
correcting an external change are called _displacements of the whole
body_; the others are called _changes of attitude_.

Now let [alpha] and [beta] be two external changes, [alpha]' and [beta]'
two internal changes. Suppose that a may be corrected either by [alpha]'
or by [beta]', and that [alpha]' can correct either [alpha] or [beta];
experience tells us then that [beta]' can likewise correct [beta]. In
this case we say that [alpha] and [beta] correspond to the _same_
displacement and also that [alpha]' and [beta]' correspond to the _same_
displacement. That postulated, we can imagine a physical continuum which
we shall call _the continuum or group of displacements_ and which we
shall define in the following manner. The elements of this continuum
shall be the internal changes capable of correcting an external change.
Two of these internal changes [alpha]' and [beta]' shall be regarded as
indistinguishable: (1) if they are so naturally, that is, if they are
too close to one another; (2) if [alpha]' is capable of correcting the
same external change as a third internal change naturally
indistinguishable from [beta]'. In this second case, they will be, so to
speak, indistinguishable by convention, I mean by agreeing to disregard
circumstances which might distinguish them.

Our continuum is now entirely defined, since we know its elements and
have fixed under what conditions they may be regarded as
indistinguishable. We thus have all that is necessary to apply our
definition and determine how many dimensions this continuum has. We
shall recognize that it has _six_. The continuum of displacements is,
therefore, not equivalent to space, since the number of dimensions is
not the same; it is only related to space. Now how do we know that this
continuum of displacements has six dimensions? We know it _by
experience_.

It would be easy to describe the experiments by which we could arrive
at this result. It would be seen that in this continuum cuts can be made
which divide it and which are continua; that these cuts themselves can
be divided by other cuts of the second order which yet are continua, and
that this would stop only after cuts of the sixth order which would no
longer be continua. From our definitions that would mean that the group
of displacements has six dimensions.

That would be easy, I have said, but that would be rather long; and
would it not be a little superficial? This group of displacements, we
have seen, is related to space, and space could be deduced from it, but
it is not equivalent to space, since it has not the same number of
dimensions; and when we shall have shown how the notion of this
continuum can be formed and how that of space may be deduced from it, it
might always be asked why space of three dimensions is much more
familiar to us than this continuum of six dimensions, and consequently
doubted whether it was by this detour that the notion of space was
formed in the human mind.


2. _Identity of Two Points_

What is a point? How do we know whether two points of space are
identical or different? Or, in other words, when I say: The object _A_
occupied at the instant [alpha] the point which the object _B_ occupies
at the instant [beta], what does that mean?

Such is the problem we set ourselves in the preceding chapter, §4. As I
have explained it, it is not a question of comparing the positions of
the objects _A_ and _B_ in absolute space; the question then would
manifestly have no meaning. It is a question of comparing the positions
of these two objects with regard to axes invariably bound to my body,
supposing always this body replaced in the same attitude.

I suppose that between the instants [alpha] and [beta] I have moved
neither my body nor my eye, as I know from my muscular sense. Nor have I
moved either my head, my arm or my hand. I ascertain that at the instant
[alpha] impressions that I attributed to the object _A_ were transmitted
to me, some by one of the fibers of my optic nerve, the others by one of
the sensitive tactile nerves of my finger; I ascertain that at the
instant [beta] other impressions which I attribute to the object _B_ are
transmitted to me, some by this same fiber of the optic nerve, the
others by this same tactile nerve.

Here I must pause for an explanation; how am I told that this impression
which I attribute to _A_, and that which I attribute to _B_, impressions
which are qualitatively different, are transmitted to me by the same
nerve? Must we suppose, to take for example the visual sensations, that
_A_ produces two simultaneous sensations, a sensation purely luminous
_a_ and a colored sensation _a'_, that _B_ produces in the same way
simultaneously a luminous sensation _b_ and a colored sensation _b'_,
that if these different sensations are transmitted to me by the same
retinal fiber, _a_ is identical with _b_, but that in general the
colored sensations _a'_ and _b'_ produced by different bodies are
different? In that case it would be the identity of the sensation _a_
which accompanies _a'_ with the sensation _b_ which accompanies _b'_,
which would tell that all these sensations are transmitted to me by the
same fiber.

However it may be with this hypothesis and although I am led to prefer
to it others considerably more complicated, it is certain that we are
told in some way that there is something in common between these
sensations _a_ + _a'_ and _b_ +_b'_, without which we should have no
means of recognizing that the object _B_ has taken the place of the
object _A_.

Therefore I do not further insist and I recall the hypothesis I have
just made: I suppose that I have ascertained that the impressions which
I attribute to _B_ are transmitted to me at the instant [beta] by the
same fibers, optic as well as tactile, which, at the instant [alpha],
had transmitted to me the impressions that I attributed to _A_. If it is
so, we shall not hesitate to declare that the point occupied by _B_ at
the instant [beta] is identical with the point occupied by _A_ at the
instant [alpha].

I have just enunciated two conditions for these points being identical;
one is relative to sight, the other to touch. Let us consider them
separately. The first is necessary, but is not sufficient. The second is
at once necessary and sufficient. A person knowing geometry could easily
explain this in the following manner: Let _O_ be the point of the retina
where is formed at the instant [alpha] the image of the body _A_; let
_M_ be the point of space occupied at the instant [alpha] by this body
_A_; let _M'_ be the point of space occupied at the instant [beta] by
the body _B_. For this body _B_ to form its image in _O_, it is not
necessary that the points _M_ and _M'_ coincide; since vision acts at a
distance, it suffices for the three points _O_ _M_ _M'_ to be in a
straight line. This condition that the two objects form their image on
_O_ is therefore necessary, but not sufficient for the points _M_ and
_M'_ to coincide. Let now _P_ be the point occupied by my finger and
where it remains, since it does not budge. As touch does not act at a
distance, if the body _A_ touches my finger at the instant [alpha], it
is because _M_ and _P_ coincide; if _B_ touches my finger at the instant
[beta], it is because _M'_ and _P_ coincide. Therefore _M_ and _M'_
coincide. Thus this condition that if _A_ touches my finger at the
instant [alpha], _B_ touches it at the instant [beta], is at once
necessary and sufficient for _M_ and _M'_ to coincide.

But we who, as yet, do not know geometry can not reason thus; all that
we can do is to ascertain experimentally that the first condition
relative to sight may be fulfilled without the second, which is relative
to touch, but that the second can not be fulfilled without the first.

Suppose experience had taught us the contrary, as might well be; this
hypothesis contains nothing absurd. Suppose, therefore, that we had
ascertained experimentally that the condition relative to touch may be
fulfilled without that of sight being fulfilled and that, on the
contrary, that of sight can not be fulfilled without that of touch being
also. It is clear that if this were so we should conclude that it is
touch which may be exercised at a distance, and that sight does not
operate at a distance.

But this is not all; up to this time I have supposed that to determine
the place of an object I have made use only of my eye and a single
finger; but I could just as well have employed other means, for example,
all my other fingers.

I suppose that my first finger receives at the instant [alpha] a tactile
impression which I attribute to the object _A_. I make a series of
movements, corresponding to a series _S_ of muscular sensations. After
these movements, at the instant [alpha]', my _second_ finger receives a
tactile impression that I attribute likewise to _A_. Afterward, at the
instant [beta], without my having budged, as my muscular sense tells me,
this same second finger transmits to me anew a tactile impression which
I attribute this time to the object _B_; I then make a series of
movements, corresponding to a series _S'_ of muscular sensations. I know
that this series _S'_ is the inverse of the series _S_ and corresponds
to contrary movements. I know this because many previous experiences
have shown me that if I made successively the two series of movements
corresponding to _S_ and to _S'_, the primitive impressions would be
reestablished, in other words, that the two series mutually compensate.
That settled, should I expect that at the instant [beta]', when the
second series of movements is ended, my _first finger_ would feel a
tactile impression attributable to the object _B_?

To answer this question, those already knowing geometry would reason as
follows: There are chances that the object _A_ has not budged, between
the instants [alpha] and [alpha]', nor the object _B_ between the
instants [beta] and [beta]'; assume this. At the instant [alpha], the
object _A_ occupied a certain point _M_ of space. Now at this instant it
touched my first finger, and _as touch does not operate at a distance_,
my first finger was likewise at the point _M_. I afterward made the
series _S_ of movements and at the end of this series, at the instant
[alpha]', I ascertained that the object _A_ touched my second finger. I
thence conclude that this second finger was then at _M_, that is, that
the movements _S_ had the result of bringing the second finger to the
place of the first. At the instant [beta] the object _B_ has come in
contact with my second finger: as I have not budged, this second finger
has remained at _M_; therefore the object _B_ has come to _M_; by
hypothesis it does not budge up to the instant [beta]'. But between the
instants [beta] and [beta]' I have made the movements _S'_; as these
movements are the inverse of the movements _S_, they must have for
effect bringing the first finger in the place of the second. At the
instant [beta]' this first finger will, therefore, be at _M_; and as the
object _B_ is likewise at _M_, this object _B_ will touch my first
finger. To the question put, the answer should therefore be yes.

We who do not yet know geometry can not reason thus; but we ascertain
that this anticipation is ordinarily realized; and we can always explain
the exceptions by saying that the object _A_ has moved between the
instants [alpha] and [alpha]', or the object _B_ between the instants
[beta] and [beta]'.

But could not experience have given a contrary result? Would this
contrary result have been absurd in itself? Evidently not. What should
we have done then if experience had given this contrary result? Would
all geometry thus have become impossible? Not the least in the world. We
should have contented ourselves with concluding _that touch can operate
at a distance_.

When I say, touch does not operate at a distance, but sight operates at
a distance, this assertion has only one meaning, which is as follows: To
recognize whether _B_ occupies at the instant [beta] the point occupied
by _A_ at the instant [alpha], I can use a multitude of different
criteria. In one my eye intervenes, in another my first finger, in
another my second finger, etc. Well, it is sufficient for the criterion
relative to one of my fingers to be satisfied in order that all the
others should be satisfied, but it is not sufficient that the criterion
relative to the eye should be. This is the sense of my assertion. I
content myself with affirming an experimental fact which is ordinarily
verified.

At the end of the preceding chapter we analyzed visual space; we saw
that to engender this space it is necessary to bring in the retinal
sensations, the sensation of convergence and the sensation of
accommodation; that if these last two were not always in accord, visual
space would have four dimensions in place of three; we also saw that if
we brought in only the retinal sensations, we should obtain 'simple
visual space,' of only two dimensions. On the other hand, consider
tactile space, limiting ourselves to the sensations of a single finger,
that is in sum to the assemblage of positions this finger can occupy.
This tactile space that we shall analyze in the following section and
which consequently I ask permission not to consider further for the
moment, this tactile space, I say, has three dimensions. Why has space
properly so called as many dimensions as tactile space and more than
simple visual space? It is because touch does not operate at a distance,
while vision does operate at a distance. These two assertions have the
same meaning and we have just seen what this is.

Now I return to a point over which I passed rapidly in order not to
interrupt the discussion. How do we know that the impressions made on
our retina by _A_ at the instant [alpha] and _B_ at the instant [beta]
are transmitted by the same retinal fiber, although these impressions
are qualitatively different? I have suggested a simple hypothesis, while
adding that other hypotheses, decidedly more complex, would seem to me
more probably true. Here then are these hypotheses, of which I have
already said a word. How do we know that the impressions produced by the
red object A at the instant [alpha], and by the blue object _B_ at the
instant [beta], if these two objects have been imaged on the same point
of the retina, have something in common? The simple hypothesis above
made may be rejected and we may suppose that these two impressions,
qualitatively different, are transmitted by two different though
contiguous nervous fibers. What means have I then of knowing that these
fibers are contiguous? It is probable that we should have none, if the
eye were immovable. It is the movements of the eye which have told us
that there is the same relation between the sensation of blue at the
point _A_ and the sensation of blue at the point _B_ of the retina as
between the sensation of red at the point _A_ and the sensation of red
at the point _B_. They have shown us, in fact, that the same movements,
corresponding to the same muscular sensations, carry us from the first
to the second, or from the third to the fourth. I do not emphasize these
considerations, which belong, as one sees, to the question of local
signs raised by Lotze.


3. _Tactile Space_

Thus I know how to recognize the identity of two points, the point
occupied by _A_ at the instant [alpha] and the point occupied by _B_ at
the instant [beta], but only _on one condition_, namely, that I have not
budged between the instants [alpha] and [beta]. That does not suffice
for our object. Suppose, therefore, that I have moved in any manner in
the interval between these two instants, how shall I know whether the
point occupied by _A_ at the instant [alpha] is identical with the point
occupied by _B_ at the instant [beta]? I suppose that at the instant
[alpha], the object _A_ was in contact with my first finger and that in
the same way, at the instant [beta], the object _B_ touches this first
finger; but at the same time my muscular sense has told me that in the
interval my body has moved. I have considered above two series of
muscular sensations _S_ and _S'_, and I have said it sometimes happens
that we are led to consider two such series _S_ and _S'_ as inverse one
of the other, because we have often observed that when these two series
succeed one another our primitive impressions are reestablished.

If then my muscular sense tells me that I have moved between the two
instants [alpha] and [beta], but so as to feel successively the two
series of muscular sensations _S_ and _S'_ that I consider inverses, I
shall still conclude, just as if I had not budged, that the points
occupied by _A_ at the instant [alpha] and by _B_ at the instant [beta]
are identical, if I ascertain that my first finger touches _A_ at the
instant [alpha], and _B_ at the instant [beta].

This solution is not yet completely satisfactory, as one will see. Let
us see, in fact, how many dimensions it would make us attribute to
space. I wish to compare the two points occupied by _A_ and _B_ at the
instants [alpha] and [beta], or (what amounts to the same thing since I
suppose that my finger touches _A_ at the instant [alpha] and _B_ at the
instant [beta]) I wish to compare the two points occupied by my finger
at the two instants [alpha] and [beta]. The sole means I use for this
comparison is the series [Sigma] of muscular sensations which have
accompanied the movements of my body between these two instants. The
different imaginable series [Sigma] form evidently a physical continuum
of which the number of dimensions is very great. Let us agree, as I have
done, not to consider as distinct the two series [Sigma] and [Sigma] +
_S_ + _S'_, when _S_ and _S'_ are inverses one of the other in the sense
above given to this word; in spite of this agreement, the aggregate of
distinct series [Sigma] will still form a physical continuum and the
number of dimensions will be less but still very great.

To each of these series [Sigma] corresponds a point of space; to two
series [Sigma] and [Sigma]' thus correspond two points _M_ and _M'_. The
means we have hitherto used enable us to recognize that _M_ and _M'_ are
not distinct in two cases: (1) if [Sigma] is identical with [Sigma]';
(2) if [Sigma]' = [Sigma] + _S_ + _S'_, _S_ and _S'_ being inverses one
of the other. If in all the other cases we should regard _M_ and _M'_ as
distinct, the manifold of points would have as many dimensions as the
aggregate of distinct series [Sigma], that is, much more than three.

For those who already know geometry, the following explanation would be
easily comprehensible. Among the imaginable series of muscular
sensations, there are those which correspond to series of movements
where the finger does not budge. I say that if one does not consider as
distinct the series [Sigma] and [Sigma] + [sigma], where the series
[sigma] corresponds to movements where the finger does not budge, the
aggregate of series will constitute a continuum of three dimensions, but
that if one regards as distinct two series [Sigma] and [Sigma]' unless
[Sigma]' = [Sigma] + _S_ + _S'_, _S_ and _S'_ being inverses, the
aggregate of series will constitute a continuum of more than three
dimensions.

In fact, let there be in space a surface _A_, on this surface a line
_B_, on this line a point _M_. Let C_{0} be the aggregate of all series
[Sigma]. Let C_{1} be the aggregate of all the series [Sigma], such that
at the end of corresponding movements the finger is found upon the
surface _A_, and C_{2} or C_{3} the aggregate of series [Sigma] such
that at the end the finger is found on _B_, or at _M_. It is clear,
first that C_{1} will constitute a cut which will divide C_{0}, that
C_{2} will be a cut which will divide C_{1}, and C_{3} a cut which will
divide C_2. Thence it results, in accordance with our definitions, that
if C_{3} is a continuum of _n_ dimensions, C_{0} will be a physical
continuum of _n_ + 3 dimensions.

Therefore, let [Sigma] and [Sigma]' = [Sigma] + [sigma] be two series
forming part of C_{3}; for both, at the end of the movements, the finger
is found at _M_; thence results that at the beginning and at the end of
the series [sigma] the finger is at the same point _M_. This series
[sigma] is therefore one of those which correspond to movements where
the finger does not budge. If [Sigma] and [Sigma] + [sigma] are not
regarded as distinct, all the series of C_{3} blend into one; therefore
C_{3} will have 0 dimension, and C_{0} will have 3, as I wished to
prove. If, on the contrary, I do not regard [Sigma] and [Sigma] +
[sigma] as blending (unless [sigma] = _S_ + _S'_, _S_ and _S'_ being
inverses), it is clear that C_{3} will contain a great number of series
of distinct sensations; because, without the finger budging, the body
may take a multitude of different attitudes. Then C_{3} will form a
continuum and C_{0} will have more than three dimensions, and this also
I wished to prove.

We who do not yet know geometry can not reason in this way; we can only
verify. But then a question arises; how, before knowing geometry, have
we been led to distinguish from the others these series [sigma] where
the finger does not budge? It is, in fact, only after having made this
distinction that we could be led to regard [Sigma] and [Sigma] + [sigma]
as identical, and it is on this condition alone, as we have just seen,
that we can arrive at space of three dimensions.

We are led to distinguish the series [sigma], because it often happens
that when we have executed the movements which correspond to these
series [sigma] of muscular sensations, the tactile sensations which are
transmitted to us by the nerve of the finger that we have called the
first finger, persist and are not altered by these movements. Experience
alone tells us that and it alone could tell us.

If we have distinguished the series of muscular sensations _S_ + _S'_
formed by the union of two inverse series, it is because they preserve
the totality of our impressions; if now we distinguish the series
[sigma], it is because they preserve _certain_ of our impressions. (When
I say that a series of muscular sensations _S_ 'preserves' one of our
impressions _A_, I mean that we ascertain that if we feel the impression
_A_, then the muscular sensations _S_, we _still_ feel the impression
_A_ _after_ these sensations _S_.)

I have said above it often happens that the series [sigma] do not alter
the tactile impressions felt by our first finger; I said _often_, I did
not say _always_. This it is that we express in our ordinary language by
saying that the tactile impressions would not be altered if the finger
has not moved, _on the condition_ that _neither has_ the object _A_,
which was in contact with this finger, moved. Before knowing geometry,
we could not give this explanation; all we could do is to ascertain that
the impression often persists, but not always.

But that the impression often continues is enough to make the series
[sigma] appear remarkable to us, to lead us to put in the same class the
series [Sigma] and [Sigma] + [sigma], and hence not regard them as
distinct. Under these conditions we have seen that they will engender a
physical continuum of three dimensions.

Behold then a space of three dimensions engendered by my first finger.
Each of my fingers will create one like it. It remains to consider how
we are led to regard them as identical with visual space, as identical
with geometric space.

But one reflection before going further; according to the foregoing, we
know the points of space, or more generally the final situation of our
body, only by the series of muscular sensations revealing to us the
movements which have carried us from a certain initial situation to this
final situation. But it is clear that this final situation will depend,
on the one hand, upon these movements and, _on the other hand, upon the
initial situation_ from which we set out. Now these movements are
revealed to us by our muscular sensations; but nothing tells us the
initial situation; nothing can distinguish it for us from all the other
possible situations. This puts well in evidence the essential relativity
of space.


4. _Identity of the Different Spaces_

We are therefore led to compare the two continua _C_ and _C'_
engendered, for instance, one by my first finger _D_, the other by my
second finger _D'_. These two physical continua both have three
dimensions. To each element of the continuum _C_, or, if you prefer, to
each point of the first tactile space, corresponds a series of muscular
sensations [Sigma], which carry me from a certain initial situation to a
certain final situation.[8] Moreover, the same point of this first space
will correspond to [Sigma] and [Sigma] + [sigma], if [sigma] is a series
of which we know that it does not make the finger _D_ move.

  [8] In place of saying that we refer space to axes rigidly bound to
      our body, perhaps it would be better to say, in conformity to
      what precedes, that we refer it to axes rigidly bound to the
      initial situation of our body.

Similarly to each element of the continuum _C'_, or to each point of the
second tactile space, corresponds a series of sensations [Sigma]', and
the same point will correspond to [Sigma]' and to [Sigma]' + [sigma]',
if [sigma]' is a series which does not make the finger _D'_ move.

What makes us distinguish the various series designated [sigma] from
those called [sigma]' is that the first do not alter the tactile
impressions felt by the finger _D_ and the second preserve those the
finger _D'_ feels.

Now see what we ascertain: in the beginning my finger _D'_ feels a
sensation _A'_; I make movements which produce muscular sensations _S_;
my finger _D_ feels the impression _A_; I make movements which produce a
series of sensations [sigma]; my finger _D_ continues to feel the
impression _A_, since this is the characteristic property of the series
[sigma]; I then make movements which produce the series _S'_ of muscular
sensations, _inverse_ to _S_ in the sense above given to this word. I
ascertain then that my finger _D'_ feels anew the impression _A'_. (It
is of course understood that _S_ has been suitably chosen.)

This means that the series _S_ + [sigma] + _S'_, preserving the tactile
impressions of the finger _D'_, is one of the series I have called
[sigma]'. Inversely, if one takes any series [sigma]', _S'_ + [sigma]' +
_S_ will be one of the series that we call [sigma]'.

Thus if _S_ is suitably chosen, _S_ + [sigma] + _S'_ will be a series
[sigma]', and by making [sigma] vary in all possible ways, we shall
obtain all the possible series [sigma]'.

Not yet knowing geometry, we limit ourselves to verifying all that, but
here is how those who know geometry would explain the fact. In the
beginning my finger _D'_ is at the point _M_, in contact with the object
_a_, which makes it feel the impression _A'_. I make the movements
corresponding to the series _S_; I have said that this series should be
suitably chosen, I should so make this choice that these movements carry
the finger _D_ to the point originally occupied by the finger _D'_, that
is, to the point _M_; this finger _D_ will thus be in contact with the
object _a_, which will make it feel the impression _A_.

I then make the movements corresponding to the series [sigma]; in these
movements, by hypothesis, the position of the finger _D_ does not
change, this finger therefore remains in contact with the object a and
continues to feel the impression _A_. Finally I make the movements
corresponding to the series _S'_. As _S'_ is inverse to _S_, these
movements carry the finger _D'_ to the point previously occupied by the
finger _D_, that is, to the point _M_. If, as may be supposed, the
object _a_ has not budged, this finger _D'_ will be in contact with this
object and will feel anew the impression _A'_.... _Q.E.D._

Let us see the consequences. I consider a series of muscular sensations
[Sigma]. To this series will correspond a point _M_ of the first tactile
space. Now take again the two series _S_ and _S'_, inverses of one
another, of which we have just spoken. To the series _S_ + [Sigma] +
_S'_ will correspond a point _N_ of the second tactile space, since to
any series of muscular sensations corresponds, as we have said, a
point, whether in the first space or in the second.

I am going to consider the two points _N_ and _M_, thus defined, as
corresponding. What authorizes me so to do? For this correspondence to
be admissible, it is necessary that if two points _M_ and _M'_,
corresponding in the first space to two series [Sigma] and [Sigma]', are
identical, so also are the two corresponding points of the second space
_N_ and _N'_, that is, the two points which correspond to the two series
_S_ + [Sigma] + _S'_ and _S_ + [Sigma]' + _S'_. Now we shall see that
this condition is fulfilled.

First a remark. As _S_ and _S'_ are inverses of one another, we shall
have _S_ + _S'_ = 0, and consequently _S_ + _S'_ + [Sigma] = [Sigma] +
_S_ + _S'_ = [Sigma], or again [Sigma] + _S_ + _S'_ + [Sigma]' = [Sigma]
+ [Sigma]'; but it does not follow that we have _S_ + [Sigma] + _S'_ =
[Sigma]; because, though we have used the addition sign to represent the
succession of our sensations, it is clear that the order of this
succession is not indifferent: we can not, therefore, as in ordinary
addition, invert the order of the terms; to use abridged language, our
operations are associative, but not commutative.

That fixed, in order that [Sigma] and [Sigma]' should correspond to the
same point _M_ = _M'_ of the first space, it is necessary and sufficient
for us to have [Sigma]' = [Sigma] + [sigma]. We shall then have: _S_ +
[Sigma]' + _S'_ = _S_ + [Sigma] + [sigma] + _S'_ = _S_ + [Sigma] + _S'_
+ _S_ + [sigma] + _S'_.

But we have just ascertained that _S_ + [sigma] + _S'_ was one of the
series [sigma]'. We shall therefore have: _S_ + [Sigma]' + _S'_ = _S_ +
[Sigma] + _S'_ + [sigma]', which means that the series _S_ + [Sigma]' +
_S'_ and _S_ + [Sigma] + _S'_ correspond to the same point _N_ = _N'_ of
the second space. Q.E.D.

Our two spaces therefore correspond point for point; they can be
'transformed' one into the other; they are isomorphic. How are we led to
conclude thence that they are identical?

Consider the two series [sigma] and _S_ + [sigma] + _S'_ = [sigma]'. I
have said that often, but not always, the series [sigma] preserves the
tactile impression _A_ felt by the finger _D_; and similarly it often
happens, but not always, that the series [sigma]' preserves the tactile
impression _A'_ felt by the finger _D'_. Now I ascertain that it happens
_very often_ (that is, much more often than what I have just called
'often') that when the series [sigma] has preserved the impression _A_
of the finger _D_, the series [sigma]' preserves at the same time the
impression _A'_ of the finger _D'_; and, inversely, that if the first
impression is altered, the second is likewise. That happens _very
often_, but not always.

We interpret this experimental fact by saying that the unknown object
_a_ which gives the impression _A_ to the finger _D_ is identical with
the unknown object _a'_ which gives the impression _A'_ to the finger
_D'_. And in fact when the first object moves, which the disappearance
of the impression _A_ tells us, the second likewise moves, since the
impression _A'_ disappears likewise. When the first object remains
motionless, the second remains motionless. If these two objects are
identical, as the first is at the point _M_ of the first space and the
second at the point _N_ of the second space, these two points are
identical. This is how we are led to regard these two spaces as
identical; or better, this is what we mean when we say that they are
identical.

What we have just said of the identity of the two tactile spaces makes
unnecessary our discussing the question of the identity of tactile space
and visual space, which could be treated in the same way.


5. _Space and Empiricism_

It seems that I am about to be led to conclusions in conformity with
empiristic ideas. I have, in fact, sought to put in evidence the rôle of
experience and to analyze the experimental facts which intervene in the
genesis of space of three dimensions. But whatever may be the importance
of these facts, there is one thing we must not forget and to which
besides I have more than once called attention. These experimental facts
are often verified but not always. That evidently does not mean that
space has often three dimensions, but not always.

I know well that it is easy to save oneself and that, if the facts do
not verify, it will be easily explained by saying that the exterior
objects have moved. If experience succeeds, we say that it teaches us
about space; if it does not succeed, we hie to exterior objects which we
accuse of having moved; in other words, if it does not succeed, it is
given a fillip.

These fillips are legitimate; I do not refuse to admit them; but they
suffice to tell us that the properties of space are not experimental
truths, properly so called. If we had wished to verify other laws, we
could have succeeded also, by giving other analogous fillips. Should we
not always have been able to justify these fillips by the same reasons?
One could at most have said to us: 'Your fillips are doubtless
legitimate, but you abuse them; why move the exterior objects so often?'

To sum up, experience does not prove to us that space has three
dimensions; it only proves to us that it is convenient to attribute
three to it, because thus the number of fillips is reduced to a minimum.

I will add that experience brings us into contact only with
representative space, which is a physical continuum, never with
geometric space, which is a mathematical continuum. At the very most it
would appear to tell us that it is convenient to give to geometric space
three dimensions, so that it may have as many as representative space.

The empiric question may be put under another form. Is it impossible to
conceive physical phenomena, the mechanical phenomena, for example,
otherwise than in space of three dimensions? We should thus have an
objective experimental proof, so to speak, independent of our
physiology, of our modes of representation.

But it is not so; I shall not here discuss the question completely, I
shall confine myself to recalling the striking example given us by the
mechanics of Hertz. You know that the great physicist did not believe in
the existence of forces, properly so called; he supposed that visible
material points are subjected to certain invisible bonds which join them
to other invisible points and that it is the effect of these invisible
bonds that we attribute to forces.

But that is only a part of his ideas. Suppose a system formed of n
material points, visible or not; that will give in all 3_n_ coordinates;
let us regard them as the coordinates of a _single_ point in space of
3_n_ dimensions. This single point would be constrained to remain upon a
surface (of any number of dimensions < 3_n_) in virtue of the bonds of
which we have just spoken; to go on this surface from one point to
another, it would always take the shortest way; this would be the
single principle which would sum up all mechanics.

Whatever should be thought of this hypothesis, whether we be allured by
its simplicity, or repelled by its artificial character, the simple fact
that Hertz was able to conceive it, and to regard it as more convenient
than our habitual hypotheses, suffices to prove that our ordinary ideas,
and, in particular, the three dimensions of space, are in no wise
imposed upon mechanics with an invincible force.


6. _Mind and Space_

Experience, therefore, has played only a single rôle, it has served as
occasion. But this rôle was none the less very important; and I have
thought it necessary to give it prominence. This rôle would have been
useless if there existed an _a priori_ form imposing itself upon our
sensitivity, and which was space of three dimensions.

Does this form exist, or, if you choose, can we represent to ourselves
space of more than three dimensions? And first what does this question
mean? In the true sense of the word, it is clear that we can not
represent to ourselves space of four, nor space of three, dimensions; we
can not first represent them to ourselves empty, and no more can we
represent to ourselves an object either in space of four, or in space of
three, dimensions: (1) Because these spaces are both infinite and we can
not represent to ourselves a figure _in_ space, that is, the part _in_
the whole, without representing the whole, and that is impossible,
because it is infinite; (2) because these spaces are both mathematical
continua, and we can represent to ourselves only the physical continuum;
(3) because these spaces are both homogeneous, and the frames in which
we enclose our sensations, being limited, can not be homogeneous.

Thus the question put can only be understood in one way; is it possible
to imagine that, the results of the experiences related above having
been different, we might have been led to attribute to space more than
three dimensions; to imagine, for instance, that the sensation of
accommodation might not be constantly in accord with the sensation of
convergence of the eyes; or indeed that the experiences of which we
have spoken in § 2, and of which we express the result by saying 'that
touch does not operate at a distance,' might have led us to an inverse
conclusion.

And then yes evidently that is possible; from the moment one imagines an
experience, one imagines just thereby the two contrary results it may
give. That is possible, but that is difficult, because we have to
overcome a multitude of associations of ideas, which are the fruit of a
long personal experience and of the still longer experience of the race.
Is it these associations (or at least those of them that we have
inherited from our ancestors), which constitute this _a priori_ form of
which it is said that we have pure intuition? Then I do not see why one
should declare it refractory to analysis and should deny me the right of
investigating its origin.

When it is said that our sensations are 'extended' only one thing can be
meant, that is that they are always associated with the idea of certain
muscular sensations, corresponding to the movements which enable us to
reach the object which causes them, which enable us, in other words, to
defend ourselves against it. And it is just because this association is
useful for the defense of the organism, that it is so old in the history
of the species and that it seems to us indestructible. Nevertheless, it
is only an association and we can conceive that it may be broken; so
that we may not say that sensation can not enter consciousness without
entering in space, but that in fact it does not enter consciousness
without entering in space, which means, without being entangled in this
association.

No more can I understand one's saying that the idea of time is logically
subsequent to space, since we can represent it to ourselves only under
the form of a straight line; as well say that time is logically
subsequent to the cultivation of the prairies, since it is usually
represented armed with a scythe. That one can not represent to himself
simultaneously the different parts of time, goes without saying, since
the essential character of these parts is precisely not to be
simultaneous. That does not mean that we have not the intuition of time.
So far as that goes, no more should we have that of space, because
neither can we represent it, in the proper sense of the word, for the
reasons I have mentioned. What we represent to ourselves under the name
of straight is a crude image which as ill resembles the geometric
straight as it does time itself.

Why has it been said that every attempt to give a fourth dimension to
space always carries this one back to one of the other three? It is easy
to understand. Consider our muscular sensations and the 'series' they
may form. In consequence of numerous experiences, the ideas of these
series are associated together in a very complex woof, our series are
_classed_. Allow me, for convenience of language, to express my thought
in a way altogether crude and even inexact by saying that our series of
muscular sensations are classed in three classes corresponding to the
three dimensions of space. Of course this classification is much more
complicated than that, but that will suffice to make my reasoning
understood. If I wish to imagine a fourth dimension, I shall suppose
another series of muscular sensations, making part of a fourth class.
But as _all_ my muscular sensations have already been classed in one of
the three pre-existent classes, I can only represent to myself a series
belonging to one of these three classes, so that my fourth dimension is
carried back to one of the other three.

What does that prove? This: that it would have been necessary first to
destroy the old classification and replace it by a new one in which the
series of muscular sensations should have been distributed into four
classes. The difficulty would have disappeared.

It is presented sometimes under a more striking form. Suppose I am
enclosed in a chamber between the six impassable boundaries formed by
the four walls, the floor and the ceiling; it will be impossible for me
to get out and to imagine my getting out. Pardon, can you not imagine
that the door opens, or that two of these walls separate? But of course,
you answer, one must suppose that these walls remain immovable. Yes, but
it is evident that I have the right to move; and then the walls that we
suppose absolutely at rest will be in motion with regard to me. Yes, but
such a relative motion can not be arbitrary; when objects are at rest,
their relative motion with regard to any axes is that of a rigid solid;
now, the apparent motions that you imagine are not in conformity with
the laws of motion of a rigid solid. Yes, but it is experience which has
taught us the laws of motion of a rigid solid; nothing would prevent our
_imagining_ them different. To sum up, for me to imagine that I get out
of my prison, I have only to imagine that the walls seem to open, when I
move.

I believe, therefore, that if by space is understood a mathematical
continuum of three dimensions, were it otherwise amorphous, it is the
mind which constructs it, but it does not construct it out of nothing;
it needs materials and models. These materials, like these models,
preexist within it. But there is not a single model which is imposed
upon it; it has _choice_; it may choose, for instance, between space of
four and space of three dimensions. What then is the rôle of experience?
It gives the indications following which the choice is made.

Another thing: whence does space get its quantitative character? It
comes from the rôle which the series of muscular sensations play in its
genesis. These are series which may _repeat themselves_, and it is from
their repetition that number comes; it is because they can repeat
themselves indefinitely that space is infinite. And finally we have
seen, at the end of section 3, that it is also because of this that
space is relative. So it is repetition which has given to space its
essential characteristics; now, repetition supposes time; this is enough
to tell that time is logically anterior to space.

7. _Rôle of the Semicircular Canals_

I have not hitherto spoken of the rôle of certain organs to which the
physiologists attribute with reason a capital importance, I mean the
semicircular canals. Numerous experiments have sufficiently shown that
these canals are necessary to our sense of orientation; but the
physiologists are not entirely in accord; two opposing theories have
been proposed, that of Mach-Delage and that of M. de Cyon.

M. de Cyon is a physiologist who has made his name illustrious by
important discoveries on the innervation of the heart; I can not,
however, agree with his ideas on the question before us. Not being a
physiologist, I hesitate to criticize the experiments he has directed
against the adverse theory of Mach-Delage; it seems to me, however, that
they are not convincing, because in many of them the _total_ pressure
was made to vary in one of the canals, while, physiologically, what
varies is the _difference_ between the pressures on the two extremities
of the canal; in others the organs were subjected to profound lesions,
which must alter their functions.

Besides, this is not important; the experiments, if they were
irreproachable, might be convincing against the old theory. They would
not be convincing _for_ the new theory. In fact, if I have rightly
understood the theory, my explaining it will be enough for one to
understand that it is impossible to conceive of an experiment confirming
it.

The three pairs of canals would have as sole function to tell us that
space has three dimensions. Japanese mice have only two pairs of canals;
they believe, it would seem, that space has only two dimensions, and
they manifest this opinion in the strangest way; they put themselves in
a circle, and, so ordered, they spin rapidly around. The lampreys,
having only one pair of canals, believe that space has only one
dimension, but their manifestations are less turbulent.

It is evident that such a theory is inadmissible. The sense-organs are
designed to tell us of _changes_ which happen in the exterior world. We
could not understand why the Creator should have given us organs
destined to cry without cease: Remember that space has three dimensions,
since the number of these three dimensions is not subject to change.

We must, therefore, come back to the theory of Mach-Delage. What the
nerves of the canals can tell us is the difference of pressure on the
two extremities of the same canal, and thereby: (1) the direction of the
vertical with regard to three axes rigidly bound to the head; (2) the
three components of the acceleration of translation of the center of
gravity of the head; (3) the centrifugal forces developed by the
rotation of the head; (4) the acceleration of the motion of rotation of
the head.

It follows from the experiments of M. Delage that it is this last
indication which is much the most important; doubtless because the
nerves are less sensible to the difference of pressure itself than to
the brusque variations of this difference. The first three indications
may thus be neglected.

Knowing the acceleration of the motion of rotation of the head at each
instant, we deduce from it, by an unconscious integration, the final
orientation of the head, referred to a certain initial orientation taken
as origin. The circular canals contribute, therefore, to inform us of
the movements that we have executed, and that on the same ground as the
muscular sensations. When, therefore, above we speak of the series _S_
or of the series [Sigma], we should say, not that these were series of
muscular sensations alone, but that they were series at the same time of
muscular sensations and of sensations due to the semicircular canals.
Apart from this addition, we should have nothing to change in what
precedes.

In the series _S_ and [Sigma], these sensations of the semicircular
canals evidently hold a very important place. Yet alone they would not
suffice, because they can tell us only of the movements of the head;
they tell us nothing of the relative movements of the body or of the
members in regard to the head. And more, it seems that they tell us only
of the rotations of the head and not of the translations it may
undergo.



PART II


THE PHYSICAL SCIENCES



CHAPTER V

ANALYSIS AND PHYSICS


I

You have doubtless often been asked of what good is mathematics and
whether these delicate constructions entirely mind-made are not
artificial and born of our caprice.

Among those who put this question I should make a distinction; practical
people ask of us only the means of money-making. These merit no reply;
rather would it be proper to ask of them what is the good of
accumulating so much wealth and whether, to get time to acquire it, we
are to neglect art and science, which alone give us souls capable of
enjoying it, 'and for life's sake to sacrifice all reasons for living.'

Besides, a science made solely in view of applications is impossible;
truths are fecund only if bound together. If we devote ourselves solely
to those truths whence we expect an immediate result, the intermediary
links are wanting and there will no longer be a chain.

The men most disdainful of theory get from it, without suspecting it,
their daily bread; deprived of this food, progress would quickly cease,
and we should soon congeal into the immobility of old China.

But enough of uncompromising practicians! Besides these, there are those
who are only interested in nature and who ask us if we can enable them
to know it better.

To answer these, we have only to show them the two monuments already
rough-hewn, Celestial Mechanics and Mathematical Physics.

They would doubtless concede that these structures are well worth the
trouble they have cost us. But this is not enough. Mathematics has a
triple aim. It must furnish an instrument for the study of nature. But
that is not all: it has a philosophic aim and, I dare maintain, an
esthetic aim. It must aid the philosopher to fathom the notions of
number, of space, of time. And above all, its adepts find therein
delights analogous to those given by painting and music. They admire the
delicate harmony of numbers and forms; they marvel when a new discovery
opens to them an unexpected perspective; and has not the joy they thus
feel the esthetic character, even though the senses take no part
therein? Only a privileged few are called to enjoy it fully, it is true,
but is not this the case for all the noblest arts?

This is why I do not hesitate to say that mathematics deserves to be
cultivated for its own sake, and the theories inapplicable to physics as
well as the others. Even if the physical aim and the esthetic aim were
not united, we ought not to sacrifice either.

But more: these two aims are inseparable and the best means of attaining
one is to aim at the other, or at least never to lose sight of it. This
is what I am about to try to demonstrate in setting forth the nature of
the relations between the pure science and its applications.

The mathematician should not be for the physicist a mere purveyor of
formulas; there should be between them a more intimate collaboration.
Mathematical physics and pure analysis are not merely adjacent powers,
maintaining good neighborly relations; they mutually interpenetrate and
their spirit is the same. This will be better understood when I have
shown what physics gets from mathematics and what mathematics, in
return, borrows from physics.


II

The physicist can not ask of the analyst to reveal to him a new truth;
the latter could at most only aid him to foresee it. It is a long time
since one still dreamt of forestalling experiment, or of constructing
the entire world on certain premature hypotheses. Since all those
constructions in which one yet took a naïve delight it is an age, to-day
only their ruins remain.

All laws are therefore deduced from experiment; but to enunciate them, a
special language is needful; ordinary language is too poor, it is
besides too vague, to express relations so delicate, so rich, and so
precise.

This therefore is one reason why the physicist can not do without
mathematics; it furnishes him the only language he can speak. And a
well-made language is no indifferent thing; not to go beyond physics,
the unknown man who invented the word _heat_ devoted many generations to
error. Heat has been treated as a substance, simply because it was
designated by a substantive, and it has been thought indestructible.

On the other hand, he who invented the word _electricity_ had the
unmerited good fortune to implicitly endow physics with a _new_ law,
that of the conservation of electricity, which, by a pure chance, has
been found exact, at least until now.

Well, to continue the simile, the writers who embellish a language, who
treat it as an object of art, make of it at the same time a more supple
instrument, more apt for rendering shades of thought.

We understand, then, how the analyst, who pursues a purely esthetic aim,
helps create, just by that, a language more fit to satisfy the
physicist.

But this is not all: law springs from experiment, but not immediately.
Experiment is individual, the law deduced from it is general; experiment
is only approximate, the law is precise, or at least pretends to be.
Experiment is made under conditions always complex, the enunciation of
the law eliminates these complications. This is what is called
'correcting the systematic errors.'

In a word, to get the law from experiment, it is necessary to
generalize; this is a necessity imposed upon the most circumspect
observer. But how generalize? Every particular truth may evidently be
extended in an infinity of ways. Among these thousand routes opening
before us, it is necessary to make a choice, at least provisional; in
this choice, what shall guide us?

It can only be analogy. But how vague is this word! Primitive man knew
only crude analogies, those which strike the senses, those of colors or
of sounds. He never would have dreamt of likening light to radiant
heat.

What has taught us to know the true, profound analogies, those the eyes
do not see but reason divines?

It is the mathematical spirit, which disdains matter to cling only to
pure form. This it is which has taught us to give the same name to
things differing only in material, to call by the same name, for
instance, the multiplication of quaternions and that of whole numbers.

If quaternions, of which I have just spoken, had not been so promptly
utilized by the English physicists, many persons would doubtless see in
them only a useless fancy, and yet, in teaching us to liken what
appearances separate, they would have already rendered us more apt to
penetrate the secrets of nature.

Such are the services the physicist should expect of analysis; but for
this science to be able to render them, it must be cultivated in the
broadest fashion without immediate expectation of utility--the
mathematician must have worked as artist.

What we ask of him is to help us to see, to discern our way in the
labyrinth which opens before us. Now, he sees best who stands highest.
Examples abound, and I limit myself to the most striking.

The first will show us how to change the language suffices to reveal
generalizations not before suspected.

When Newton's law has been substituted for Kepler's we still know only
elliptic motion. Now, in so far as concerns this motion, the two laws
differ only in form; we pass from one to the other by a simple
differentiation. And yet from Newton's law may be deduced by an
immediate generalization all the effects of perturbations and the whole
of celestial mechanics. If, on the other hand, Kepler's enunciation had
been retained, no one would ever have regarded the orbits of the
perturbed planets, those complicated curves of which no one has ever
written the equation, as the natural generalizations of the ellipse. The
progress of observations would only have served to create belief in
chaos.

The second example is equally deserving of consideration.

When Maxwell began his work, the laws of electro-dynamics admitted up to
his time accounted for all the known facts. It was not a new experiment
which came to invalidate them. But in looking at them under a new bias,
Maxwell saw that the equations became more symmetrical when a term was
added, and besides, this term was too small to produce effects
appreciable with the old methods.

You know that Maxwell's _a priori_ views awaited for twenty years an
experimental confirmation; or, if you prefer, Maxwell was twenty years
ahead of experiment. How was this triumph obtained?

It was because Maxwell was profoundly steeped in the sense of
mathematical symmetry; would he have been so, if others before him had
not studied this symmetry for its own beauty?

It was because Maxwell was accustomed to 'think in vectors,' and yet it
was through the theory of imaginaries (neomonics) that vectors were
introduced into analysis. And those who invented imaginaries hardly
suspected the advantage which would be obtained from them for the study
of the real world, of this the name given them is proof sufficient.

In a word, Maxwell was perhaps not an able analyst, but this ability
would have been for him only a useless and bothersome baggage. On the
other hand, he had in the highest degree the intimate sense of
mathematical analogies. Therefore it is that he made good mathematical
physics.

Maxwell's example teaches us still another thing.

How should the equations of mathematical physics be treated? Should we
simply deduce all the consequences and regard them as intangible
realities? Far from it; what they should teach us above all is what can
and what should be changed. It is thus that we get from them something
useful.

The third example goes to show us how we may perceive mathematical
analogies between phenomena which have physically no relation either
apparent or real, so that the laws of one of these phenomena aid us to
divine those of the other.

The very same equation, that of Laplace, is met in the theory of
Newtonian attraction, in that of the motion of liquids, in that of the
electric potential, in that of magnetism, in that of the propagation of
heat and in still many others. What is the result? These theories seem
images copied one from the other; they are mutually illuminating,
borrowing their language from each other; ask electricians if they do
not felicitate themselves on having invented the phrase flow of force,
suggested by hydrodynamics and the theory of heat.

Thus mathematical analogies not only may make us foresee physical
analogies, but besides do not cease to be useful when these latter fail.

To sum up, the aim of mathematical physics is not only to facilitate for
the physicist the numerical calculation of certain constants or the
integration of certain differential equations. It is besides, it is
above all, to reveal to him the hidden harmony of things in making him
see them in a new way.

Of all the parts of analysis, the most elevated, the purest, so to
speak, will be the most fruitful in the hands of those who know how to
use them.


III

Let us now see what analysis owes to physics.

It would be necessary to have completely forgotten the history of
science not to remember that the desire to understand nature has had on
the development of mathematics the most constant and happiest influence.

In the first place the physicist sets us problems whose solution he
expects of us. But in proposing them to us, he has largely paid us in
advance for the service we shall render him, if we solve them.

If I may be allowed to continue my comparison with the fine arts, the
pure mathematician who should forget the existence of the exterior world
would be like a painter who knew how to harmoniously combine colors and
forms, but who lacked models. His creative power would soon be
exhausted.

The combinations which numbers and symbols may form are an infinite
multitude. In this multitude how shall we choose those which are worthy
to fix our attention? Shall we let ourselves be guided solely by our
caprice? This caprice, which itself would besides soon tire, would
doubtless carry us very far apart and we should quickly cease to
understand each other.

But this is only the smaller side of the question. Physics will
doubtless prevent our straying, but it will also preserve us from a
danger much more formidable; it will prevent our ceaselessly going
around in the same circle.

History proves that physics has not only forced us to choose among
problems which came in a crowd; it has imposed upon us such as we should
without it never have dreamed of. However varied may be the imagination
of man, nature is still a thousand times richer. To follow her we must
take ways we have neglected, and these paths lead us often to summits
whence we discover new countries. What could be more useful!

It is with mathematical symbols as with physical realities; it is in
comparing the different aspects of things that we are able to comprehend
their inner harmony, which alone is beautiful and consequently worthy of
our efforts.

The first example I shall cite is so old we are tempted to forget it; it
is nevertheless the most important of all.

The sole natural object of mathematical thought is the whole number. It
is the external world which has imposed the continuum upon us, which we
doubtless have invented, but which it has forced us to invent. Without
it there would be no infinitesimal analysis; all mathematical science
would reduce itself to arithmetic or to the theory of substitutions.

On the contrary, we have devoted to the study of the continuum almost
all our time and all our strength. Who will regret it; who will think
that this time and this strength have been wasted? Analysis unfolds
before us infinite perspectives that arithmetic never suspects; it shows
us at a glance a majestic assemblage whose array is simple and
symmetric; on the contrary, in the theory of numbers, where reigns the
unforeseen, the view is, so to speak, arrested at every step.

Doubtless it will be said that outside of the whole number there is no
rigor, and consequently no mathematical truth; that the whole number
hides everywhere, and that we must strive to render transparent the
screens which cloak it, even if to do so we must resign ourselves to
interminable repetitions. Let us not be such purists and let us be
grateful to the continuum, which, if _all_ springs from the whole
number, was alone capable of making _so much_ proceed therefrom.

Need I also recall that M. Hermite obtained a surprising advantage from
the introduction of continuous variables into the theory of numbers?
Thus the whole number's own domain is itself invaded, and this invasion
has established order where disorder reigned.

See what we owe to the continuum and consequently to physical nature.

Fourier's series is a precious instrument of which analysis makes
continual use, it is by this means that it has been able to represent
discontinuous functions; Fourier invented it to solve a problem of
physics relative to the propagation of heat. If this problem had not
come up naturally, we should never have dared to give discontinuity its
rights; we should still long have regarded continuous functions as the
only true functions.

The notion of function has been thereby considerably extended and has
received from some logician-analysts an unforeseen development. These
analysts have thus adventured into regions where reigns the purest
abstraction and have gone as far away as possible from the real world.
Yet it is a problem of physics which has furnished them the occasion.

After Fourier's series, other analogous series have entered the domain
of analysis; they have entered by the same door; they have been imagined
in view of applications.

The theory of partial differential equations of the second order has an
analogous history. It has been developed chiefly by and for physics. But
it may take many forms, because such an equation does not suffice to
determine the unknown function, it is necessary to adjoin to it
complementary conditions which are called conditions at the limits;
whence many different problems.

If the analysts had abandoned themselves to their natural tendencies,
they would never have known but one, that which Madame Kovalevski has
treated in her celebrated memoir. But there are a multitude of others
which they would have ignored. Each of the theories of physics, that of
electricity, that of heat, presents us these equations under a new
aspect. It may, therefore, be said that without these theories we should
not know partial differential equations.

It is needless to multiply examples. I have given enough to be able to
conclude: when physicists ask of us the solution of a problem, it is not
a duty-service they impose upon us, it is on the contrary we who owe
them thanks.


IV

But this is not all; physics not only gives us the occasion to solve
problems; it aids us to find the means thereto, and that in two ways. It
makes us foresee the solution; it suggests arguments to us.

I have spoken above of Laplace's equation which is met in a multitude of
diverse physical theories. It is found again in geometry, in the theory
of conformal representation and in pure analysis, in that of
imaginaries.

In this way, in the study of functions of complex variables, the
analyst, alongside of the geometric image, which is his usual
instrument, finds many physical images which he may make use of with the
same success. Thanks to these images, he can see at a glance what pure
deduction would show him only successively. He masses thus the separate
elements of the solution, and by a sort of intuition divines before
being able to demonstrate.

To divine before demonstrating! Need I recall that thus have been made
all the important discoveries? How many are the truths that physical
analogies permit us to present and that we are not in condition to
establish by rigorous reasoning!

For example, mathematical physics introduces a great number of
developments in series. No one doubts that these developments converge;
but the mathematical certitude is lacking. These are so many conquests
assured for the investigators who shall come after us.

On the other hand, physics furnishes us not alone solutions; it
furnishes us besides, in a certain measure, arguments. It will suffice
to recall how Felix Klein, in a question relative to Riemann surfaces,
has had recourse to the properties of electric currents.

It is true, the arguments of this species are not rigorous, in the sense
the analyst attaches to this word. And here a question arises: How can a
demonstration not sufficiently rigorous for the analyst suffice for the
physicist? It seems there can not be two rigors, that rigor is or is
not, and that, where it is not there can not be deduction.

This apparent paradox will be better understood by recalling under what
conditions number is applied to natural phenomena. Whence come in
general the difficulties encountered in seeking rigor? We strike them
almost always in seeking to establish that some quantity tends to some
limit, or that some function is continuous, or that it has a derivative.

Now the numbers the physicist measures by experiment are never known
except approximately; and besides, any function always differs as little
as you choose from a discontinuous function, and at the same time it
differs as little as you choose from a continuous function. The
physicist may, therefore, at will suppose that the function studied is
continuous, or that it is discontinuous; that it has or has not a
derivative; and may do so without fear of ever being contradicted,
either by present experience or by any future experiment. We see that
with such liberty he makes sport of difficulties which stop the analyst.
He may always reason as if all the functions which occur in his
calculations were entire polynomials.

Thus the sketch which suffices for physics is not the deduction which
analysis requires. It does not follow thence that one can not aid in
finding the other. So many physical sketches have already been
transformed into rigorous demonstrations that to-day this transformation
is easy. There would be plenty of examples did I not fear in citing them
to tire the reader.

I hope I have said enough to show that pure analysis and mathematical
physics may serve one another without making any sacrifice one to the
other, and that each of these two sciences should rejoice in all which
elevates its associate.



CHAPTER VI

ASTRONOMY


Governments and parliaments must find that astronomy is one of the
sciences which cost most dear: the least instrument costs hundreds of
thousands of dollars, the least observatory costs millions; each eclipse
carries with it supplementary appropriations. And all that for stars
which are so far away, which are complete strangers to our electoral
contests, and in all probability will never take any part in them. It
must be that our politicians have retained a remnant of idealism, a
vague instinct for what is grand; truly, I think they have been
calumniated; they should be encouraged and shown that this instinct does
not deceive them, that they are not dupes of that idealism.

We might indeed speak to them of navigation, of which no one can
underestimate the importance, and which has need of astronomy. But this
would be to take the question by its smaller side.

Astronomy is useful because it raises us above ourselves; it is useful
because it is grand; that is what we should say. It shows us how small
is man's body, how great his mind, since his intelligence can embrace
the whole of this dazzling immensity, where his body is only an obscure
point, and enjoy its silent harmony. Thus we attain the consciousness of
our power, and this is something which can not cost too dear, since this
consciousness makes us mightier.

But what I should wish before all to show is, to what point astronomy
has facilitated the work of the other sciences, more directly useful,
since it has given us a soul capable of comprehending nature.

Think how diminished humanity would be if, under heavens constantly
overclouded, as Jupiter's must be, it had forever remained ignorant of
the stars. Do you think that in such a world we should be what we are? I
know well that under this somber vault we should have been deprived of
the light of the sun, necessary to organisms like those which inhabit
the earth. But if you please, we shall assume that these clouds are
phosphorescent and emit a soft and constant light. Since we are making
hypotheses, another will cost no more. Well! I repeat my question: Do
you think that in such a world we should be what we are?

The stars send us not only that visible and gross light which strikes
our bodily eyes, but from them also comes to us a light far more subtle,
which illuminates our minds and whose effects I shall try to show you.
You know what man was on the earth some thousands of years ago, and what
he is to-day. Isolated amidst a nature where everything was a mystery to
him, terrified at each unexpected manifestation of incomprehensible
forces, he was incapable of seeing in the conduct of the universe
anything but caprice; he attributed all phenomena to the action of a
multitude of little genii, fantastic and exacting, and to act on the
world he sought to conciliate them by means analogous to those employed
to gain the good graces of a minister or a deputy. Even his failures did
not enlighten him, any more than to-day a beggar refused is discouraged
to the point of ceasing to beg.

To-day we no longer beg of nature; we command her, because we have
discovered certain of her secrets and shall discover others each day. We
command her in the name of laws she can not challenge, because they are
hers; these laws we do not madly ask her to change, we are the first to
submit to them. Nature can only be governed by obeying her.

What a change must our souls have undergone to pass from the one state
to the other! Does any one believe that, without the lessons of the
stars, under the heavens perpetually overclouded that I have just
supposed, they would have changed so quickly? Would the metamorphosis
have been possible, or at least would it not have been much slower?

And first of all, astronomy it is which taught that there are laws. The
Chaldeans, who were the first to observe the heavens with some
attention, saw that this multitude of luminous points is not a confused
crowd wandering at random, but rather a disciplined army. Doubtless the
rules of this discipline escaped them, but the harmonious spectacle of
the starry night sufficed to give them the impression of regularity,
and that was in itself already a great thing. Besides, these rules were
discerned by Hipparchus, Ptolemy, Copernicus, Kepler, one after another,
and finally, it is needless to recall that Newton it was who enunciated
the oldest, the most precise, the most simple, the most general of all
natural laws.

And then, taught by this example, we have seen our little terrestrial
world better and, under the apparent disorder, there also we have found
again the harmony that the study of the heavens had revealed to us. It
also is regular, it also obeys immutable laws, but they are more
complicated, in apparent conflict one with another, and an eye untrained
by other sights would have seen there only chaos and the reign of chance
or caprice. If we had not known the stars, some bold spirits might
perhaps have sought to foresee physical phenomena; but their failures
would have been frequent, and they would have excited only the derision
of the vulgar; do we not see, that even in our day the meteorologists
sometimes deceive themselves, and that certain persons are inclined to
laugh at them.

How often would the physicists, disheartened by so many checks, have
fallen into discouragement, if they had not had, to sustain their
confidence, the brilliant example of the success of the astronomers!
This success showed them that nature obeys laws; it only remained to
know what laws; for that they only needed patience, and they had the
right to demand that the sceptics should give them credit.

This is not all: astronomy has not only taught us that there are laws,
but that from these laws there is no escape, that with them there is no
possible compromise. How much time should we have needed to comprehend
that fact, if we had known only the terrestrial world, where each
elemental force would always seem to us in conflict with other forces?
Astronomy has taught us that the laws are infinitely precise, and that
if those we enunciate are approximative, it is because we do not know
them well. Aristotle, the most scientific mind of antiquity, still
accorded a part to accident, to chance, and seemed to think that the
laws of nature, at least here below, determine only the large features
of phenomena. How much has the ever-increasing precision of
astronomical predictions contributed to correct such an error, which
would have rendered nature unintelligible!

But are these laws not local, varying in different places, like those
which men make; does not that which is truth in one corner of the
universe, on our globe, for instance, or in our little solar system,
become error a little farther away? And then could it not be asked
whether laws depending on space do not also depend upon time, whether
they are not simple habitudes, transitory, therefore, and ephemeral?
Again it is astronomy that answers this question. Consider the double
stars; all describe conics; thus, as far as the telescope carries, it
does not reach the limits of the domain which obeys Newton's law.

Even the simplicity of this law is a lesson for us; how many complicated
phenomena are contained in the two lines of its enunciation; persons who
do not understand celestial mechanics may form some idea of it at least
from the size of the treatises devoted to this science; and then it may
be hoped that the complication of physical phenomena likewise hides from
us some simple cause still unknown.

It is therefore astronomy which has shown us what are the general
characteristics of natural laws; but among these characteristics there
is one, the most subtle and the most important of all, which I shall ask
leave to stress.

How was the order of the universe understood by the ancients; for
instance, by Pythagoras, Plato or Aristotle? It was either an immutable
type fixed once for all, or an ideal to which the world sought to
approach. Kepler himself still thought thus when, for instance, he
sought whether the distances of the planets from the sun had not some
relation to the five regular polyhedrons. This idea contained nothing
absurd, but it was sterile, since nature is not so made. Newton has
shown us that a law is only a necessary relation between the present
state of the world and its immediately subsequent state. All the other
laws since discovered are nothing else; they are in sum, differential
equations; but it is astronomy which furnished the first model for them,
without which we should doubtless long have erred.

Astronomy has also taught us to set at naught appearances. The day
Copernicus proved that what was thought the most stable was in motion,
that what was thought moving was fixed, he showed us how deceptive could
be the infantile reasonings which spring directly from the immediate
data of our senses. True, his ideas did not easily triumph, but since
this triumph there is no longer a prejudice so inveterate that we can
not shake it off. How can we estimate the value of the new weapon thus
won?

The ancients thought everything was made for man, and this illusion must
be very tenacious, since it must ever be combated. Yet it is necessary
to divest oneself of it; or else one will be only an eternal myope,
incapable of seeing the truth. To comprehend nature one must be able to
get out of self, so to speak, and to contemplate her from many different
points of view; otherwise we never shall know more than one side. Now,
to get out of self is what he who refers everything to himself can not
do. Who delivered us from this illusion? It was those who showed us that
the earth is only one of the smallest planets of the solar system, and
that the solar system itself is only an imperceptible point in the
infinite spaces of the stellar universe.

At the same time astronomy taught us not to be afraid of big numbers.
This was needful, not only for knowing the heavens, but to know the
earth itself; and was not so easy as it seems to us to-day. Let us try
to go back and picture to ourselves what a Greek would have thought if
told that red light vibrates four hundred millions of millions of times
per second. Without any doubt, such an assertion would have appeared to
him pure madness, and he never would have lowered himself to test it.
To-day a hypothesis will no longer appear absurd to us because it
obliges us to imagine objects much larger or smaller than those our
senses are capable of showing us, and we no longer comprehend those
scruples which arrested our predecessors and prevented them from
discovering certain truths simply because they were afraid of them. But
why? It is because we have seen the heavens enlarging and enlarging
without cease; because we know that the sun is 150 millions of
kilometers from the earth and that the distances of the nearest stars
are hundreds of thousands of times greater yet. Habituated to the
contemplation of the infinitely great, we have become apt to comprehend
the infinitely small. Thanks to the education it has received, our
imagination, like the eagle's eye that the sun does not dazzle, can look
truth in the face.

Was I wrong in saying that it is astronomy which has made us a soul
capable of comprehending nature; that under heavens always overcast and
starless, the earth itself would have been for us eternally
unintelligible; that we should there have seen only caprice and
disorder; and that, not knowing the world, we should never have been
able to subdue it? What science could have been more useful? And in thus
speaking I put myself at the point of view of those who only value
practical applications. Certainly, this point of view is not mine; as
for me, on the contrary, if I admire the conquests of industry, it is
above all because if they free us from material cares, they will one day
give to all the leisure to contemplate nature. I do not say: Science is
useful, because it teaches us to construct machines. I say: Machines are
useful, because in working for us, they will some day leave us more time
to make science. But finally it is worth remarking that between the two
points of view there is no antagonism, and that man having pursued a
disinterested aim, all else has been added unto him.

Auguste Comte has said somewhere, that it would be idle to seek to know
the composition of the sun, since this knowledge would be of no use to
sociology. How could he be so short-sighted? Have we not just seen that
it is by astronomy that, to speak his language, humanity has passed from
the theological to the positive state? He found an explanation for that
because it had happened. But how has he not understood that what
remained to do was not less considerable and would be not less
profitable? Physical astronomy, which he seems to condemn, has already
begun to bear fruit, and it will give us much more, for it only dates
from yesterday.

First was discovered the nature of the sun, what the founder of
positivism wished to deny us, and there bodies were found which exist on
the earth, but had here remained undiscovered; for example, helium, that
gas almost as light as hydrogen. That already contradicted Comte. But to
the spectroscope we owe a lesson precious in a quite different way; in
the most distant stars, it shows us the same substances. It might have
been asked whether the terrestrial elements were not due to some chance
which had brought together more tenuous atoms to construct of them the
more complex edifice that the chemists call atom; whether, in other
regions of the universe, other fortuitous meetings had not engendered
edifices entirely different. Now we know that this is not so, that the
laws of our chemistry are the general laws of nature, and that they owe
nothing to the chance which caused us to be born on the earth.

But, it will be said, astronomy has given to the other sciences all it
can give them, and now that the heavens have procured for us the
instruments which enable us to study terrestrial nature, they could
without danger veil themselves forever. After what we have just said, is
there still need to answer this objection? One could have reasoned the
same in Ptolemy's time; then also men thought they knew everything, and
they still had almost everything to learn.

The stars are majestic laboratories, gigantic crucibles, such as no
chemist could dream. There reign temperatures impossible for us to
realize. Their only defect is being a little far away; but the telescope
will soon bring them near to us, and then we shall see how matter acts
there. What good fortune for the physicist and the chemist!

Matter will there exhibit itself to us under a thousand different
states, from those rarefied gases which seem to form the nebulæ and
which are luminous with I know not what glimmering of mysterious origin,
even to the incandescent stars and to the planets so near and yet so
different.

Perchance even, the stars will some day teach us something about life;
that seems an insensate dream and I do not at all see how it can be
realized; but, a hundred years ago, would not the chemistry of the stars
have also appeared a mad dream?

But limiting our views to horizons less distant, there still will remain
to us promises less contingent and yet sufficiently seductive. If the
past has given us much, we may rest assured that the future will give us
still more.

In sum, it is incredible how useful belief in astrology has been to
humanity. If Kepler and Tycho Brahe made a living, it was because they
sold to naïve kings predictions founded on the conjunctions of the
stars. If these princes had not been so credulous, we should perhaps
still believe that nature obeys caprice, and we should still wallow in
ignorance.



CHAPTER VII

THE HISTORY OF MATHEMATICAL PHYSICS


_The Past and the Future of Physics._--What is the present state of
mathematical physics? What are the problems it is led to set itself?
What is its future? Is its orientation about to be modified?

Ten years hence will the aim and the methods of this science appear to
our immediate successors in the same light as to ourselves; or, on the
contrary, are we about to witness a profound transformation? Such are
the questions we are forced to raise in entering to-day upon our
investigation.

If it is easy to propound them: to answer is difficult. If we felt
tempted to risk a prediction, we should easily resist this temptation,
by thinking of all the stupidities the most eminent savants of a hundred
years ago would have uttered, if some one had asked them what the
science of the nineteenth century would be. They would have thought
themselves bold in their predictions, and after the event, how very
timid we should have found them. Do not, therefore, expect of me any
prophecy.

But if, like all prudent physicians, I shun giving a prognosis, yet I
can not dispense with a little diagnostic; well, yes, there are
indications of a serious crisis, as if we might expect an approaching
transformation. Still, be not too anxious: we are sure the patient will
not die of it, and we may even hope that this crisis will be salutary,
for the history of the past seems to guarantee us this. This crisis, in
fact, is not the first, and to understand it, it is important to recall
those which have preceded. Pardon then a brief historical sketch.

_The Physics of Central Forces._--Mathematical physics, as we know, was
born of celestial mechanics, which gave birth to it at the end of the
eighteenth century, at the moment when it itself attained its complete
development. During its first years especially, the infant strikingly
resembled its mother.

The astronomic universe is formed of masses, very great, no doubt, but
separated by intervals so immense that they appear to us only as
material points. These points attract each other inversely as the square
of the distance, and this attraction is the sole force which influences
their movements. But if our senses were sufficiently keen to show us all
the details of the bodies which the physicist studies, the spectacle
thus disclosed would scarcely differ from the one the astronomer
contemplates. There also we should see material points, separated from
one another by intervals, enormous in comparison with their dimensions,
and describing orbits according to regular laws. These infinitesimal
stars are the atoms. Like the stars proper, they attract or repel each
other, and this attraction or this repulsion, following the straight
line which joins them, depends only on the distance. The law according
to which this force varies as function of the distance is perhaps not
the law of Newton, but it is an analogous law; in place of the exponent
-2, we have probably a different exponent, and it is from this change of
exponent that arises all the diversity of physical phenomena, the
variety of qualities and of sensations, all the world, colored and
sonorous, which surrounds us; in a word, all nature.

Such is the primitive conception in all its purity. It only remains to
seek in the different cases what value should be given to this exponent
in order to explain all the facts. It is on this model that Laplace, for
example, constructed his beautiful theory of capillarity; he regards it
only as a particular case of attraction, or, as he says, of universal
gravitation, and no one is astonished to find it in the middle of one of
the five volumes of the 'Mécanique céleste.' More recently Briot
believes he penetrated the final secret of optics in demonstrating that
the atoms of ether attract each other in the inverse ratio of the sixth
power of the distance; and Maxwell himself, does he not say somewhere
that the atoms of gases repel each other in the inverse ratio of the
fifth power of the distance? We have the exponent -6, or -5, in place of
the exponent -2, but it is always an exponent.

Among the theories of this epoch, one alone is an exception, that of
Fourier; in it are indeed atoms acting at a distance one upon the other;
they mutually transmit heat, but they do not attract, they never budge.
From this point of view, Fourier's theory must have appeared to the eyes
of his contemporaries, to those of Fourier himself, as imperfect and
provisional.

This conception was not without grandeur; it was seductive, and many
among us have not finally renounced it; they know that one will attain
the ultimate elements of things only by patiently disentangling the
complicated skein that our senses give us; that it is necessary to
advance step by step, neglecting no intermediary; that our fathers were
wrong in wishing to skip stations; but they believe that when one shall
have arrived at these ultimate elements, there again will be found the
majestic simplicity of celestial mechanics.

Neither has this conception been useless; it has rendered us an
inestimable service, since it has contributed to make precise the
fundamental notion of the physical law.

I will explain myself; how did the ancients understand law? It was for
them an internal harmony, static, so to say, and immutable; or else it
was like a model that nature tried to imitate. For us a law is something
quite different; it is a constant relation between the phenomenon of
to-day and that of to-morrow; in a word, it is a differential equation.

Behold the ideal form of physical law; well, it is Newton's law which
first clothed it forth. If then one has acclimated this form in physics,
it is precisely by copying as far as possible this law of Newton, that
is by imitating celestial mechanics. This is, moreover, the idea I have
tried to bring out in Chapter VI.

_The Physics of the Principles._--Nevertheless, a day arrived when the
conception of central forces no longer appeared sufficient, and this is
the first of those crises of which I just now spoke.

What was done then? The attempt to penetrate into the detail of the
structure of the universe, to isolate the pieces of this vast mechanism,
to analyze one by one the forces which put them in motion, was
abandoned, and we were content to take as guides certain general
principles the express object of which is to spare us this minute study.
How so? Suppose we have before us any machine; the initial wheel work
and the final wheel work alone are visible, but the transmission, the
intermediary machinery by which the movement is communicated from one to
the other, is hidden in the interior and escapes our view; we do not
know whether the communication is made by gearing or by belts, by
connecting-rods or by other contrivances. Do we say that it is
impossible for us to understand anything about this machine so long as
we are not permitted to take it to pieces? You know well we do not, and
that the principle of the conservation of energy suffices to determine
for us the most interesting point. We easily ascertain that the final
wheel turns ten times less quickly than the initial wheel, since these
two wheels are visible; we are able thence to conclude that a couple
applied to the one will be balanced by a couple ten times greater
applied to the other. For that there is no need to penetrate the
mechanism of this equilibrium and to know how the forces compensate each
other in the interior of the machine; it suffices to be assured that
this compensation can not fail to occur.

Well, in regard to the universe, the principle of the conservation of
energy is able to render us the same service. The universe is also a
machine, much more complicated than all those of industry, of which
almost all the parts are profoundly hidden from us; but in observing the
motion of those that we can see, we are able, by the aid of this
principle, to draw conclusions which remain true whatever may be the
details of the invisible mechanism which animates them.

The principle of the conservation of energy, or Mayer's principle, is
certainly the most important, but it is not the only one; there are
others from which we can derive the same advantage. These are:

Carnot's principle, or the principle of the degradation of energy.

Newton's principle, or the principle of the equality of action and
reaction.

The principle of relativity, according to which the laws of physical
phenomena must be the same for a stationary observer as for an observer
carried along in a uniform motion of translation; so that we have not
and can not have any means of discerning whether or not we are carried
along in such a motion.

The principle of the conservation of mass, or Lavoisier's principle.

I will add the principle of least action.

The application of these five or six general principles to the different
physical phenomena is sufficient for our learning of them all that we
could reasonably hope to know of them. The most remarkable example of
this new mathematical physics is, beyond question, Maxwell's
electromagnetic theory of light.

We know nothing as to what the ether is, how its molecules are disposed,
whether they attract or repel each other; but we know that this medium
transmits at the same time the optical perturbations and the electrical
perturbations; we know that this transmission must take place in
conformity with the general principles of mechanics, and that suffices
us for the establishment of the equations of the electromagnetic field.

These principles are results of experiments boldly generalized; but they
seem to derive from their very generality a high degree of certainty. In
fact, the more general they are, the more frequent are the opportunities
to check them, and the verifications multiplying, taking the most
varied, the most unexpected forms, end by no longer leaving place for
doubt.

_Utility of the Old Physics._--Such is the second phase of the history
of mathematical physics and we have not yet emerged from it. Shall we
say that the first has been useless? that during fifty years science
went the wrong way, and that there is nothing left but to forget so many
accumulated efforts that a vicious conception condemned in advance to
failure? Not the least in the world. Do you think the second phase could
have come into existence without the first? The hypothesis of central
forces contained all the principles; it involved them as necessary
consequences; it involved both the conservation of energy and that of
masses, and the equality of action and reaction, and the law of least
action, which appeared, it is true, not as experimental truths, but as
theorems; the enunciation of which had at the same time something more
precise and less general than under their present form.

It is the mathematical physics of our fathers which has familiarized us
little by little with these various principles; which has habituated us
to recognize them under the different vestments in which they disguise
themselves. They have been compared with the data of experience, it has
been seen how it was necessary to modify their enunciation to adapt them
to these data; thereby they have been extended and consolidated. Thus
they came to be regarded as experimental truths; the conception of
central forces became then a useless support, or rather an
embarrassment, since it made the principles partake of its hypothetical
character.

The frames then have not broken, because they are elastic; but they have
enlarged; our fathers, who established them, did not labor in vain, and
we recognize in the science of to-day the general traits of the sketch
which they traced.



CHAPTER VIII

THE PRESENT CRISIS OF MATHEMATICAL PHYSICS


_The New Crisis._--Are we now about to enter upon a third period? Are we
on the eve of a second crisis? These principles on which we have built
all, are they about to crumble away in their turn? This has been for
some time a pertinent question.

When I speak thus, you no doubt think of radium, that grand
revolutionist of the present time, and in fact I shall come back to it
presently; but there is something else. It is not alone the conservation
of energy which is in question; all the other principles are equally in
danger, as we shall see in passing them successively in review.

_Carnot's Principle._--Let us commence with the principle of Carnot.
This is the only one which does not present itself as an immediate
consequence of the hypothesis of central forces; more than that, it
seems, if not to directly contradict that hypothesis, at least not to be
reconciled with it without a certain effort. If physical phenomena were
due exclusively to the movements of atoms whose mutual attraction
depended only on the distance, it seems that all these phenomena should
be reversible; if all the initial velocities were reversed, these atoms,
always subjected to the same forces, ought to go over their trajectories
in the contrary sense, just as the earth would describe in the
retrograde sense this same elliptic orbit which it describes in the
direct sense, if the initial conditions of its motion had been reversed.
On this account, if a physical phenomenon is possible, the inverse
phenomenon should be equally so, and one should be able to reascend the
course of time. Now, it is not so in nature, and this is precisely what
the principle of Carnot teaches us; heat can pass from the warm body to
the cold body; it is impossible afterward to make it take the inverse
route and to reestablish differences of temperature which have been
effaced. Motion can be wholly dissipated and transformed into heat by
friction; the contrary transformation can never be made except
partially.

We have striven to reconcile this apparent contradiction. If the world
tends toward uniformity, this is not because its ultimate parts, at
first unlike, tend to become less and less different; it is because,
shifting at random, they end by blending. For an eye which should
distinguish all the elements, the variety would remain always as great;
each grain of this dust preserves its originality and does not model
itself on its neighbors; but as the blend becomes more and more
intimate, our gross senses perceive only the uniformity. This is why,
for example, temperatures tend to a level, without the possibility of
going backwards.

A drop of wine falls into a glass of water; whatever may be the law of
the internal motion of the liquid, we shall soon see it colored of a
uniform rosy tint, and however much from this moment one may shake it
afterwards, the wine and the water do not seem capable of again
separating. Here we have the type of the irreversible physical
phenomenon: to hide a grain of barley in a heap of wheat, this is easy;
afterwards to find it again and get it out, this is practically
impossible. All this Maxwell and Boltzmann have explained; but the one
who has seen it most clearly, in a book too little read because it is a
little difficult to read, is Gibbs, in his `Elementary Principles of
Statistical Mechanics.'

For those who take this point of view, Carnot's principle is only an
imperfect principle, a sort of concession to the infirmity of our
senses; it is because our eyes are too gross that we do not distinguish
the elements of the blend; it is because our hands are too gross that we
can not force them to separate; the imaginary demon of Maxwell, who is
able to sort the molecules one by one, could well constrain the world to
return backward. Can it return of itself? That is not impossible; that
is only infinitely improbable. The chances are that we should wait a
long time for the concourse of circumstances which would permit a
retrogradation; but sooner or later they will occur, after years whose
number it would take millions of figures to write. These reservations,
however, all remained theoretic; they were not very disquieting, and
Carnot's principle retained all its practical value. But here the scene
changes. The biologist, armed with his microscope, long ago noticed in
his preparations irregular movements of little particles in suspension;
this is the Brownian movement. He first thought this was a vital
phenomenon, but soon he saw that the inanimate bodies danced with no
less ardor than the others; then he turned the matter over to the
physicists. Unhappily, the physicists remained long uninterested in this
question; one concentrates the light to illuminate the microscopic
preparation, thought they; with light goes heat; thence inequalities of
temperature and in the liquid interior currents which produce the
movements referred to. It occurred to M. Gouy to look more closely, and
he saw, or thought he saw, that this explanation is untenable, that the
movements become brisker as the particles are smaller, but that they are
not influenced by the mode of illumination. If then these movements
never cease, or rather are reborn without cease, without borrowing
anything from an external source of energy, what ought we to believe? To
be sure, we should not on this account renounce our belief in the
conservation of energy, but we see under our eyes now motion transformed
into heat by friction, now inversely heat changed into motion, and that
without loss since the movement lasts forever. This is the contrary of
Carnot's principle. If this be so, to see the world return backward, we
no longer have need of the infinitely keen eye of Maxwell's demon; our
microscope suffices. Bodies too large, those, for example, which are a
tenth of a millimeter, are hit from all sides by moving atoms, but they
do not budge, because these shocks are very numerous and the law of
chance makes them compensate each other; but the smaller particles
receive too few shocks for this compensation to take place with
certainty and are incessantly knocked about. And behold already one of
our principles in peril.

_The Principle of Relativity._--Let us pass to the principle of
relativity; this not only is confirmed by daily experience, not only is
it a necessary consequence of the hypothesis of central forces, but it
is irresistibly imposed upon our good sense, and yet it also is
assailed. Consider two electrified bodies; though they seem to us at
rest, they are both carried along by the motion of the earth; an
electric charge in motion, Rowland has taught us, is equivalent to a
current; these two charged bodies are, therefore, equivalent to two
parallel currents of the same sense and these two currents should
attract each other. In measuring this attraction, we shall measure the
velocity of the earth; not its velocity in relation to the sun or the
fixed stars, but its absolute velocity.

I well know what will be said: It is not its absolute velocity that is
measured, it is its velocity in relation to the ether. How
unsatisfactory that is! Is it not evident that from the principle so
understood we could no longer infer anything? It could no longer tell us
anything just because it would no longer fear any contradiction. If we
succeed in measuring anything, we shall always be free to say that this
is not the absolute velocity, and if it is not the velocity in relation
to the ether, it might always be the velocity in relation to some new
unknown fluid with which we might fill space.

Indeed, experiment has taken upon itself to ruin this interpretation of
the principle of relativity; all attempts to measure the velocity of the
earth in relation to the ether have led to negative results. This time
experimental physics has been more faithful to the principle than
mathematical physics; the theorists, to put in accord their other
general views, would not have spared it; but experiment has been
stubborn in confirming it. The means have been varied; finally Michelson
pushed precision to its last limits; nothing came of it. It is precisely
to explain this obstinacy that the mathematicians are forced to-day to
employ all their ingenuity.

Their task was not easy, and if Lorentz has got through it, it is only
by accumulating hypotheses.

The most ingenious idea was that of local time. Imagine two observers
who wish to adjust their timepieces by optical signals; they exchange
signals, but as they know that the transmission of light is not
instantaneous, they are careful to cross them. When station B perceives
the signal from station A, its clock should not mark the same hour as
that of station A at the moment of sending the signal, but this hour
augmented by a constant representing the duration of the transmission.
Suppose, for example, that station A sends its signal when its clock
marks the hour _O_, and that station B perceives it when its clock marks
the hour _t_. The clocks are adjusted if the slowness equal to _t_
represents the duration of the transmission, and to verify it, station B
sends in its turn a signal when its clock marks _O_; then station A
should perceive it when its clock marks _t_. The timepieces are then
adjusted.

And in fact they mark the same hour at the same physical instant, but on
the one condition, that the two stations are fixed. Otherwise the
duration of the transmission will not be the same in the two senses,
since the station A, for example, moves forward to meet the optical
perturbation emanating from B, whereas the station B flees before the
perturbation emanating from A. The watches adjusted in that way will not
mark, therefore, the true time; they will mark what may be called the
_local time_, so that one of them will be slow of the other. It matters
little, since we have no means of perceiving it. All the phenomena which
happen at A, for example, will be late, but all will be equally so, and
the observer will not perceive it, since his watch is slow; so, as the
principle of relativity requires, he will have no means of knowing
whether he is at rest or in absolute motion.

Unhappily, that does not suffice, and complementary hypotheses are
necessary; it is necessary to admit that bodies in motion undergo a
uniform contraction in the sense of the motion. One of the diameters of
the earth, for example, is shrunk by one two-hundred-millionth in
consequence of our planet's motion, while the other diameter retains its
normal length. Thus the last little differences are compensated. And
then, there is still the hypothesis about forces. Forces, whatever be
their origin, gravity as well as elasticity, would be reduced in a
certain proportion in a world animated by a uniform translation; or,
rather, this would happen for the components perpendicular to the
translation; the components parallel would not change. Resume, then, our
example of two electrified bodies; these bodies repel each other, but at
the same time if all is carried along in a uniform translation, they are
equivalent to two parallel currents of the same sense which attract each
other. This electrodynamic attraction diminishes, therefore, the
electrostatic repulsion, and the total repulsion is feebler than if the
two bodies were at rest. But since to measure this repulsion we must
balance it by another force, and all these other forces are reduced in
the same proportion, we perceive nothing. Thus all seems arranged, but
are all the doubts dissipated? What would happen if one could
communicate by non-luminous signals whose velocity of propagation
differed from that of light? If, after having adjusted the watches by
the optical procedure, we wished to verify the adjustment by the aid of
these new signals, we should observe discrepancies which would render
evident the common translation of the two stations. And are such signals
inconceivable, if we admit with Laplace that universal gravitation is
transmitted a million times more rapidly than light?

Thus, the principle of relativity has been valiantly defended in these
latter times, but the very energy of the defense proves how serious was
the attack.

_Newton's Principle._--Let us speak now of the principle of Newton, on
the equality of action and reaction. This is intimately bound up with
the preceding, and it seems indeed that the fall of the one would
involve that of the other. Thus we must not be astonished to find here
the same difficulties.

Electrical phenomena, according to the theory of Lorentz, are due to the
displacements of little charged particles, called electrons, immersed in
the medium we call ether. The movements of these electrons produce
perturbations in the neighboring ether; these perturbations propagate
themselves in every direction with the velocity of light, and in turn
other electrons, originally at rest, are made to vibrate when the
perturbation reaches the parts of the ether which touch them. The
electrons, therefore, act on one another, but this action is not direct,
it is accomplished through the ether as intermediary. Under these
conditions can there be compensation between action and reaction, at
least for an observer who should take account only of the movements of
matter, that is, of the electrons, and who should be ignorant of those
of the ether that he could not see? Evidently not. Even if the
compensation should be exact, it could not be simultaneous. The
perturbation is propagated with a finite velocity; it, therefore,
reaches the second electron only when the first has long ago entered
upon its rest. This second electron, therefore, will undergo, after a
delay, the action of the first, but will certainly not at that moment
react upon it, since around this first electron nothing any longer
budges.

The analysis of the facts permits us to be still more precise. Imagine,
for example, a Hertzian oscillator, like those used in wireless
telegraphy; it sends out energy in every direction; but we can provide
it with a parabolic mirror, as Hertz did with his smallest oscillators,
so as to send all the energy produced in a single direction. What
happens then according to the theory? The apparatus recoils, as if it
were a cannon and the projected energy a ball; and that is contrary to
the principle of Newton, since our projectile here has no mass, it is
not matter, it is energy. The case is still the same, moreover, with a
beacon light provided with a reflector, since light is nothing but a
perturbation of the electromagnetic field. This beacon light should
recoil as if the light it sends out were a projectile. What is the force
that should produce this recoil? It is what is called the
Maxwell-Bartholi pressure. It is very minute, and it has been difficult
to put it in evidence even with the most sensitive radiometers; but it
suffices that it exists.

If all the energy issuing from our oscillator falls on a receiver, this
will act as if it had received a mechanical shock, which will represent
in a sense the compensation of the oscillator's recoil; the reaction
will be equal to the action, but it will not be simultaneous; the
receiver will move on, but not at the moment when the oscillator
recoils. If the energy propagates itself indefinitely without
encountering a receiver, the compensation will never occur.

Shall we say that the space which separates the oscillator from the
receiver and which the perturbation must pass over in going from the one
to the other is not void, that it is full not only of ether, but of air,
or even in the interplanetary spaces of some fluid subtile but still
ponderable; that this matter undergoes the shock like the receiver at
the moment when the energy reaches it, and recoils in its turn when the
perturbation quits it? That would save Newton's principle, but that is
not true. If energy in its diffusion remained always attached to some
material substratum, then matter in motion would carry along light with
it, and Fizeau has demonstrated that it does nothing of the sort, at
least for air. Michelson and Morley have since confirmed this. It might
be supposed also that the movements of matter proper are exactly
compensated by those of the ether; but that would lead us to the same
reflections as before now. The principle so understood will explain
everything, since, whatever might be the visible movements, we always
could imagine hypothetical movements which compensate them. But if it is
able to explain everything, this is because it does not enable us to
foresee anything; it does not enable us to decide between the different
possible hypotheses, since it explains everything beforehand. It
therefore becomes useless.

And then the suppositions that it would be necessary to make on the
movements of the ether are not very satisfactory. If the electric
charges double, it would be natural to imagine that the velocities of
the diverse atoms of ether double also; but, for the compensation, it
would be necessary that the mean velocity of the ether quadruple.

This is why I have long thought that these consequences of theory,
contrary to Newton's principle, would end some day by being abandoned,
and yet the recent experiments on the movements of the electrons issuing
from radium seem rather to confirm them.

_Lavoisier's Principle._--I arrive at the principle of Lavoisier on the
conservation of mass. Certainly, this is one not to be touched without
unsettling all mechanics. And now certain persons think that it seems
true to us only because in mechanics merely moderate velocities are
considered, but that it would cease to be true for bodies animated by
velocities comparable to that of light. Now these velocities are
believed at present to have been realized; the cathode rays and those of
radium may be formed of very minute particles or of electrons which are
displaced with velocities smaller no doubt than that of light, but which
might be its one tenth or one third.

These rays can be deflected, whether by an electric field, or by a
magnetic field, and we are able, by comparing these deflections, to
measure at the same time the velocity of the electrons and their mass
(or rather the relation of their mass to their charge). But when it was
seen that these velocities approached that of light, it was decided that
a correction was necessary. These molecules, being electrified, can not
be displaced without agitating the ether; to put them in motion it is
necessary to overcome a double inertia, that of the molecule itself and
that of the ether. The total or apparent mass that one measures is
composed, therefore, of two parts: the real or mechanical mass of the
molecule and the electrodynamic mass representing the inertia of the
ether.

The calculations of Abraham and the experiments of Kaufmann have then
shown that the mechanical mass, properly so called, is null, and that
the mass of the electrons, or, at least, of the negative electrons, is
of exclusively electrodynamic origin. This is what forces us to change
the definition of mass; we can not any longer distinguish mechanical
mass and electrodynamic mass, since then the first would vanish; there
is no mass other than electrodynamic inertia. But in this case the mass
can no longer be constant; it augments with the velocity, and it even
depends on the direction, and a body animated by a notable velocity will
not oppose the same inertia to the forces which tend to deflect it from
its route, as to those which tend to accelerate or to retard its
progress.

There is still a resource; the ultimate elements of bodies are
electrons, some charged negatively, the others charged positively. The
negative electrons have no mass, this is understood; but the positive
electrons, from the little we know of them, seem much greater. Perhaps
they have, besides their electrodynamic mass, a true mechanical mass.
The real mass of a body would, then, be the sum of the mechanical masses
of its positive electrons, the negative electrons not counting; mass so
defined might still be constant.

Alas! this resource also evades us. Recall what we have said of the
principle of relativity and of the efforts made to save it. And it is
not merely a principle which it is a question of saving, it is the
indubitable results of the experiments of Michelson.

Well, as was above seen, Lorentz, to account for these results, was
obliged to suppose that all forces, whatever their origin, were reduced
in the same proportion in a medium animated by a uniform translation;
this is not sufficient; it is not enough that this take place for the
real forces, it must also be the same for the forces of inertia; it is
therefore necessary, he says, that _the masses of all the particles be
influenced by a translation to the same degree as the electromagnetic
masses of the electrons_.

So the mechanical masses must vary in accordance with the same laws as
the electrodynamic masses; they can not, therefore, be constant.

Need I point out that the fall of Lavoisier's principle involves that of
Newton's? This latter signifies that the center of gravity of an
isolated system moves in a straight line; but if there is no longer a
constant mass, there is no longer a center of gravity, we no longer know
even what this is. This is why I said above that the experiments on the
cathode rays appeared to justify the doubts of Lorentz concerning
Newton's principle.

From all these results, if they were confirmed, would arise an entirely
new mechanics, which would be, above all, characterized by this fact,
that no velocity could surpass that of light,[9] any more than any
temperature can fall below absolute zero.

  [9] Because bodies would oppose an increasing inertia to the causes
      which would tend to accelerate their motion; and this inertia
      would become infinite when one approached the velocity of light.

No more for an observer, carried along himself in a translation he does
not suspect, could any apparent velocity surpass that of light; and this
would be then a contradiction, if we did not recall that this observer
would not use the same clocks as a fixed observer, but, indeed, clocks
marking 'local time.'

Here we are then facing a question I content myself with stating. If
there is no longer any mass, what becomes of Newton's law? Mass has two
aspects: it is at the same time a coefficient of inertia and an
attracting mass entering as factor into Newtonian attraction. If the
coefficient of inertia is not constant, can the attracting mass be? That
is the question.

_Mayer's Principle._--At least, the principle of the conservation of
energy yet remained to us, and this seemed more solid. Shall I recall to
you how it was in its turn thrown into discredit? This event has made
more noise than the preceding, and it is in all the memoirs. From the
first words of Becquerel, and, above all, when the Curies had discovered
radium, it was seen that every radioactive body was an inexhaustible
source of radiation. Its activity seemed to subsist without alteration
throughout the months and the years. This was in itself a strain on the
principles; these radiations were in fact energy, and from the same
morsel of radium this issued and forever issued. But these quantities of
energy were too slight to be measured; at least that was the belief and
we were not much disquieted.

The scene changed when Curie bethought himself to put radium in a
calorimeter; it was then seen that the quantity of heat incessantly
created was very notable.

The explanations proposed were numerous; but in such case we can not
say, the more the better. In so far as no one of them has prevailed over
the others, we can not be sure there is a good one among them. Since
some time, however, one of these explanations seems to be getting the
upper hand and we may reasonably hope that we hold the key to the
mystery.

Sir W. Ramsay has striven to show that radium is in process of
transformation, that it contains a store of energy enormous but not
inexhaustible. The transformation of radium then would produce a million
times more heat than all known transformations; radium would wear itself
out in 1,250 years; this is quite short, and you see that we are at
least certain to have this point settled some hundreds of years from
now. While waiting, our doubts remain.



CHAPTER IX

THE FUTURE OF MATHEMATICAL PHYSICS


_The Principles and Experiment._--In the midst of so much ruin, what
remains standing? The principle of least action is hitherto intact, and
Larmor appears to believe that it will long survive the others; in
reality, it is still more vague and more general.

In presence of this general collapse of the principles, what attitude
will mathematical physics take? And first, before too much excitement,
it is proper to ask if all that is really true. All these derogations to
the principles are encountered only among infinitesimals; the microscope
is necessary to see the Brownian movement; electrons are very light;
radium is very rare, and one never has more than some milligrams of it
at a time. And, then, it may be asked whether, besides the infinitesimal
seen, there was not another infinitesimal unseen counterpoise to the
first.

So there is an interlocutory question, and, as it seems, only experiment
can solve it. We shall, therefore, only have to hand over the matter to
the experimenters, and, while waiting for them to finally decide the
debate, not to preoccupy ourselves with these disquieting problems, and
to tranquilly continue our work as if the principles were still
uncontested. Certes, we have much to do without leaving the domain where
they may be applied in all security; we have enough to employ our
activity during this period of doubts.

_The Rôle of the Analyst._--And as to these doubts, is it indeed true
that we can do nothing to disembarrass science of them? It must indeed
be said, it is not alone experimental physics that has given birth to
them; mathematical physics has well contributed. It is the experimenters
who have seen radium throw out energy, but it is the theorists who have
put in evidence all the difficulties raised by the propagation of light
across a medium in motion; but for these it is probable we should not
have become conscious of them. Well, then, if they have done their best
to put us into this embarrassment, it is proper also that they help us
to get out of it.

They must subject to critical examination all these new views I have
just outlined before you, and abandon the principles only after having
made a loyal effort to save them. What can they do in this sense? That
is what I will try to explain.

It is a question before all of endeavoring to obtain a more satisfactory
theory of the electrodynamics of bodies in motion. It is there
especially, as I have sufficiently shown above, that difficulties
accumulate. It is useless to heap up hypotheses, we can not satisfy all
the principles at once; so far, one has succeeded in safeguarding some
only on condition of sacrificing the others; but all hope of obtaining
better results is not yet lost. Let us take, then, the theory of
Lorentz, turn it in all senses, modify it little by little, and perhaps
everything will arrange itself.

Thus in place of supposing that bodies in motion undergo a contraction
in the sense of the motion, and that this contraction is the same
whatever be the nature of these bodies and the forces to which they are
otherwise subjected, could we not make a more simple and natural
hypothesis? We might imagine, for example, that it is the ether which is
modified when it is in relative motion in reference to the material
medium which penetrates it, that, when it is thus modified, it no longer
transmits perturbations with the same velocity in every direction. It
might transmit more rapidly those which are propagated parallel to the
motion of the medium, whether in the same sense or in the opposite
sense, and less rapidly those which are propagated perpendicularly. The
wave surfaces would no longer be spheres, but ellipsoids, and we could
dispense with that extraordinary contraction of all bodies.

I cite this only as an example, since the modifications that might be
essayed would be evidently susceptible of infinite variation.

_Aberration and Astronomy._--It is possible also that astronomy may some
day furnish us data on this point; she it was in the main who raised the
question in making us acquainted with the phenomenon of the aberration
of light. If we make crudely the theory of aberration, we reach a very
curious result. The apparent positions of the stars differ from their
real positions because of the earth's motion, and as this motion is
variable, these apparent positions vary. The real position we can not
ascertain, but we can observe the variations of the apparent position.
The observations of the aberration show us, therefore, not the earth's
motion, but the variations of this motion; they can not, therefore, give
us information about the absolute motion of the earth.

At least this is true in first approximation, but the case would be no
longer the same if we could appreciate the thousandths of a second. Then
it would be seen that the amplitude of the oscillation depends not alone
on the variation of the motion, a variation which is well known, since
it is the motion of our globe on its elliptic orbit, but on the mean
value of this motion, so that the constant of aberration would not be
quite the same for all the stars, and the differences would tell us the
absolute motion of the earth in space.

This, then, would be, under another form, the ruin of the principle of
relativity. We are far, it is true, from appreciating the thousandth of
a second, but, after all, say some, the earth's total absolute velocity
is perhaps much greater than its relative velocity with respect to the
sun. If, for example, it were 300 kilometers per second in place of 30,
this would suffice to make the phenomenon observable.

I believe that in reasoning thus one admits a too simple theory of
aberration. Michelson has shown us, I have told you, that the physical
procedures are powerless to put in evidence absolute motion; I am
persuaded that the same will be true of the astronomic procedures,
however far precision be carried.

However that may be, the data astronomy will furnish us in this regard
will some day be precious to the physicist. Meanwhile, I believe that
the theorists, recalling the experience of Michelson, may anticipate a
negative result, and that they would accomplish a useful work in
constructing a theory of aberration which would explain this in advance.

_Electrons and Spectra._--This dynamics of electrons can be approached
from many sides, but among the ways leading thither is one which has
been somewhat neglected, and yet this is one of those which promise us
the most surprises. It is movements of electrons which produce the lines
of the emission spectra; this is proved by the Zeeman effect; in an
incandescent body what vibrates is sensitive to the magnet, therefore
electrified. This is a very important first point, but no one has gone
farther. Why are the lines of the spectrum distributed in accordance
with a regular law? These laws have been studied by the experimenters in
their least details; they are very precise and comparatively simple. A
first study of these distributions recalls the harmonics encountered in
acoustics; but the difference is great. Not only are the numbers of
vibrations not the successive multiples of a single number, but we do
not even find anything analogous to the roots of those transcendental
equations to which we are led by so many problems of mathematical
physics: that of the vibrations of an elastic body of any form, that of
the Hertzian oscillations in a generator of any form, the problem of
Fourier for the cooling of a solid body.

The laws are simpler, but they are of wholly other nature, and to cite
only one of these differences, for the harmonics of high order, the
number of vibrations tends toward a finite limit, instead of increasing
indefinitely.

That has not yet been accounted for, and I believe that there we have
one of the most important secrets of nature. A Japanese physicist, M.
Nagaoka, has recently proposed an explanation; according to him, atoms
are composed of a large positive electron surrounded by a ring formed of
a great number of very small negative electrons. Such is the planet
Saturn with its rings. This is a very interesting attempt, but not yet
wholly satisfactory; this attempt should be renewed. We will penetrate,
so to speak, into the inmost recess of matter. And from the particular
point of view which we to-day occupy, when we know why the vibrations of
incandescent bodies differ thus from ordinary elastic vibrations, why
the electrons do not behave like the matter which is familiar to us, we
shall better comprehend the dynamics of electrons and it will be perhaps
more easy for us to reconcile it with the principles.

_Conventions Preceding Experiment._--Suppose, now, that all these
efforts fail, and, after all, I do not believe they will, what must be
done? Will it be necessary to seek to mend the broken principles by
giving what we French call a _coup de pouce_? That evidently is always
possible, and I retract nothing of what I have said above.

Have you not written, you might say if you wished to seek a quarrel with
me--have you not written that the principles, though of experimental
origin, are now unassailable by experiment because they have become
conventions? And now you have just told us that the most recent
conquests of experiment put these principles in danger.

Well, formerly I was right and to-day I am not wrong. Formerly I was
right, and what is now happening is a new proof of it. Take, for
example, the calorimetric experiment of Curie on radium. Is it possible
to reconcile it with the principle of the conservation of energy? This
has been attempted in many ways. But there is among them one I should
like you to notice; this is not the explanation which tends to-day to
prevail, but it is one of those which have been proposed. It has been
conjectured that radium was only an intermediary, that it only stored
radiations of unknown nature which flashed through space in every
direction, traversing all bodies, save radium, without being altered by
this passage and without exercising any action upon them. Radium alone
took from them a little of their energy and afterward gave it out to us
in various forms.

What an advantageous explanation, and how convenient! First, it is
unverifiable and thus irrefutable. Then again it will serve to account
for any derogation whatever to Mayer's principle; it answers in advance
not only the objection of Curie, but all the objections that future
experimenters might accumulate. This new and unknown energy would serve
for everything.

This is just what I said, and therewith we are shown that our principle
is unassailable by experiment.

But then, what have we gained by this stroke? The principle is intact,
but thenceforth of what use is it? It enabled us to foresee that in such
or such circumstance we could count on such a total quantity of energy;
it limited us; but now that this indefinite provision of new energy is
placed at our disposal, we are no longer limited by anything; and, as I
have written in 'Science and Hypothesis,' if a principle ceases to be
fecund, experiment without contradicting it directly will nevertheless
have condemned it.

_Future Mathematical Physics._--This, therefore, is not what would have
to be done; it would be necessary to rebuild anew. If we were reduced to
this necessity; we could moreover console ourselves. It would not be
necessary thence to conclude that science can weave only a Penelope's
web, that it can raise only ephemeral structures, which it is soon
forced to demolish from top to bottom with its own hands.

As I have said, we have already passed through a like crisis. I have
shown you that in the second mathematical physics, that of the
principles, we find traces of the first, that of central forces; it will
be just the same if we must know a third. Just so with the animal that
exuviates, that breaks its too narrow carapace and makes itself a fresh
one; under the new envelope one will recognize the essential traits of
the organism which have persisted.

We can not foresee in what way we are about to expand; perhaps it is the
kinetic theory of gases which is about to undergo development and serve
as model to the others. Then the facts which first appeared to us as
simple thereafter would be merely resultants of a very great number of
elementary facts which only the laws of chance would make cooperate for
a common end. Physical law would then assume an entirely new aspect; it
would no longer be solely a differential equation, it would take the
character of a statistical law.

Perhaps, too, we shall have to construct an entirely new mechanics that
we only succeed in catching a glimpse of, where, inertia increasing with
the velocity, the velocity of light would become an impassable limit.
The ordinary mechanics, more simple, would remain a first approximation,
since it would be true for velocities not too great, so that the old
dynamics would still be found under the new. We should not have to
regret having believed in the principles, and even, since velocities too
great for the old formulas would always be only exceptional, the surest
way in practise would be still to act as if we continued to believe in
them. They are so useful, it would be necessary to keep a place for
them. To determine to exclude them altogether would be to deprive
oneself of a precious weapon. I hasten to say in conclusion that we are
not yet there, and as yet nothing proves that the principles will not
come forth from out the fray victorious and intact.[10]

  [10] These considerations on mathematical physics are borrowed from
       my St. Louis address.



PART III


THE OBJECTIVE VALUE OF SCIENCE



CHAPTER X

IS SCIENCE ARTIFICIAL?


1. _The Philosophy of M. LeRoy_

There are many reasons for being sceptics; should we push this
scepticism to the very end or stop on the way? To go to the end is the
most tempting solution, the easiest and that which many have adopted,
despairing of saving anything from the shipwreck.

Among the writings inspired by this tendency it is proper to place in
the first rank those of M. LeRoy. This thinker is not only a philosopher
and a writer of the greatest merit, but he has acquired a deep knowledge
of the exact and physical sciences, and even has shown rare powers of
mathematical invention. Let us recapitulate in a few words his doctrine,
which has given rise to numerous discussions.

Science consists only of conventions, and to this circumstance solely
does it owe its apparent certitude; the facts of science and, _a
fortiori_, its laws are the artificial work of the scientist; science
therefore can teach us nothing of the truth; it can only serve us as
rule of action.

Here we recognize the philosophic theory known under the name of
nominalism; all is not false in this theory; its legitimate domain must
be left it, but out of this it should not be allowed to go.

This is not all; M. LeRoy's doctrine is not only nominalistic; it has
besides another characteristic which it doubtless owes to M. Bergson, it
is anti-intellectualistic. According to M. LeRoy, the intellect deforms
all it touches, and that is still more true of its necessary instrument
'discourse.' There is reality only in our fugitive and changing
impressions, and even this reality, when touched, vanishes.

And yet M. LeRoy is not a sceptic; if he regards the intellect as
incurably powerless, it is only to give more scope to other sources of
knowledge, to the heart, for instance, to sentiment, to instinct or to
faith.

However great my esteem for M. LeRoy's talent, whatever the ingenuity of
this thesis, I can not wholly accept it. Certes, I am in accord on many
points with M. LeRoy, and he has even cited, in support of his view,
various passages of my writings which I am by no means disposed to
reject. I think myself only the more bound to explain why I can not go
with him all the way.

M. LeRoy often complains of being accused of scepticism. He could not
help being, though this accusation is probably unjust. Are not
appearances against him? Nominalist in doctrine, but realist at heart,
he seems to escape absolute nominalism only by a desperate act of faith.

The fact is that anti-intellectualistic philosophy in rejecting analysis
and 'discourse,' just by that condemns itself to being intransmissible;
it is a philosophy essentially internal, or, at the very least, only its
negations can be transmitted; what wonder then that for an external
observer it takes the shape of scepticism?

Therein lies the weak point of this philosophy; if it strives to remain
faithful to itself, its energy is spent in a negation and a cry of
enthusiasm. Each author may repeat this negation and this cry, may vary
their form, but without adding anything.

And, yet, would it not be more logical in remaining silent? See, you
have written long articles; for that, it was necessary to use words. And
therein have you not been much more 'discursive' and consequently much
farther from life and truth than the animal who simply lives without
philosophizing? Would not this animal be the true philosopher?

However, because no painter has made a perfect portrait, should we
conclude that the best painting is not to paint? When a zoologist
dissects an animal, certainly he 'alters it.' Yes, in dissecting it, he
condemns himself to never know all of it; but in not dissecting it, he
would condemn himself to never know anything of it and consequently to
never see anything of it.

Certes, in man are other forces besides his intellect; no one has ever
been mad enough to deny that. The first comer makes these blind forces
act or lets them act; the philosopher must _speak_ of them; to speak of
them, he must know of them the little that can be known, he should
therefore _see_ them act. How? With what eyes, if not with his
intellect? Heart, instinct, may guide it, but not render it useless;
they may direct the look, but not replace the eye. It may be granted
that the heart is the workman, and the intellect only the instrument.
Yet is it an instrument not to be done without, if not for action, at
least for philosophizing? Therefore a philosopher really
anti-intellectualistic is impossible. Perhaps we shall have to declare
for the supremacy of action; always it is our intellect which will thus
conclude; in allowing precedence to action it will thus retain the
superiority of the thinking reed. This also is a supremacy not to be
disdained.

Pardon these brief reflections and pardon also their brevity, scarcely
skimming the question. The process of intellectualism is not the subject
I wish to treat: I wish to speak of science, and about it there is no
doubt; by definition, so to speak, it will be intellectualistic or it
will not be at all. Precisely the question is, whether it will be.


2. _Science, Rule of Action_

For M. LeRoy, science is only a rule of action. We are powerless to know
anything and yet we are launched, we must act, and at all hazards we
have established rules. It is the aggregate of these rules that is
called science.

It is thus that men, desirous of diversion, have instituted rules of
play, like those of tric-trac for instance, which, better than science
itself, could rely upon the proof by universal consent. It is thus
likewise that, unable to choose, but forced to choose, we toss up a
coin, head or tail to win.

The rule of tric-trac is indeed a rule of action like science, but does
any one think the comparison just and not see the difference? The rules
of the game are arbitrary conventions and the contrary convention might
have been adopted, _which would have been none the less good_. On the
contrary, science is a rule of action which is successful, generally at
least, and I add, while the contrary rule would not have succeeded.

If I say, to make hydrogen cause an acid to act on zinc, I formulate a
rule which succeeds; I could have said, make distilled water act on
gold; that also would have been a rule, only it would not have
succeeded. If, therefore, scientific 'recipes' have a value, as rule of
action, it is because we know they succeed, generally at least. But to
know this is to know something and then why tell us we can know nothing?

Science foresees, and it is because it foresees that it can be useful
and serve as rule of action. I well know that its previsions are often
contradicted by the event; that shows that science is imperfect, and if
I add that it will always remain so, I am certain that this is a
prevision which, at least, will never be contradicted. Always the
scientist is less often mistaken than a prophet who should predict at
random. Besides the progress though slow is continuous, so that
scientists, though more and more bold, are less and less misled. This is
little, but it is enough.

I well know that M. LeRoy has somewhere said that science was mistaken
oftener than one thought, that comets sometimes played tricks on
astronomers, that scientists, who apparently are men, did not willingly
speak of their failures, and that, if they should speak of them, they
would have to count more defeats than victories.

That day, M. LeRoy evidently overreached himself. If science did not
succeed, it could not serve as rule of action; whence would it get its
value? Because it is 'lived,' that is, because we love it and believe in
it? The alchemists had recipes for making gold, they loved them and had
faith in them, and yet our recipes are the good ones, although our faith
be less lively, because they succeed.

There is no escape from this dilemma; either science does not enable us
to foresee, and then it is valueless as rule of action; or else it
enables us to foresee, in a fashion more or less imperfect, and then it
is not without value as means of knowledge.

It should not even be said that action is the goal of science; should we
condemn studies of the star Sirius, under pretext that we shall probably
never exercise any influence on that star? To my eyes, on the contrary,
it is the knowledge which is the end, and the action which is the means.
If I felicitate myself on the industrial development, it is not alone
because it furnishes a facile argument to the advocates of science; it
is above all because it gives to the scientist faith in himself and also
because it offers him an immense field of experience where he clashes
against forces too colossal to be tampered with. Without this ballast,
who knows whether he would not quit solid ground, seduced by the mirage
of some scholastic novelty, or whether he would not despair, believing
he had fashioned only a dream?


3. _The Crude Fact and the Scientific Fact_

What was most paradoxical in M. LeRoy's thesis was that affirmation that
_the scientist creates the fact_; this was at the same time its
essential point and it is one of those which have been most discussed.

Perhaps, says he (I well believe that this was a concession), it is not
the scientist that creates the fact in the rough; it is at least he who
creates the scientific fact.

This distinction between the fact in the rough and the scientific fact
does not by itself appear to me illegitimate. But I complain first that
the boundary has not been traced either exactly or precisely; and then
that the author has seemed to suppose that the crude fact, not being
scientific, is outside of science.

Finally, I can not admit that the scientist creates without restraint
the scientific fact, since it is the crude fact which imposes it upon
him.

The examples given by M. LeRoy have greatly astonished me. The first is
taken from the notion of atom. The atom chosen as example of fact! I
avow that this choice has so disconcerted me that I prefer to say
nothing about it. I have evidently misunderstood the author's thought
and I could not fruitfully discuss it.

The second case taken as example is that of an eclipse where the crude
phenomenon is a play of light and shadow, but where the astronomer can
not intervene without introducing two foreign elements, to wit, a clock
and Newton's law.

Finally, M. LeRoy cites the rotation of the earth; it has been answered:
but this is not a fact, and he has replied: it was one for Galileo, who
affirmed it, as for the inquisitor, who denied it. It always remains
that this is not a fact in the same sense as those just spoken of and
that to give them the same name is to expose one's self to many
confusions.

Here then are four degrees:

1º. It grows dark, says the clown.

2º. The eclipse happened at nine o'clock, says the astronomer.

3º. The eclipse happened at the time deducible from the tables
constructed according to Newton's law, says he again.

4º. That results from the earth's turning around the sun, says Galileo
finally.

Where then is the boundary between the fact in the rough and the
scientific fact? To read M. LeRoy one would believe that it is between
the first and the second stage, but who does not see that there is a
greater distance from the second to the third, and still more from the
third to the fourth.

Allow me to cite two examples which perhaps will enlighten us a little.

I observe the deviation of a galvanometer by the aid of a movable mirror
which projects a luminous image or spot on a divided scale. The crude
fact is this: I see the spot displace itself on the scale, and the
scientific fact is this: a current passes in the circuit.

Or again: when I make an experiment I should subject the result to
certain corrections, because I know I must have made errors. These
errors are of two kinds, some are accidental and these I shall correct
by taking the mean; the others are systematic and I shall be able to
correct those only by a thorough study of their causes. The first result
obtained is then the fact in the rough, while the scientific fact is the
final result after the finished corrections.

Reflecting on this latter example, we are led to subdivide our second
stage, and in place of saying:

2. The eclipse happened at nine o'clock, we shall say:

2_a_. The eclipse happened when my clock pointed to nine, and

2_b_. My clock being ten minutes slow, the eclipse happened at ten
minutes past nine.

And this is not all: the first stage also should be subdivided, and not
between these two subdivisions will be the least distance; it is
necessary to distinguish between the impression of obscurity felt by one
witnessing an eclipse, and the affirmation: It grows dark, which this
impression extorts from him. In a sense it is the first which is the
only true fact in the rough, and the second is already a sort of
scientific fact.

Now then our scale has six stages, and even though there is no reason
for halting at this figure, there we shall stop.

What strikes me at the start is this. At the first of our six stages,
the fact, still completely in the rough, is, so to speak, individual, it
is completely distinct from all other possible facts. From the second
stage, already it is no longer the same. The enunciation of the fact
would suit an infinity of other facts. So soon as language intervenes, I
have at my command only a finite number of terms to express the shades,
in number infinite, that my impressions might cover. When I say: It
grows dark, that well expresses the impressions I feel in being present
at an eclipse; but even in obscurity a multitude of shades could be
imagined, and if, instead of that actually realized, had happened a
slightly different shade, yet I should still have enunciated this
_other_ fact by saying: It grows dark.

Second remark: even at the second stage, the enunciation of a fact can
only be _true or false_. This is not so of any proposition; if this
proposition is the enunciation of a convention, it can not be said that
this enunciation is _true_, in the proper sense of the word, since it
could not be true apart from me and is true only because I wish it to
be.

When, for instance, I say the unit for length is the meter, this is a
decree that I promulgate, it is not something ascertained which forces
itself upon me. It is the same, as I think I have elsewhere shown, when
it is a question, for example, of Euclid's postulate.

When I am asked: Is it growing dark? I always know whether I ought to
reply yes or no. Although an infinity of possible facts may be
susceptible of this same enunciation, it grows dark, I shall always
know whether the fact realized belongs or does not belong among those
which answer to this enunciation. Facts are classed in categories, and
if I am asked whether the fact that I ascertain belongs or does not
belong in such a category, I shall not hesitate.

Doubtless this classification is sufficiently arbitrary to leave a large
part to man's freedom or caprice. In a word, this classification is a
convention. _This convention being given_, if I am asked: Is such a fact
true? I shall always know what to answer, and my reply will be imposed
upon me by the witness of my senses.

If therefore, during an eclipse, it is asked: Is it growing dark? all
the world will answer yes. Doubtless those speaking a language where
bright was called dark, and dark bright, would answer no. But of what
importance is that?

In the same way, in mathematics, _when I have laid down the definitions,
and the postulates which are conventions_, a theorem henceforth can only
be true or false. But to answer the question: Is this theorem true? it
is no longer to the witness of my senses that I shall have recourse, but
to reasoning.

A statement of fact is always verifiable, and for the verification we
have recourse either to the witness of our senses, or to the memory of
this witness. This is properly what characterizes a fact. If you put the
question to me: Is such a fact true? I shall begin by asking you, if
there is occasion, to state precisely the conventions, by asking you, in
other words, what language you have spoken; then once settled on this
point, I shall interrogate my senses and shall answer yes or no. But it
will be my senses that will have made answer, it will not be _you_ when
you say to me: I have spoken to you in English or in French.

Is there something to change in all that when we pass to the following
stages? When I observe a galvanometer, as I have just said, if I ask an
ignorant visitor: Is the current passing? he looks at the wire to try to
see something pass; but if I put the same question to my assistant who
understands my language, he will know I mean: Does the spot move? and he
will look at the scale.

What difference is there then between the statement of a fact in the
rough and the statement of a scientific fact? The same difference as
between the statement of the same crude fact in French and in German.
The scientific statement is the translation of the crude statement into
a language which is distinguished above all from the common German or
French, because it is spoken by a very much smaller number of people.

Yet let us not go too fast. To measure a current I may use a very great
number of types of galvanometers or besides an electrodynamometer. And
then when I shall say there is running in this circuit a current of so
many amperes, that will mean: if I adapt to this circuit such a
galvanometer I shall see the spot come to the division _a_;
but that will mean equally: if I adapt to this circuit such an
electrodynamometer, I shall see the spot go to the division _b_. And
that will mean still many other things, because the current can manifest
itself not only by mechanical effects, but by effects chemical, thermal,
luminous, etc.

Here then is one same statement which suits a very great number of facts
absolutely different. Why? It is because I assume a law according to
which, whenever such a mechanical effect shall happen, such a chemical
effect will happen also. Previous experiments, very numerous, have never
shown this law to fail, and then I have understood that I could express
by the same statement two facts so invariably bound one to the other.

When I am asked: Is the current passing? I can understand that that
means: Will such a mechanical effect happen? But I can understand also:
Will such a chemical effect happen? I shall then verify either the
existence of the mechanical effect, or that of the chemical effect; that
will be indifferent, since in both cases the answer must be the same.

And if the law should one day be found false? If it was perceived that
the concordance of the two effects, mechanical and chemical, is not
constant? That day it would be necessary to change the scientific
language to free it from a grave ambiguity.

And after that? Is it thought that ordinary language by aid of which are
expressed the facts of daily life is exempt from ambiguity?

_Shall we thence conclude that the facts of daily life are the work of
the grammarians?_

You ask me: Is there a current? I try whether the mechanical effect
exists, I ascertain it and I answer: Yes, there is a current. You
understand at once that that means that the mechanical effect exists,
and that the chemical effect, that I have not investigated, exists
likewise. Imagine now, supposing an impossibility, the law we believe
true, not to be, and the chemical effect not to exist. Under this
hypothesis there will be two distinct facts, the one directly observed
and which is true, the other inferred and which is false. It may
strictly be said that we have created the second. So that error is the
part of man's personal collaboration in the creation of the scientific
fact.

But if we can say that the fact in question is false, is this not just
because it is not a free and arbitrary creation of our mind, a disguised
convention, in which case it would be neither true nor false. And in
fact it was verifiable; I had not made the verification, but I could
have made it. If I answered amiss, it was because I chose to reply too
quickly, without having asked nature, who alone knew the secret.

When, after an experiment, I correct the accidental and systematic
errors to bring out the scientific fact, the case is the same; the
scientific fact will never be anything but the crude fact translated
into another language. When I shall say: It is such an hour, that will
be a short way of saying: There is such a relation between the hour
indicated by my clock, and the hour it marked at the moment of the
passing of such a star and such another star across the meridian. And
this convention of language once adopted, when I shall be asked: Is it
such an hour? it will not depend upon me to answer yes or no.

Let us pass to the stage before the last: the eclipse happened at the
hour given by the tables deduced from Newton's laws. This is still a
convention of language which is perfectly clear for those who know
celestial mechanics or simply for those who have the tables calculated
by the astronomers. I am asked: Did the eclipse happen at the hour
predicted? I look in the nautical almanac, I see that the eclipse was
announced for nine o'clock and I understand that the question means: Did
the eclipse happen at nine o'clock? There still we have nothing to
change in our conclusions. _The scientific fact is only the crude fact
translated into a convenient language._

It is true that at the last stage things change. Does the earth rotate?
Is this a verifiable fact? Could Galileo and the Grand Inquisitor, to
settle the matter, appeal to the witness of their senses? On the
contrary, they were in accord about the appearances, and whatever had
been the accumulated experiences, they would have remained in accord
with regard to the appearances without ever agreeing on their
interpretation. It is just on that account that they were obliged to
have recourse to procedures of discussion so unscientific.

This is why I think they did not disagree about a _fact_: we have not
the right to give the same name to the rotation of the earth, which was
the object of their discussion, and to the facts crude or scientific we
have hitherto passed in review.

After what precedes, it seems superfluous to investigate whether the
fact in the rough is outside of science, because there can neither be
science without scientific fact, nor scientific fact without fact in the
rough, since the first is only the translation of the second.

And then, has one the right to say that the scientist creates the
scientific fact? First of all, he does not create it from nothing, since
he makes it with the fact in the rough. Consequently he does not make it
freely and _as he chooses_. However able the worker may be, his freedom
is always limited by the properties of the raw material on which he
works.

After all, what do you mean when you speak of this free creation of the
scientific fact and when you take as example the astronomer who
intervenes actively in the phenomenon of the eclipse by bringing his
clock? Do you mean: The eclipse happened at nine o'clock; but if the
astronomer had wished it to happen at ten, that depended only on him, he
had only to advance his clock an hour?

But the astronomer, in perpetrating that bad joke, would evidently have
been guilty of an equivocation. When he tells me: The eclipse happened
at nine, I understand that nine is the hour deduced from the crude
indication of the pendulum by the usual series of corrections. If he has
given me solely that crude indication, or if he has made corrections
contrary to the habitual rules, he has changed the language agreed upon
without forewarning me. If, on the contrary, he took care to forewarn
me, I have nothing to complain of, but then it is always the same fact
expressed in another language.

In sum, _all the scientist creates in a fact is the language in which he
enunciates it_. If he predicts a fact, he will employ this language, and
for all those who can speak and understand it, his prediction is free
from ambiguity. Moreover, this prediction once made, it evidently does
not depend upon him whether it is fulfilled or not.

What then remains of M. LeRoy's thesis? This remains: the scientist
intervenes actively in choosing the facts worth observing. An isolated
fact has by itself no interest; it becomes interesting if one has reason
to think that it may aid in the prediction of other facts; or better,
if, having been predicted, its verification is the confirmation of a
law. Who shall choose the facts which, corresponding to these
conditions, are worthy the freedom of the city in science? This is the
free activity of the scientist.

And that is not all. I have said that the scientific fact is the
translation of a crude fact into a certain language; I should add that
every scientific fact is formed of many crude facts. This is
sufficiently shown by the examples cited above. For instance, for the
hour of the eclipse my clock marked the hour [alpha] at the instant of
the eclipse; it marked the hour [beta] at the moment of the last transit
of the meridian of a certain star that we take as origin of right
ascensions; it marked the hour [gamma] at the moment of the preceding
transit of this same star. There are three distinct facts (still it will
be noticed that each of them results itself from two simultaneous facts
in the rough; but let us pass this over). In place of that I say: The
eclipse happened at the hour 24 ([alpha]-[beta])/([beta]-[gamma]), and
the three facts are combined in a single scientific fact. I have
concluded that the three readings, [alpha], [beta], [gamma] made on my
clock at three different moments lacked interest and that the only thing
interesting was the combination ([alpha]-[beta])/([beta]-[gamma]) of
the three. In this conclusion is found the free activity of my mind.

But I have thus used up my power; I can not make this combination
([alpha]-[beta])/([beta]-[gamma]) have such a value and not such
another, since I can not influence either the value of [alpha], or that
of [beta], or that of [gamma], which are imposed upon me as crude
facts.

In sum, facts are facts, and _if it happens that they satisfy a
prediction, this is not an effect of our free activity_. There is no
precise frontier between the fact in the rough and the scientific fact;
it can only be said that such an enunciation of fact is _more crude_ or,
on the contrary, _more scientific_ than such another.


4. _'Nominalism' and 'the Universal Invariant'_

If from facts we pass to laws, it is clear that the part of the free
activity of the scientist will become much greater. But did not M. LeRoy
make it still too great? This is what we are about to examine.

Recall first the examples he has given. When I say: Phosphorus melts at
44°, I think I am enunciating a law; in reality it is just the
definition of phosphorus; if one should discover a body which,
possessing otherwise all the properties of phosphorus, did not melt at
44°, we should give it another name, that is all, and the law would
remain true.

Just so when I say: Heavy bodies falling freely pass over spaces
proportional to the squares of the times, I only give the definition of
free fall. Whenever the condition shall not be fulfilled, I shall say
that the fall is not free, so that the law will never be wrong. It is
clear that if laws were reduced to that, they could not serve in
prediction; then they would be good for nothing, either as means of
knowledge or as principle of action.

When I say: Phosphorus melts at 44°, I mean by that: All bodies
possessing such or such a property (to wit, all the properties of
phosphorus, save fusing-point) fuse at 44°. So understood, my
proposition is indeed a law, and this law may be useful to me, because
if I meet a body possessing these properties I shall be able to predict
that it will fuse at 44°.

Doubtless the law may be found to be false. Then we shall read in the
treatises on chemistry: "There are two bodies which chemists long
confounded under the name of phosphorus; these two bodies differ only by
their points of fusion." That would evidently not be the first time for
chemists to attain to the separation of two bodies they were at first
not able to distinguish; such, for example, are neodymium and
praseodymium, long confounded under the name of didymium.

I do not think the chemists much fear that a like mischance will ever
happen to phosphorus. And if, to suppose the impossible, it should
happen, the two bodies would probably not have _identically_ the same
density, _identically_ the same specific heat, etc., so that after
having determined with care the density, for instance, one could still
foresee the fusion point.

It is, moreover, unimportant; it suffices to remark that there is a law,
and that this law, true or false, does not reduce to a tautology.

Will it be said that if we do not know on the earth a body which does
not fuse at 44° while having all the other properties of phosphorus, we
can not know whether it does not exist on other planets? Doubtless that
may be maintained, and it would then be inferred that the law in
question, which may serve as a rule of action to us who inhabit the
earth, has yet no general value from the point of view of knowledge, and
owes its interest only to the chance which has placed us on this globe.
This is possible, but, if it were so, the law would be valueless, not
because it reduced to a convention, but because it would be false.

The same is true in what concerns the fall of bodies. It would do me no
good to have given the name of free fall to falls which happen in
conformity with Galileo's law, if I did not know that elsewhere, in such
circumstances, the fall will be _probably_ free or _approximately_ free.
That then is a law which may be true or false, but which does not reduce
to a convention.

Suppose the astronomers discover that the stars do not exactly obey
Newton's law. They will have the choice between two attitudes; they may
say that gravitation does not vary exactly as the inverse of the square
of the distance, or else they may say that gravitation is not the only
force which acts on the stars and that there is in addition a different
sort of force.

In the second case, Newton's law will be considered as the definition of
gravitation. This will be the nominalist attitude. The choice between
the two attitudes is free, and is made from considerations of
convenience, though these considerations are most often so strong that
there remains practically little of this freedom.

We can break up this proposition: (1) The stars obey Newton's law, into
two others; (2) gravitation obeys Newton's law; (3) gravitation is the
only force acting on the stars. In this case proposition (2) is no
longer anything but a definition and is beyond the test of experiment;
but then it will be on proposition (3) that this check can be exercised.
This is indeed necessary, since the resulting proposition (1) predicts
verifiable facts in the rough.

It is thanks to these artifices that by an unconscious nominalism the
scientists have elevated above the laws what they call principles. When
a law has received a sufficient confirmation from experiment, we may
adopt two attitudes: either we may leave this law in the fray; it will
then remain subjected to an incessant revision, which without any doubt
will end by demonstrating that it is only approximative. Or else we may
elevate it into a _principle_ by adopting conventions such that the
proposition may be certainly true. For that the procedure is always the
same. The primitive law enunciated a relation between two facts in the
rough, _A_ and _B_; between these two crude facts is introduced an
abstract intermediary _C_, more or less fictitious (such was in the
preceding example the impalpable entity, gravitation). And then we have
a relation between _A_ and _C_ that we may suppose rigorous and which is
the _principle_; and another between _C_ and _B_ which remains a _law_
subject to revision.

The principle, henceforth crystallized, so to speak, is no longer
subject to the test of experiment. It is not true or false, it is
convenient.

Great advantages have often been found in proceeding in that way, but it
is clear that if _all_ the laws had been transformed into principles
_nothing_ would be left of science. Every law may be broken up into a
principle and a law, but thereby it is very clear that, however far this
partition be pushed, there will always remain laws.

Nominalism has therefore limits, and this is what one might fail to
recognize if one took to the very letter M. LeRoy's assertions.

A rapid review of the sciences will make us comprehend better what are
these limits. The nominalist attitude is justified only when it is
convenient; when is it so?

Experiment teaches us relations between bodies; this is the fact in the
rough; these relations are extremely complicated. Instead of envisaging
directly the relation of the body _A_ and the body _B_, we introduce
between them an intermediary, which is space, and we envisage three
distinct relations: that of the body _A_ with the figure _A'_ of space,
that of the body _B_ with the figure _B'_ of space, that of the two
figures _A'_ and _B'_ to each other. Why is this detour advantageous?
Because the relation of _A_ and _B_ was complicated, but differed little
from that of _A'_ and _B'_, which is simple; so that this complicated
relation may be replaced by the simple relation between _A'_ and _B'_
and by two other relations which tell us that the differences between
_A_ and _A'_, on the one hand, between _B_ and _B'_, on the other hand,
are _very small_. For example, if _A_ and _B_ are two natural solid
bodies which are displaced with slight deformation, we envisage two
movable _rigid_ figures _A'_ and _B'_. The laws of the relative
displacement of these figures _A'_ and _B'_ will be very simple; they
will be those of geometry. And we shall afterward add that the body _A_,
which always differs very little from _A'_, dilates from the effect of
heat and bends from the effect of elasticity. These dilatations and
flexions, just because they are very small, will be for our mind
relatively easy to study. Just imagine to what complexities of language
it would have been necessary to be resigned if we had wished to
comprehend in the same enunciation the displacement of the solid, its
dilatation and its flexure?

The relation between _A_ and _B_ was a rough law, and was broken up; we
now have two laws which express the relations of _A_ and _A'_, of _B_
and _B'_, and a principle which expresses that of _A'_ with _B'_. It is
the aggregate of these principles that is called geometry.

Two other remarks. We have a relation between two bodies _A_ and _B_,
which we have replaced by a relation between two figures _A'_ and _B'_;
but this same relation between the same two figures _A'_ and _B'_ could
just as well have replaced advantageously a relation between two other
bodies _A''_ and _B''_, entirely different from _A_ and _B_. And that in
many ways. If the principles of geometry had not been invented, after
having studied the relation of _A_ and _B_, it would be necessary to
begin again _ab ovo_ the study of the relation of _A''_ and _B''_.
That is why geometry is so precious. A geometrical relation can
advantageously replace a relation which, considered in the rough state,
should be regarded as mechanical, it can replace another which should be
regarded as optical, etc.

Yet let no one say: But that proves geometry an experimental science; in
separating its principles from laws whence they have been drawn, you
artificially separate it itself from the sciences which have given birth
to it. The other sciences have likewise principles, but that does not
preclude our having to call them experimental.

It must be recognized that it would have been difficult not to make this
separation that is pretended to be artificial. We know the rôle that the
kinematics of solid bodies has played in the genesis of geometry; should
it then be said that geometry is only a branch of experimental
kinematics? But the laws of the rectilinear propagation of light have
also contributed to the formation of its principles. Must geometry be
regarded both as a branch of kinematics and as a branch of optics? I
recall besides that our Euclidean space which is the proper object of
geometry has been chosen, for reasons of convenience, from among a
certain number of types which preexist in our mind and which are called
groups.

If we pass to mechanics, we still see great principles whose origin is
analogous, and, as their 'radius of action,' so to speak, is smaller,
there is no longer reason to separate them from mechanics proper and to
regard this science as deductive.

In physics, finally, the rôle of the principles is still more
diminished. And in fact they are only introduced when it is of
advantage. Now they are advantageous precisely because they are few,
since each of them very nearly replaces a great number of laws.
Therefore it is not of interest to multiply them. Besides an outcome is
necessary, and for that it is needful to end by leaving abstraction to
take hold of reality.

Such are the limits of nominalism, and they are narrow.

M. LeRoy has insisted, however, and he has put the question under
another form.

Since the enunciation of our laws may vary with the conventions that we
adopt, since these conventions may modify even the natural relations of
these laws, is there in the manifold of these laws something independent
of these conventions and which may, so to speak, play the rôle of
_universal invariant_? For instance, the fiction has been introduced of
beings who, having been educated in a world different from ours, would
have been led to create a non-Euclidean geometry. If these beings were
afterward suddenly transported into our world, they would observe the
same laws as we, but they would enunciate them in an entirely different
way. In truth there would still be something in common between the two
enunciations, but this is because these beings do not yet differ enough
from us. Beings still more strange may be imagined, and the part common
to the two systems of enunciations will shrink more and more. Will it
thus shrink in convergence toward zero, or will there remain an
irreducible residue which will then be the universal invariant sought?

The question calls for precise statement. Is it desired that this common
part of the enunciations be expressible in words? It is clear, then,
that there are not words common to all languages, and we can not pretend
to construct I know not what universal invariant which should be
understood both by us and by the fictitious non-Euclidean geometers of
whom I have just spoken; no more than we can construct a phrase which
can be understood both by Germans who do not understand French and by
French who do not understand German. But we have fixed rules which
permit us to translate the French enunciations into German, and
inversely. It is for that that grammars and dictionaries have been made.
There are also fixed rules for translating the Euclidean language into
the non-Euclidean language, or, if there are not, they could be made.

And even if there were neither interpreter nor dictionary, if the
Germans and the French, after having lived centuries in separate worlds,
found themselves all at once in contact, do you think there would be
nothing in common between the science of the German books and that of
the French books? The French and the Germans would certainly end by
understanding each other, as the American Indians ended by understanding
the language of their conquerors after the arrival of the Spanish.

But, it will be said, doubtless the French would be capable of
understanding the Germans even without having learned German, but this
is because there remains between the French and the Germans something in
common, since both are men. We should still attain to an understanding
with our hypothetical non-Euclideans, though they be not men, because
they would still retain something human. But in any case a minimum of
humanity is necessary.

This is possible, but I shall observe first that this little humanness
which would remain in the non-Euclideans would suffice not only to make
possible the translation of _a little_ of their language, but to make
possible the translation of _all_ their language.

Now, that there must be a minimum is what I concede; suppose there
exists I know not what fluid which penetrates between the molecules of
our matter, without having any action on it and without being subject to
any action coming from it. Suppose beings sensible to the influence of
this fluid and insensible to that of our matter. It is clear that the
science of these beings would differ absolutely from ours and that it
would be idle to seek an 'invariant' common to these two sciences. Or
again, if these beings rejected our logic and did not admit, for
instance, the principle of contradiction.

But truly I think it without interest to examine such hypotheses.

And then, if we do not push whimsicality so far, if we introduce only
fictitious beings having senses analogous to ours and sensible to the
same impressions, and moreover admitting the principles of our logic, we
shall then be able to conclude that their language, however different
from ours it may be, would always be capable of translation. Now the
possibility of translation implies the existence of an invariant. To
translate is precisely to disengage this invariant. Thus, to decipher a
cryptogram is to seek what in this document remains invariant, when the
letters are permuted.

What now is the nature of this invariant it is easy to understand, and a
word will suffice us. The invariant laws are the relations between the
crude facts, while the relations between the 'scientific facts' remain
always dependent on certain conventions.



CHAPTER XI

SCIENCE AND REALITY


5. _Contingence and Determinism_

I do not intend to treat here the question of the contingence of the
laws of nature, which is evidently insoluble, and on which so much has
already been written. I only wish to call attention to what different
meanings have been given to this word, contingence, and how advantageous
it would be to distinguish them.

If we look at any particular law, we may be certain in advance that it
can only be approximate. It is, in fact, deduced from experimental
verifications, and these verifications were and could be only
approximate. We should always expect that more precise measurements will
oblige us to add new terms to our formulas; this is what has happened,
for instance, in the case of Mariotte's law.

Moreover the statement of any law is necessarily incomplete. This
enunciation should comprise the enumeration of _all_ the antecedents in
virtue of which a given consequent can happen. I should first describe
_all_ the conditions of the experiment to be made and the law would then
be stated: If all the conditions are fulfilled, the phenomenon will
happen.

But we shall be sure of not having forgotten _any_ of these conditions
only when we shall have described the state of the entire universe at
the instant _t_; all the parts of this universe may, in fact, exercise
an influence more or less great on the phenomenon which must happen at
the instant _t_ + _dt_.

Now it is clear that such a description could not be found in the
enunciation of the law; besides, if it were made, the law would become
incapable of application; if one required so many conditions, there
would be very little chance of their ever being all realized at any
moment.

Then as one can never be certain of not having forgotten some essential
condition, it can not be said: If such and such conditions are
realized, such a phenomenon will occur; it can only be said: If such and
such conditions are realized, it is probable that such a phenomenon will
occur, very nearly.

Take the law of gravitation, which is the least imperfect of all known
laws. It enables us to foresee the motions of the planets. When I use
it, for instance, to calculate the orbit of Saturn, I neglect the action
of the stars, and in doing so I am certain of not deceiving myself,
because I know that these stars are too far away for their action to be
sensible.

I announce, then, with a quasi-certitude that the coordinates of Saturn
at such an hour will be comprised between such and such limits. Yet is
that certitude absolute? Could there not exist in the universe some
gigantic mass, much greater than that of all the known stars and whose
action could make itself felt at great distances? That mass might be
animated by a colossal velocity, and after having circulated from all
time at such distances that its influence had remained hitherto
insensible to us, it might come all at once to pass near us. Surely it
would produce in our solar system enormous perturbations that we could
not have foreseen. All that can be said is that such an event is wholly
improbable, and then, instead of saying: Saturn will be near such a
point of the heavens, we must limit ourselves to saying: Saturn will
probably be near such a point of the heavens. Although this probability
may be practically equivalent to certainty, it is only a probability.

For all these reasons, no particular law will ever be more than
approximate and probable. Scientists have never failed to recognize this
truth; only they believe, right or wrong, that every law may be replaced
by another closer and more probable, that this new law will itself be
only provisional, but that the same movement can continue indefinitely,
so that science in progressing will possess laws more and more probable,
that the approximation will end by differing as little as you choose
from exactitude and the probability from certitude.

If the scientists who think thus are right, still could it be said that
_the_ laws of nature are contingent, even though _each_ law, taken in
particular, may be qualified as contingent? Or must one require, before
concluding the contingence _of the_ natural laws, that this progress
have an end, that the scientist finish some day by being arrested in his
search for a closer and closer approximation, and that, beyond a certain
limit, he thereafter meet in nature only caprice?

In the conception of which I have just spoken (and which I shall call
the scientific conception), every law is only a statement imperfect and
provisional, but it must one day be replaced by another, a superior law,
of which it is only a crude image. No place therefore remains for the
intervention of a free will.

It seems to me that the kinetic theory of gases will furnish us a
striking example.

You know that in this theory all the properties of gases are explained
by a simple hypothesis; it is supposed that all the gaseous molecules
move in every direction with great velocities and that they follow
rectilineal paths which are disturbed only when one molecule passes very
near the sides of the vessel or another molecule. The effects our crude
senses enable us to observe are the mean effects, and in these means,
the great deviations compensate, or at least it is very improbable that
they do not compensate; so that the observable phenomena follow simple
laws such as that of Mariotte or of Gay-Lussac. But this compensation of
deviations is only probable. The molecules incessantly change place and
in these continual displacements the figures they form pass successively
through all possible combinations. Singly these combinations are very
numerous; almost all are in conformity with Mariotte's law, only a few
deviate from it. These also will happen, only it would be necessary to
wait a long time for them. If a gas were observed during a sufficiently
long time it would certainly be finally seen to deviate, for a very
short time, from Mariotte's law. How long would it be necessary to wait?
If it were desired to calculate the probable number of years, it would
be found that this number is so great that to write only the number of
places of figures employed would still require half a score places of
figures. No matter; enough that it may be done.

I do not care to discuss here the value of this theory. It is evident
that if it be adopted, Mariotte's law will thereafter appear only as
contingent, since a day will come when it will not be true. And yet,
think you the partisans of the kinetic theory are adversaries of
determinism? Far from it; they are the most ultra of mechanists. Their
molecules follow rigid paths, from which they depart only under the
influence of forces which vary with the distance, following a perfectly
determinate law. There remains in their system not the smallest place
either for freedom, or for an evolutionary factor, properly so-called,
or for anything whatever that could be called contingence. I add, to
avoid mistake, that neither is there any evolution of Mariotte's law
itself; it ceases to be true after I know not how many centuries; but at
the end of a fraction of a second it again becomes true and that for an
incalculable number of centuries.

And since I have pronounced the word evolution, let us clear away
another mistake. It is often said: Who knows whether the laws do not
evolve and whether we shall not one day discover that they were not at
the Carboniferous epoch what they are to-day? What are we to understand
by that? What we think we know about the past state of our globe, we
deduce from its present state. And how is this deduction made? It is by
means of laws supposed known. The law, being a relation between the
antecedent and the consequent, enables us equally well to deduce the
consequent from the antecedent, that is, to foresee the future, and to
deduce the antecedent from the consequent, that is, to conclude from the
present to the past. The astronomer who knows the present situation of
the stars can from it deduce their future situation by Newton's law, and
this is what he does when he constructs ephemerides; and he can equally
deduce from it their past situation. The calculations he thus can make
can not teach him that Newton's law will cease to be true in the future,
since this law is precisely his point of departure; not more can they
tell him it was not true in the past. Still, in what concerns the
future, his ephemerides can one day be tested and our descendants will
perhaps recognize that they were false. But in what concerns the past,
the geologic past which had no witnesses, the results of his
calculation, like those of all speculations where we seek to deduce the
past from the present, escape by their very nature every species of
test. So that if the laws of nature were not the same in the
Carboniferous age as at the present epoch, we shall never be able to
know it, since we can know nothing of this age, only what we deduce from
the hypothesis of the permanence of these laws.

Perhaps it will be said that this hypothesis might lead to contradictory
results and that we shall be obliged to abandon it. Thus, in what
concerns the origin of life, we may conclude that there have always been
living beings, since the present world shows us always life springing
from life; and we may also conclude that there have not always been,
since the application of the existent laws of physics to the present
state of our globe teaches us that there was a time when this globe was
so warm that life on it was impossible. But contradictions of this sort
can always be removed in two ways; it may be supposed that the actual
laws of nature are not exactly what we have assumed; or else it may be
supposed that the laws of nature actually are what we have assumed, but
that it has not always been so.

It is evident that the actual laws will never be sufficiently well known
for us not to be able to adopt the first of these two solutions and for
us to be constrained to infer the evolution of natural laws.

On the other hand, suppose such an evolution; assume, if you wish, that
humanity lasts sufficiently long for this evolution to have witnesses.
The _same_ antecedent shall produce, for instance, different consequents
at the Carboniferous epoch and at the Quaternary. That evidently means
that the antecedents are closely alike; if all the circumstances were
identical, the Carboniferous epoch would be indistinguishable from the
Quaternary. Evidently this is not what is supposed. What remains is that
such antecedent, accompanied by such accessory circumstance, produces
such consequent; and that the same antecedent, accompanied by such other
accessory circumstance, produces such other consequent. Time does not
enter into the affair.

The law, such as ill-informed science would have stated it, and which
would have affirmed that this antecedent always produces this
consequent, without taking account of the accessory circumstances, this
law, which was only approximate and probable, must be replaced by
another law more approximate and more probable, which brings in these
accessory circumstances. We always come back, therefore, to that same
process which we have analyzed above, and if humanity should discover
something of this sort, it would not say that it is the laws which have
evoluted, but the circumstances which have changed.

Here, therefore, are several different senses of the word contingence.
M. LeRoy retains them all and he does not sufficiently distinguish them,
but he introduces a new one. Experimental laws are only approximate, and
if some appear to us as exact, it is because we have artificially
transformed them into what I have above called a principle. We have made
this transformation freely, and as the caprice which has determined us
to make it is something eminently contingent, we have communicated this
contingence to the law itself. It is in this sense that we have the
right to say that determinism supposes freedom, since it is freely that
we become determinists. Perhaps it will be found that this is to give
large scope to nominalism and that the introduction of this new sense of
the word contingence will not help much to solve all those questions
which naturally arise and of which we have just been speaking.

I do not at all wish to investigate here the foundations of the
principle of induction; I know very well that I should not succeed; it
is as difficult to justify this principle as to get on without it. I
only wish to show how scientists apply it and are forced to apply it.

When the same antecedent recurs, the same consequent must likewise
recur; such is the ordinary statement. But reduced to these terms this
principle could be of no use. For one to be able to say that the same
antecedent recurred, it would be necessary for the circumstances _all_
to be reproduced, since no one is absolutely indifferent, and for them
to be _exactly_ reproduced. And, as that will never happen, the
principle can have no application.

We should therefore modify the enunciation and say: If an antecedent _A_
has once produced a consequent _B_, an antecedent _A'_, slightly
different from _A_, will produce a consequent _B'_, slightly different
from _B_. But how shall we recognize that the antecedents _A_ and _A'_
are 'slightly different'? If some one of the circumstances can be
expressed by a number, and this number has in the two cases values very
near together, the sense of the phrase 'slightly different' is
relatively clear; the principle then signifies that the consequent is a
continuous function of the antecedent. And as a practical rule, we reach
this conclusion that we have the right to interpolate. This is in fact
what scientists do every day, and without interpolation all science
would be impossible.

Yet observe one thing. The law sought may be represented by a curve.
Experiment has taught us certain points of this curve. In virtue of the
principle we have just stated, we believe these points may be connected
by a continuous graph. We trace this graph with the eye. New experiments
will furnish us new points of the curve. If these points are outside of
the graph traced in advance, we shall have to modify our curve, but not
to abandon our principle. Through any points, however numerous they may
be, a continuous curve may always be passed. Doubtless, if this curve is
too capricious, we shall be shocked (and we shall even suspect errors of
experiment), but the principle will not be directly put at fault.

Furthermore, among the circumstances of a phenomenon, there are some
that we regard as negligible, and we shall consider _A_ and _A'_ as
slightly different if they differ only by these accessory circumstances.
For instance, I have ascertained that hydrogen unites with oxygen under
the influence of the electric spark, and I am certain that these two
gases will unite anew, although the longitude of Jupiter may have
changed considerably in the interval. We assume, for instance, that the
state of distant bodies can have no sensible influence on terrestrial
phenomena, and that seems in fact requisite, but there are cases where
the choice of these practically indifferent circumstances admits of more
arbitrariness or, if you choose, requires more tact.

One more remark: The principle of induction would be inapplicable if
there did not exist in nature a great quantity of bodies like one
another, or almost alike, and if we could not infer, for instance, from
one bit of phosphorus to another bit of phosphorus.

If we reflect on these considerations, the problem of determinism and of
contingence will appear to us in a new light.

Suppose we were able to embrace the series of all phenomena of the
universe in the whole sequence of time. We could envisage what might be
called the _sequences_; I mean relations between antecedent and
consequent. I do not wish to speak of constant relations or laws, I
envisage separately (individually, so to speak) the different sequences
realized.

We should then recognize that among these sequences there are no two
altogether alike. But, if the principle of induction, as we have just
stated it, is true, there will be those almost alike and that can be
classed alongside one another. In other words, it is possible to make a
classification of sequences.

It is to the possibility and the legitimacy of such a classification
that determinism, in the end, reduces. This is all that the preceding
analysis leaves of it. Perhaps under this modest form it will seem less
appalling to the moralist.

It will doubtless be said that this is to come back by a detour to M.
LeRoy's conclusion which a moment ago we seemed to reject: we are
determinists voluntarily. And in fact all classification supposes the
active intervention of the classifier. I agree that this may be
maintained, but it seems to me that this detour will not have been
useless and will have contributed to enlighten us a little.


6. _Objectivity of Science_

I arrive at the question set by the title of this article: What is the
objective value of science? And first what should we understand by
objectivity?

What guarantees the objectivity of the world in which we live is that
this world is common to us with other thinking beings. Through the
communications that we have with other men, we receive from them
ready-made reasonings; we know that these reasonings do not come from us
and at the same time we recognize in them the work of reasonable beings
like ourselves. And as these reasonings appear to fit the world of our
sensations, we think we may infer that these reasonable beings have seen
the same thing as we; thus it is we know we have not been dreaming.

Such, therefore, is the first condition of objectivity; what is
objective must be common to many minds and consequently transmissible
from one to the other, and as this transmission can only come about by
that 'discourse' which inspires so much distrust in M. LeRoy, we are
even forced to conclude: no discourse, no objectivity.

The sensations of others will be for us a world eternally closed. We
have no means of verifying that the sensation I call red is the same as
that which my neighbor calls red.

Suppose that a cherry and a red poppy produce on me the sensation _A_
and on him the sensation _B_ and that, on the contrary, a leaf produces
on me the sensation _B_ and on him the sensation _A_. It is clear we
shall never know anything about it; since I shall call red the sensation
_A_ and green the sensation _B_, while he will call the first green and
the second red. In compensation, what we shall be able to ascertain is
that, for him as for me, the cherry and the red poppy produce the _same_
sensation, since he gives the same name to the sensations he feels and I
do the same.

Sensations are therefore intransmissible, or rather all that is pure
quality in them is intransmissible and forever impenetrable. But it is
not the same with relations between these sensations.

From this point of view, all that is objective is devoid of all quality
and is only pure relation. Certes, I shall not go so far as to say that
objectivity is only pure quantity (this would be to particularize too
far the nature of the relations in question), but we understand how some
one could have been carried away into saying that the world is only a
differential equation.

With due reserve regarding this paradoxical proposition, we must
nevertheless admit that nothing is objective which is not transmissible,
and consequently that the relations between the sensations can alone
have an objective value.

Perhaps it will be said that the esthetic emotion, which is common to
all mankind, is proof that the qualities of our sensations are also the
same for all men and hence are objective. But if we think about this, we
shall see that the proof is not complete; what is proved is that this
emotion is aroused in John as in James by the sensations to which James
and John give the same name or by the corresponding combinations of
these sensations; either because this emotion is associated in John with
the sensation _A_, which John calls red, while parallelly it is
associated in James with the sensation _B_, which James calls red; or
better because this emotion is aroused, not by the qualities themselves
of the sensations, but by the harmonious combination of their relations
of which we undergo the unconscious impression.

Such a sensation is beautiful, not because it possesses such a quality,
but because it occupies such a place in the woof of our associations of
ideas, so that it can not be excited without putting in motion the
'receiver' which is at the other end of the thread and which corresponds
to the artistic emotion.

Whether we take the moral, the esthetic or the scientific point of view,
it is always the same thing. Nothing is objective except what is
identical for all; now we can only speak of such an identity if a
comparison is possible, and can be translated into a 'money of exchange'
capable of transmission from one mind to another. Nothing, therefore,
will have objective value except what is transmissible by 'discourse,'
that is, intelligible.

But this is only one side of the question. An absolutely disordered
aggregate could not have objective value since it would be
unintelligible, but no more can a well-ordered assemblage have it, if it
does not correspond to sensations really experienced. It seems to me
superfluous to recall this condition, and I should not have dreamed of
it, if it had not lately been maintained that physics is not an
experimental science. Although this opinion has no chance of being
adopted either by physicists or by philosophers, it is well to be warned
so as not to let oneself slip over the declivity which would lead
thither. Two conditions are therefore to be fulfilled, and if the first
separates reality[11] from the dream, the second distinguishes it from
the romance.

  [11] I here use the word real as a synonym of objective; I thus
       conform to common usage; perhaps I am wrong, our dreams are
       real, but they are not objective.

Now what is science? I have explained in the preceding article, it is
before all a classification, a manner of bringing together facts which
appearances separate, though they were bound together by some natural
and hidden kinship. Science, in other words, is a system of relations.
Now we have just said, it is in the relations alone that objectivity
must be sought; it would be vain to seek it in beings considered as
isolated from one another.

To say that science can not have objective value since it teaches us
only relations, this is to reason backward, since, precisely, it is
relations alone which can be regarded as objective.

External objects, for instance, for which the word _object_ was
invented, are really _objects_ and not fleeting and fugitive
appearances, because they are not only groups of sensations, but groups
cemented by a constant bond. It is this bond, and this bond alone, which
is the object in itself, and this bond is a relation.

Therefore, when we ask what is the objective value of science, that does
not mean: Does science teach us the true nature of things? but it means:
Does it teach us the true relations of things?

To the first question, no one would hesitate to reply, no; but I think
we may go farther; not only science can not teach us the nature of
things; but nothing is capable of teaching it to us, and if any god knew
it, he could not find words to express it. Not only can we not divine
the response, but if it were given to us we could understand nothing of
it; I ask myself even whether we really understand the question.

When, therefore, a scientific theory pretends to teach us what heat is,
or what is electricity, or life, it is condemned beforehand; all it can
give us is only a crude image. It is, therefore, provisional and
crumbling.

The first question being out of reason, the second remains. Can science
teach us the true relations of things? What it joins together should
that be put asunder, what it puts asunder should that be joined
together?

To understand the meaning of this new question, it is needful to refer
to what was said above on the conditions of objectivity. Have these
relations an objective value? That means: Are these relations the same
for all? Will they still be the same for those who shall come after us?

It is clear that they are not the same for the scientist and the
ignorant person. But that is unimportant, because if the ignorant person
does not see them all at once, the scientist may succeed in making him
see them by a series of experiments and reasonings. The thing essential
is that there are points on which all those acquainted with the
experiments made can reach accord.

The question is to know whether this accord will be durable and whether
it will persist for our successors. It may be asked whether the unions
that the science of to-day makes will be confirmed by the science of
to-morrow. To affirm that it will be so we can not invoke any _a priori_
reason; but this is a question of fact, and science has already lived
long enough for us to be able to find out by asking its history whether
the edifices it builds stand the test of time, or whether they are only
ephemeral constructions.

Now what do we see? At the first blush, it seems to us that the theories
last only a day and that ruins upon ruins accumulate. To-day the
theories are born, to-morrow they are the fashion, the day after
to-morrow they are classic, the fourth day they are superannuated, and
the fifth they are forgotten. But if we look more closely, we see that
what thus succumb are the theories properly so called, those which
pretend to teach us what things are. But there is in them something
which usually survives. If one of them taught us a true relation, this
relation is definitively acquired, and it will be found again under a
new disguise in the other theories which will successively come to reign
in place of the old.

Take only a single example: The theory of the undulations of the ether
taught us that light is a motion; to-day fashion favors the
electromagnetic theory which teaches us that light is a current. We do
not consider whether we could reconcile them and say that light is a
current, and that this current is a motion. As it is probable in any
case that this motion would not be identical with that which the
partisans of the old theory presume, we might think ourselves justified
in saying that this old theory is dethroned. And yet something of it
remains, since between the hypothetical currents which Maxwell supposes
there are the same relations as between the hypothetical motions that
Fresnel supposed. There is, therefore, something which remains over and
this something is the essential. This it is which explains how we see
the present physicists pass without any embarrassment from the language
of Fresnel to that of Maxwell. Doubtless many connections that were
believed well established have been abandoned, but the greatest number
remain and it would seem must remain.

And for these, then, what is the measure of their objectivity? Well, it
is precisely the same as for our belief in external objects. These
latter are real in this, that the sensations they make us feel appear to
us as united to each other by I know not what indestructible cement and
not by the hazard of a day. In the same way science reveals to us
between phenomena other bonds finer but not less solid; these are
threads so slender that they long remained unperceived, but once noticed
there remains no way of not seeing them; they are therefore not less
real than those which give their reality to external objects; small
matter that they are more recently known, since neither can perish
before the other.

It may be said, for instance, that the ether is no less real than any
external body; to say this body exists is to say there is between the
color of this body, its taste, its smell, an intimate bond, solid and
persistent; to say the ether exists is to say there is a natural kinship
between all the optical phenomena, and neither of the two propositions
has less value than the other.

And the scientific syntheses have in a sense even more reality than
those of the ordinary senses, since they embrace more terms and tend to
absorb in them the partial syntheses.

It will be said that science is only a classification and that a
classification can not be true, but convenient. But it is true that it
is convenient, it is true that it is so not only for me, but for all
men; it is true that it will remain convenient for our descendants; it
is true finally that this can not be by chance.

In sum, the sole objective reality consists in the relations of things
whence results the universal harmony. Doubtless these relations, this
harmony, could not be conceived outside of a mind which conceives them.
But they are nevertheless objective because they are, will become, or
will remain, common to all thinking beings.

This will permit us to revert to the question of the rotation of the
earth which will give us at the same time a chance to make clear what
precedes by an example.


7. _The Rotation of the Earth_

"... Therefore," have I said in _Science and Hypothesis_, "this
affirmation, the earth turns round, has no meaning ... or rather these
two propositions, the earth turns round, and, it is more convenient to
suppose that the earth turns round, have one and the same meaning."

These words have given rise to the strangest interpretations. Some have
thought they saw in them the rehabilitation of Ptolemy's system, and
perhaps the justification of Galileo's condemnation.

Those who had read attentively the whole volume could not, however,
delude themselves. This truth, the earth turns round, was put on the
same footing as Euclid's postulate, for example. Was that to reject it?
But better; in the same language it may very well be said: These two
propositions, the external world exists, or, it is more convenient to
suppose that it exists, have one and the same meaning. So the hypothesis
of the rotation of the earth would have the same degree of certitude as
the very existence of external objects.

But after what we have just explained in the fourth part, we may go
farther. A physical theory, we have said, is by so much the more true as
it puts in evidence more true relations. In the light of this new
principle, let us examine the question which occupies us.

No, there is no absolute space; these two contradictory propositions:
'The earth turns round' and 'The earth does not turn round' are,
therefore, neither of them more true than the other. To affirm one while
denying the other, _in the kinematic sense_, would be to admit the
existence of absolute space.

But if the one reveals true relations that the other hides from us, we
can nevertheless regard it as physically more true than the other, since
it has a richer content. Now in this regard no doubt is possible.

Behold the apparent diurnal motion of the stars, and the diurnal motion
of the other heavenly bodies, and besides, the flattening of the earth,
the rotation of Foucault's pendulum, the gyration of cyclones, the
trade-winds, what not else? For the Ptolemaist all these phenomena have
no bond between them; for the Copernican they are produced by the one
same cause. In saying, the earth turns round, I affirm that all these
phenomena have an intimate relation, and _that is true_, and that
remains true, although there is not and can not be absolute space.

So much for the rotation of the earth upon itself; what shall we say of
its revolution around the sun? Here again, we have three phenomena which
for the Ptolemaist are absolutely independent and which for the
Copernican are referred back to the same origin; they are the apparent
displacements of the planets on the celestial sphere, the aberration of
the fixed stars, the parallax of these same stars. Is it by chance that
all the planets admit an inequality whose period is a year, and that
this period is precisely equal to that of aberration, precisely equal
besides to that of parallax? To adopt Ptolemy's system is to answer,
yes; to adopt that of Copernicus is to answer, no; this is to affirm
that there is a bond between the three phenomena, and that also is true,
although there is no absolute space.

In Ptolemy's system, the motions of the heavenly bodies can not be
explained by the action of central forces, celestial mechanics is
impossible. The intimate relations that celestial mechanics reveals to
us between all the celestial phenomena are true relations; to affirm the
immobility of the earth would be to deny these relations, that would be
to fool ourselves.

The truth for which Galileo suffered remains, therefore, the truth,
although it has not altogether the same meaning as for the vulgar, and
its true meaning is much more subtle, more profound and more rich.


8. _Science for Its Own Sake_

Not against M. LeRoy do I wish to defend science for its own sake; maybe
this is what he condemns, but this is what he cultivates, since he loves
and seeks truth and could not live without it. But I have some thoughts
to express.

We can not know all facts and it is necessary to choose those which are
worthy of being known. According to Tolstoi, scientists make this choice
at random, instead of making it, which would be reasonable, with a view
to practical applications. On the contrary, scientists think that
certain facts are more interesting than others, because they complete an
unfinished harmony, or because they make one foresee a great number of
other facts. If they are wrong, if this hierarchy of facts that they
implicitly postulate is only an idle illusion, there could be no science
for its own sake, and consequently there could be no science. As for me,
I believe they are right, and, for example, I have shown above what is
the high value of astronomical facts, not because they are capable of
practical applications, but because they are the most instructive of
all.

It is only through science and art that civilization is of value. Some
have wondered at the formula: science for its own sake; and yet it is as
good as life for its own sake, if life is only misery; and even as
happiness for its own sake, if we do not believe that all pleasures are
of the same quality, if we do not wish to admit that the goal of
civilization is to furnish alcohol to people who love to drink.

Every act should have an aim. We must suffer, we must work, we must pay
for our place at the game, but this is for seeing's sake; or at the very
least that others may one day see.

All that is not thought is pure nothingness; since we can think only
thoughts and all the words we use to speak of things can express only
thoughts, to say there is something other than thought, is therefore an
affirmation which can have no meaning.

And yet--strange contradiction for those who believe in time--geologic
history shows us that life is only a short episode between two
eternities of death, and that, even in this episode, conscious thought
has lasted and will last only a moment. Thought is only a gleam in the
midst of a long night.

But it is this gleam which is everything.


       *       *       *       *       *



SCIENCE AND METHOD



       *       *       *       *       *



INTRODUCTION


I bring together here different studies relating more or less directly
to questions of scientific methodology. The scientific method consists
in observing and experimenting; if the scientist had at his disposal
infinite time, it would only be necessary to say to him: 'Look and
notice well'; but, as there is not time to see everything, and as it is
better not to see than to see wrongly, it is necessary for him to make
choice. The first question, therefore, is how he should make this
choice. This question presents itself as well to the physicist as to the
historian; it presents itself equally to the mathematician, and the
principles which should guide each are not without analogy. The
scientist conforms to them instinctively, and one can, reflecting on
these principles, foretell the future of mathematics.

We shall understand them better yet if we observe the scientist at work,
and first of all it is necessary to know the psychologic mechanism of
invention and, in particular, that of mathematical creation. Observation
of the processes of the work of the mathematician is particularly
instructive for the psychologist.

In all the sciences of observation account must be taken of the errors
due to the imperfections of our senses and our instruments. Luckily, we
may assume that, under certain conditions, these errors are in part
self-compensating, so as to disappear in the average; this compensation
is due to chance. But what is chance? This idea is difficult to justify
or even to define; and yet what I have just said about the errors of
observation, shows that the scientist can not neglect it. It therefore
is necessary to give a definition as precise as possible of this
concept, so indispensable yet so illusive.

These are generalities applicable in sum to all the sciences; and for
example the mechanism of mathematical invention does not differ sensibly
from the mechanism of invention in general. Later I attack questions
relating more particularly to certain special sciences and first to pure
mathematics.

In the chapters devoted to these, I have to treat subjects a little more
abstract. I have first to speak of the notion of space; every one knows
space is relative, or rather every one says so, but many think still as
if they believed it absolute; it suffices to reflect a little however to
perceive to what contradictions they are exposed.

The questions of teaching have their importance, first in themselves,
then because reflecting on the best way to make new ideas penetrate
virgin minds is at the same time reflecting on how these notions were
acquired by our ancestors, and consequently on their true origin, that
is to say, in reality on their true nature. Why do children usually
understand nothing of the definitions which satisfy scientists? Why is
it necessary to give them others? This is the question I set myself in
the succeeding chapter and whose solution should, I think, suggest
useful reflections to the philosophers occupied with the logic of the
sciences.

On the other hand, many geometers believe we can reduce mathematics to
the rules of formal logic. Unheard-of efforts have been made to do this;
to accomplish it, some have not hesitated, for example, to reverse the
historic order of the genesis of our conceptions and to try to explain
the finite by the infinite. I believe I have succeeded in showing, for
all those who attack the problem unprejudiced, that here there is a
fallacious illusion. I hope the reader will understand the importance of
the question and pardon me the aridity of the pages devoted to it.

The concluding chapters relative to mechanics and astronomy will be
easier to read.

Mechanics seems on the point of undergoing a complete revolution. Ideas
which appeared best established are assailed by bold innovators.
Certainly it would be premature to decide in their favor at once simply
because they are innovators.

But it is of interest to make known their doctrines, and this is what I
have tried to do. As far as possible I have followed the historic order;
for the new ideas would seem too astonishing unless we saw how they
arose.

Astronomy offers us majestic spectacles and raises gigantic problems. We
can not dream of applying to them directly the experimental method; our
laboratories are too small. But analogy with phenomena these
laboratories permit us to attain may nevertheless guide the astronomer.
The Milky Way, for example, is an assemblage of suns whose movements
seem at first capricious. But may not this assemblage be compared to
that of the molecules of a gas, whose properties the kinetic theory of
gases has made known to us? It is thus by a roundabout way that the
method of the physicist may come to the aid of the astronomer.

Finally I have endeavored to give in a few lines the history of the
development of French geodesy; I have shown through what persevering
efforts, and often what dangers, the geodesists have procured for us the
knowledge we have of the figure of the earth. Is this then a question of
method? Yes, without doubt, this history teaches us in fact by what
precautions it is necessary to surround a serious scientific operation
and how much time and pains it costs to conquer one new decimal.



BOOK I


SCIENCE AND THE SCIENTIST



CHAPTER I

THE CHOICE OF FACTS


Tolstoi somewhere explains why 'science for its own sake' is in his eyes
an absurd conception. We can not know _all_ facts, since their number is
practically infinite. It is necessary to choose; then we may let this
choice depend on the pure caprice of our curiosity; would it not be
better to let ourselves be guided by utility, by our practical and above
all by our moral needs; have we nothing better to do than to count the
number of lady-bugs on our planet?

It is clear the word utility has not for him the sense men of affairs
give it, and following them most of our contemporaries. Little cares he
for industrial applications, for the marvels of electricity or of
automobilism, which he regards rather as obstacles to moral progress;
utility for him is solely what can make man better.

For my part, it need scarce be said, I could never be content with
either the one or the other ideal; I want neither that plutocracy
grasping and mean, nor that democracy goody and mediocre, occupied
solely in turning the other cheek, where would dwell sages without
curiosity, who, shunning excess, would not die of disease, but would
surely die of ennui. But that is a matter of taste and is not what I
wish to discuss.

The question nevertheless remains and should fix our attention; if our
choice can only be determined by caprice or by immediate utility, there
can be no science for its own sake, and consequently no science. But is
that true? That a choice must be made is incontestable; whatever be our
activity, facts go quicker than we, and we can not catch them; while the
scientist discovers one fact, there happen milliards of milliards in a
cubic millimeter of his body. To wish to comprise nature in science
would be to want to put the whole into the part.

But scientists believe there is a hierarchy of facts and that among them
may be made a judicious choice. They are right, since otherwise there
would be no science, yet science exists. One need only open the eyes to
see that the conquests of industry which have enriched so many practical
men would never have seen the light, if these practical men alone had
existed and if they had not been preceded by unselfish devotees who died
poor, who never thought of utility, and yet had a guide far other than
caprice.

As Mach says, these devotees have spared their successors the trouble of
thinking. Those who might have worked solely in view of an immediate
application would have left nothing behind them, and, in face of a new
need, all must have been begun over again. Now most men do not love to
think, and this is perhaps fortunate when instinct guides them, for most
often, when they pursue an aim which is immediate and ever the same,
instinct guides them better than reason would guide a pure intelligence.
But instinct is routine, and if thought did not fecundate it, it would
no more progress in man than in the bee or ant. It is needful then to
think for those who love not thinking, and, as they are numerous, it is
needful that each of our thoughts be as often useful as possible, and
this is why a law will be the more precious the more general it is.

This shows us how we should choose: the most interesting facts are those
which may serve many times; these are the facts which have a chance of
coming up again. We have been so fortunate as to be born in a world
where there are such. Suppose that instead of 60 chemical elements there
were 60 milliards of them, that they were not some common, the others
rare, but that they were uniformly distributed. Then, every time we
picked up a new pebble there would be great probability of its being
formed of some unknown substance; all that we knew of other pebbles
would be worthless for it; before each new object we should be as the
new-born babe; like it we could only obey our caprices or our needs.
Biologists would be just as much at a loss if there were only
individuals and no species and if heredity did not make sons like their
fathers.

In such a world there would be no science; perhaps thought and even life
would be impossible, since evolution could not there develop the
preservational instincts. Happily it is not so; like all good fortune to
which we are accustomed, this is not appreciated at its true worth.

Which then are the facts likely to reappear? They are first the simple
facts. It is clear that in a complex fact a thousand circumstances are
united by chance, and that only a chance still much less probable could
reunite them anew. But are there any simple facts? And if there are, how
recognize them? What assurance is there that a thing we think simple
does not hide a dreadful complexity? All we can say is that we ought to
prefer the facts which _seem_ simple to those where our crude eye
discerns unlike elements. And then one of two things: either this
simplicity is real, or else the elements are so intimately mingled as
not to be distinguishable. In the first case there is chance of our
meeting anew this same simple fact, either in all its purity or entering
itself as element in a complex manifold. In the second case this
intimate mixture has likewise more chances of recurring than a
heterogeneous assemblage; chance knows how to mix, it knows not how to
disentangle, and to make with multiple elements a well-ordered edifice
in which something is distinguishable, it must be made expressly. The
facts which appear simple, even if they are not so, will therefore be
more easily revived by chance. This it is which justifies the method
instinctively adopted by the scientist, and what justifies it still
better, perhaps, is that oft-recurring facts appear to us simple,
precisely because we are used to them.

But where is the simple fact? Scientists have been seeking it in the two
extremes, in the infinitely great and in the infinitely small. The
astronomer has found it because the distances of the stars are immense,
so great that each of them appears but as a point, so great that the
qualitative differences are effaced, and because a point is simpler than
a body which has form and qualities. The physicist on the other hand has
sought the elementary phenomenon in fictively cutting up bodies into
infinitesimal cubes, because the conditions of the problem, which
undergo slow and continuous variation in passing from one point of the
body to another, may be regarded as constant in the interior of each of
these little cubes. In the same way the biologist has been instinctively
led to regard the cell as more interesting than the whole animal, and
the outcome has shown his wisdom, since cells belonging to organisms the
most different are more alike, for the one who can recognize their
resemblances, than are these organisms themselves. The sociologist is
more embarrassed; the elements, which for him are men, are too unlike,
too variable, too capricious, in a word, too complex; besides, history
never begins over again. How then choose the interesting fact, which is
that which begins again? Method is precisely the choice of facts; it is
needful then to be occupied first with creating a method, and many have
been imagined, since none imposes itself, so that sociology is the
science which has the most methods and the fewest results.

Therefore it is by the regular facts that it is proper to begin; but
after the rule is well established, after it is beyond all doubt, the
facts in full conformity with it are erelong without interest since they
no longer teach us anything new. It is then the exception which becomes
important. We cease to seek resemblances; we devote ourselves above all
to the differences, and among the differences are chosen first the most
accentuated, not only because they are the most striking, but because
they will be the most instructive. A simple example will make my thought
plainer: Suppose one wishes to determine a curve by observing some of
its points. The practician who concerns himself only with immediate
utility would observe only the points he might need for some special
object. These points would be badly distributed on the curve; they would
be crowded in certain regions, rare in others, so that it would be
impossible to join them by a continuous line, and they would be
unavailable for other applications. The scientist will proceed
differently; as he wishes to study the curve for itself, he will
distribute regularly the points to be observed, and when enough are
known he will join them by a regular line and then he will have the
entire curve. But for that how does he proceed? If he has determined an
extreme point of the curve, he does not stay near this extremity, but
goes first to the other end; after the two extremities the most
instructive point will be the mid-point, and so on.

So when a rule is established we should first seek the cases where this
rule has the greatest chance of failing. Thence, among other reasons,
come the interest of astronomic facts, and the interest of the geologic
past; by going very far away in space or very far away in time, we may
find our usual rules entirely overturned, and these grand overturnings
aid us the better to see or the better to understand the little changes
which may happen nearer to us, in the little corner of the world where
we are called to live and act. We shall better know this corner for
having traveled in distant countries with which we have nothing to do.

But what we ought to aim at is less the ascertainment of resemblances
and differences than the recognition of likenesses hidden under apparent
divergences. Particular rules seem at first discordant, but looking more
closely we see in general that they resemble each other; different as to
matter, they are alike as to form, as to the order of their parts. When
we look at them with this bias, we shall see them enlarge and tend to
embrace everything. And this it is which makes the value of certain
facts which come to complete an assemblage and to show that it is the
faithful image of other known assemblages.

I will not further insist, but these few words suffice to show that the
scientist does not choose at random the facts he observes. He does not,
as Tolstoi says, count the lady-bugs, because, however interesting
lady-bugs may be, their number is subject to capricious variations. He
seeks to condense much experience and much thought into a slender
volume; and that is why a little book on physics contains so many past
experiences and a thousand times as many possible experiences whose
result is known beforehand.

But we have as yet looked at only one side of the question. The
scientist does not study nature because it is useful; he studies it
because he delights in it, and he delights in it because it is
beautiful. If nature were not beautiful, it would not be worth knowing,
and if nature were not worth knowing, life would not be worth living. Of
course I do not here speak of that beauty which strikes the senses, the
beauty of qualities and of appearances; not that I undervalue such
beauty, far from it, but it has nothing to do with science; I mean that
profounder beauty which comes from the harmonious order of the parts
and which a pure intelligence can grasp. This it is which gives body, a
structure so to speak, to the iridescent appearances which flatter our
senses, and without this support the beauty of these fugitive dreams
would be only imperfect, because it would be vague and always fleeting.
On the contrary, intellectual beauty is sufficient unto itself, and it
is for its sake, more perhaps than for the future good of humanity, that
the scientist devotes himself to long and difficult labors.

It is, therefore, the quest of this especial beauty, the sense of the
harmony of the cosmos, which makes us choose the facts most fitting to
contribute to this harmony, just as the artist chooses from among the
features of his model those which perfect the picture and give it
character and life. And we need not fear that this instinctive and
unavowed prepossession will turn the scientist aside from the search for
the true. One may dream a harmonious world, but how far the real world
will leave it behind! The greatest artists that ever lived, the Greeks,
made their heavens; how shabby it is beside the true heavens, ours!

And it is because simplicity, because grandeur, is beautiful, that we
preferably seek simple facts, sublime facts, that we delight now to
follow the majestic course of the stars, now to examine with the
microscope that prodigious littleness which is also a grandeur, now to
seek in geologic time the traces of a past which attracts because it is
far away.

We see too that the longing for the beautiful leads us to the same
choice as the longing for the useful. And so it is that this economy of
thought, this economy of effort, which is, according to Mach, the
constant tendency of science, is at the same time a source of beauty and
a practical advantage. The edifices that we admire are those where the
architect has known how to proportion the means to the end, where the
columns seem to carry gaily, without effort, the weight placed upon
them, like the gracious caryatids of the Erechtheum.

Whence comes this concordance? Is it simply that the things which seem
to us beautiful are those which best adapt themselves to our
intelligence, and that consequently they are at the same time the
implement this intelligence knows best how to use? Or is there here a
play of evolution and natural selection? Have the peoples whose ideal
most conformed to their highest interest exterminated the others and
taken their place? All pursued their ideals without reference to
consequences, but while this quest led some to destruction, to others it
gave empire. One is tempted to believe it. If the Greeks triumphed over
the barbarians and if Europe, heir of Greek thought, dominates the
world, it is because the savages loved loud colors and the clamorous
tones of the drum which occupied only their senses, while the Greeks
loved the intellectual beauty which hides beneath sensuous beauty, and
this intellectual beauty it is which makes intelligence sure and strong.

Doubtless such a triumph would horrify Tolstoi, and he would not like to
acknowledge that it might be truly useful. But this disinterested quest
of the true for its own beauty is sane also and able to make man better.
I well know that there are mistakes, that the thinker does not always
draw thence the serenity he should find therein, and even that there are
scientists of bad character. Must we, therefore, abandon science and
study only morals? What! Do you think the moralists themselves are
irreproachable when they come down from their pedestal?



CHAPTER II

THE FUTURE OF MATHEMATICS


To foresee the future of mathematics, the true method is to study its
history and its present state.

Is this not for us mathematicians in a way a professional procedure? We
are accustomed to _extrapolate_, which is a means of deducing the future
from the past and present, and as we well know what this amounts to, we
run no risk of deceiving ourselves about the range of the results it
gives us.

We have had hitherto prophets of evil. They blithely reiterate that all
problems capable of solution have already been solved, and that nothing
is left but gleaning. Happily the case of the past reassures us. Often
it was thought all problems were solved or at least an inventory was
made of all admitting solution. And then the sense of the word solution
enlarged, the insoluble problems became the most interesting of all, and
others unforeseen presented themselves. For the Greeks a good solution
was one employing only ruler and compasses; then it became one obtained
by the extraction of roots, then one using only algebraic or logarithmic
functions. The pessimists thus found themselves always outflanked,
always forced to retreat, so that at present I think there are no more.

My intention, therefore, is not to combat them, as they are dead; we
well know that mathematics will continue to develop, but the question is
how, in what direction? You will answer, 'in every direction,' and that
is partly true; but if it were wholly true it would be a little
appalling. Our riches would soon become encumbering and their
accumulation would produce a medley as impenetrable as the unknown true
was for the ignorant.

The historian, the physicist, even, must make a choice among facts; the
head of the scientist, which is only a corner of the universe, could
never contain the universe entire; so that among the innumerable facts
nature offers, some will be passed by, others retained.

Just so, _a fortiori_, in mathematics; no more can the geometer hold
fast pell-mell all the facts presenting themselves to him; all the more
because he it is, almost I had said his caprice, that creates these
facts. He constructs a wholly new combination by putting together its
elements; nature does not in general give it to him ready made.

Doubtless it sometimes happens that the mathematician undertakes a
problem to satisfy a need in physics; that the physicist or engineer
asks him to calculate a number for a certain application. Shall it be
said that we geometers should limit ourselves to awaiting orders, and,
in place of cultivating our science for our own delectation, try only to
accommodate ourselves to the wants of our patrons? If mathematics has no
other object besides aiding those who study nature, it is from these we
should await orders. Is this way of looking at it legitimate? Certainly
not; if we had not cultivated the exact sciences for themselves, we
should not have created mathematics the instrument, and the day the call
came from the physicist we should have been helpless.

Nor do the physicists wait to study a phenomenon until some urgent need
of material life has made it a necessity for them; and they are right.
If the scientists of the eighteenth century had neglected electricity as
being in their eyes only a curiosity without practical interest, we
should have had in the twentieth century neither telegraphy, nor
electro-chemistry, nor electro-technics. The physicists, compelled to
choose, are therefore not guided in their choice solely by utility. How
then do they choose between the facts of nature? We have explained it in
the preceding chapter: the facts which interest them are those capable
of leading to the discovery of a law, and so they are analogous to many
other facts which do not seem to us isolated, but closely grouped with
others. The isolated fact attracts all eyes, those of the layman as well
as of the scientist. But what the genuine physicist alone knows how to
see, is the bond which unites many facts whose analogy is profound but
hidden. The story of Newton's apple is probably not true, but it is
symbolic; let us speak of it then as if it were true. Well then, we must
believe that before Newton plenty of men had seen apples fall; not one
knew how to conclude anything therefrom. Facts would be sterile were
there not minds capable of choosing among them, discerning those behind
which something was hidden, and of recognizing what is hiding, minds
which under the crude fact perceive the soul of the fact.

We find just the same thing in mathematics. From the varied elements at
our disposal we can get millions of different combinations; but one of
these combinations, in so far as it is isolated, is absolutely void of
value. Often we have taken great pains to construct it, but it serves no
purpose, if not perhaps to furnish a task in secondary education. Quite
otherwise will it be when this combination shall find place in a class
of analogous combinations and we shall have noticed this analogy. We are
no longer in the presence of a fact, but of a law. And upon that day the
real discoverer will not be the workman who shall have patiently built
up certain of these combinations; it will be he who brings to light
their kinship. The first will have seen merely the crude fact, only the
other will have perceived the soul of the fact. Often to fix this
kinship it suffices him to make a new word, and this word is creative.
The history of science furnishes us a crowd of examples familiar to all.

The celebrated Vienna philosopher Mach has said that the rôle of science
is to produce economy of thought, just as machines produce economy of
effort. And that is very true. The savage reckons on his fingers or by
heaping pebbles. In teaching children the multiplication table we spare
them later innumerable pebble bunchings. Some one has already found out,
with pebbles or otherwise, that 6 times 7 is 42 and has had the idea of
noting the result, and so we need not do it over again. He did not waste
his time even if he reckoned for pleasure: his operation took him only
two minutes; it would have taken in all two milliards if a milliard men
had had to do it over after him.

The importance of a fact then is measured by its yield, that is to say,
by the amount of thought it permits us to spare.

In physics the facts of great yield are those entering into a very
general law, since from it they enable us to foresee a great number of
others, and just so it is in mathematics. Suppose I have undertaken a
complicated calculation and laboriously reached a result: I shall not
be compensated for my trouble if thereby I have not become capable of
foreseeing the results of other analogous calculations and guiding them
with a certainty that avoids the gropings to which one must be resigned
in a first attempt. On the other hand, I shall not have wasted my time
if these gropings themselves have ended by revealing to me the profound
analogy of the problem just treated with a much more extended class of
other problems; if they have shown me at once the resemblances and
differences of these, if in a word they have made me perceive the
possibility of a generalization. Then it is not a new result I have won,
it is a new power.

The simple example that comes first to mind is that of an algebraic
formula which gives us the solution of a type of numeric problems when
finally we replace the letters by numbers. Thanks to it, a single
algebraic calculation saves us the pains of ceaselessly beginning over
again new numeric calculations. But this is only a crude example; we all
know there are analogies inexpressible by a formula and all the more
precious.

A new result is of value, if at all, when in unifying elements long
known but hitherto separate and seeming strangers one to another it
suddenly introduces order where apparently disorder reigned. It then
permits us to see at a glance each of these elements and its place in
the assemblage. This new fact is not merely precious by itself, but it
alone gives value to all the old facts it combines. Our mind is weak as
are the senses; it would lose itself in the world's complexity were this
complexity not harmonious; like a near-sighted person, it would see only
the details and would be forced to forget each of these details before
examining the following, since it would be incapable of embracing all.
The only facts worthy our attention are those which introduce order into
this complexity and so make it accessible.

Mathematicians attach great importance to the elegance of their methods
and their results. This is not pure dilettantism. What is it indeed that
gives us the feeling of elegance in a solution, in a demonstration? It
is the harmony of the diverse parts, their symmetry, their happy
balance; in a word it is all that introduces order, all that gives
unity, that permits us to see clearly and to comprehend at once both the
_ensemble_ and the details. But this is exactly what yields great
results; in fact the more we see this aggregate clearly and at a single
glance, the better we perceive its analogies with other neighboring
objects, consequently the more chances we have of divining the possible
generalizations. Elegance may produce the feeling of the unforeseen by
the unexpected meeting of objects we are not accustomed to bring
together; there again it is fruitful, since it thus unveils for us
kinships before unrecognized. It is fruitful even when it results only
from the contrast between the simplicity of the means and the complexity
of the problem set; it makes us then think of the reason for this
contrast and very often makes us see that chance is not the reason; that
it is to be found in some unexpected law. In a word, the feeling of
mathematical elegance is only the satisfaction due to any adaptation of
the solution to the needs of our mind, and it is because of this very
adaptation that this solution can be for us an instrument. Consequently
this esthetic satisfaction is bound up with the economy of thought.
Again the comparison of the Erechtheum comes to my mind, but I must not
use it too often.

It is for the same reason that, when a rather long calculation has led
to some simple and striking result, we are not satisfied until we have
shown that we should have been _able to foresee_, if not this entire
result, at least its most characteristic traits. Why? What prevents our
being content with a calculation which has told us, it seems, all we
wished to know? It is because, in analogous cases, the long calculation
might not again avail, and that this is not so about the reasoning often
half intuitive which would have enabled us to foresee. This reasoning
being short, we see at a single glance all its parts, so that we
immediately perceive what must be changed to adapt it to all the
problems of the same nature which can occur. And then it enables us to
foresee if the solution of these problems will be simple, it shows us at
least if the calculation is worth undertaking.

What we have just said suffices to show how vain it would be to seek to
replace by any mechanical procedure the free initiative of the
mathematician. To obtain a result of real value, it is not enough to
grind out calculations, or to have a machine to put things in order; it
is not order alone, it is unexpected order, which is worth while. The
machine may gnaw on the crude fact, the soul of the fact will always
escape it.

Since the middle of the last century, mathematicians are more and more
desirous of attaining absolute rigor; they are right, and this tendency
will be more and more accentuated. In mathematics rigor is not
everything, but without it there is nothing. A demonstration which is
not rigorous is nothingness. I think no one will contest this truth. But
if it were taken too literally, we should be led to conclude that before
1820, for example, there was no mathematics; this would be manifestly
excessive; the geometers of that time understood voluntarily what we
explain by prolix discourse. This does not mean that they did not see it
at all; but they passed over it too rapidly, and to see it well would
have necessitated taking the pains to say it.

But is it always needful to say it so many times? Those who were the
first to emphasize exactness before all else have given us arguments
that we may try to imitate; but if the demonstrations of the future are
to be built on this model, mathematical treatises will be very long; and
if I fear the lengthenings, it is not solely because I deprecate
encumbering libraries, but because I fear that in being lengthened out,
our demonstrations may lose that appearance of harmony whose usefulness
I have just explained.

The economy of thought is what we should aim at, so it is not enough to
supply models for imitation. It is needful for those after us to be able
to dispense with these models and, in place of repeating an argument
already made, summarize it in a few words. And this has already been
attained at times. For instance, there was a type of reasoning found
everywhere, and everywhere alike. They were perfectly exact but long.
Then all at once the phrase 'uniformity of convergence' was hit upon and
this phrase made those arguments needless; we were no longer called upon
to repeat them, since they could be understood. Those who conquer
difficulties then do us a double service: first they teach us to do as
they at need, but above all they enable us as often as possible to avoid
doing as they, yet without sacrifice of exactness.

We have just seen by one example the importance of words in mathematics,
but many others could be cited. It is hard to believe how much a
well-chosen word can economize thought, as Mach says. Perhaps I have
already said somewhere that mathematics is the art of giving the same
name to different things. It is proper that these things, differing in
matter, be alike in form, that they may, so to speak, run in the same
mold. When the language has been well chosen, we are astonished to see
that all the proofs made for a certain object apply immediately to many
new objects; there is nothing to change, not even the words, since the
names have become the same.

A well-chosen word usually suffices to do away with the exceptions from
which the rules stated in the old way suffer; this is why we have
created negative quantities, imaginaries, points at infinity, and what
not. And exceptions, we must not forget, are pernicious because they
hide the laws.

Well, this is one of the characteristics by which we recognize the facts
which yield great results. They are those which allow of these happy
innovations of language. The crude fact then is often of no great
interest; we may point it out many times without having rendered great
service to science. It takes value only when a wiser thinker perceives
the relation for which it stands, and symbolizes it by a word.

Moreover the physicists do just the same. They have invented the word
'energy,' and this word has been prodigiously fruitful, because it also
made the law by eliminating the exceptions, since it gave the same name
to things differing in matter and like in form.

Among words that have had the most fortunate influence I would select
'group' and 'invariant.' They have made us see the essence of many
mathematical reasonings; they have shown us in how many cases the old
mathematicians considered groups without knowing it, and how, believing
themselves far from one another, they suddenly found themselves near
without knowing why.

To-day we should say that they had dealt with isomorphic groups. We now
know that in a group the matter is of little interest, the form alone
counts, and that when we know a group we thus know all the isomorphic
groups; and thanks to these words 'group' and 'isomorphism,' which
condense in a few syllables this subtile rule and quickly make it
familiar to all minds, the transition is immediate and can be done with
every economy of thought effort. The idea of group besides attaches to
that of transformation. Why do we put such a value on the invention of a
new transformation? Because from a single theorem it enables us to get
ten or twenty; it has the same value as a zero adjoined to the right of
a whole number.

This then it is which has hitherto determined the direction of
mathematical advance, and just as certainly will determine it in the
future. But to this end the nature of the problems which come up
contributes equally. We can not forget what must be our aim. In my
opinion this aim is double. Our science borders upon both philosophy and
physics, and we work for our two neighbors; so we have always seen and
shall still see mathematicians advancing in two opposite directions.

On the one hand, mathematical science must reflect upon itself, and that
is useful since reflecting on itself is reflecting on the human mind
which has created it, all the more because it is the very one of its
creations for which it has borrowed least from without. This is why
certain mathematical speculations are useful, such as those devoted to
the study of the postulates, of unusual geometries, of peculiar
functions. The more these speculations diverge from ordinary
conceptions, and consequently from nature and applications, the better
they show us what the human mind can create when it frees itself more
and more from the tyranny of the external world, the better therefore
they let us know it in itself.

But it is toward the other side, the side of nature, that we must direct
the bulk of our army. There we meet the physicist or the engineer, who
says to us: "Please integrate this differential equation for me; I might
need it in a week in view of a construction which should be finished by
that time." "This equation," we answer, "does not come under one of the
integrable types; you know there are not many." "Yes, I know; but then
what good are you?" Usually to understand each other is enough; the
engineer in reality does not need the integral in finite terms; he
needs to know the general look of the integral function, or he simply
wants a certain number which could readily be deduced from this integral
if it were known. Usually it is not known, but the number can be
calculated without it if we know exactly what number the engineer needs
and with what approximation.

Formerly an equation was considered solved only when its solution had
been expressed by aid of a finite number of known functions; but that is
possible scarcely once in a hundred times. What we always can do, or
rather what we should always seek to do, is to solve the problem
_qualitatively_ so to speak; that is to say, seek to know the general
form of the curve which represents the unknown function.

It remains to find the _quantitative_ solution of the problem; but if
the unknown can not be determined by a finite calculation, it may always
be represented by a convergent infinite series which enables us to
calculate it. Can that be regarded as a true solution? We are told that
Newton sent Leibnitz an anagram almost like this: aaaaabbbeeeeij, etc.
Leibnitz naturally understood nothing at all of it; but we, who have the
key, know that this anagram meant, translated into modern terms: "I can
integrate all differential equations"; and we are tempted to say that
Newton had either great luck or strange delusions. He merely wished to
say he could form (by the method of indeterminate coefficients) a series
of powers formally satisfying the proposed equation.

Such a solution would not satisfy us to-day, and for two reasons:
because the convergence is too slow and because the terms follow each
other without obeying any law. On the contrary, the series [Theta] seems
to us to leave nothing to be desired, first because it converges very
quickly (this is for the practical man who wishes to get at a number as
quickly as possible) and next because we see at a glance the law of the
terms (this is to satisfy the esthetic need of the theorist).

But then there are no longer solved problems and others which are not;
there are only problems _more or less_ solved, according as they are
solved by a series converging more or less rapidly, or ruled by a law
more or less harmonious. It often happens however that an imperfect
solution guides us toward a better one. Sometimes the series converges
so slowly that the computation is impracticable and we have only
succeeded in proving the possibility of the problem.

And then the engineer finds this a mockery, and justly, since it will
not aid him to complete his construction by the date fixed. He little
cares to know if it will benefit engineers of the twenty-second century.
But as for us, we think differently and we are sometimes happier to have
spared our grandchildren a day's work than to have saved our
contemporaries an hour.

Sometimes by groping, empirically, so to speak, we reach a formula
sufficiently convergent. "What more do you want?" says the engineer. And
yet, in spite of all, we are not satisfied; we should have liked _to
foresee_ that convergence. Why? Because if we had known how to foresee
it once, we would know how to foresee it another time. We have
succeeded; that is a small matter in our eyes if we can not validly
expect to do so again.

In proportion as science develops, its total comprehension becomes more
difficult; then we seek to cut it in pieces and to be satisfied with one
of these pieces: in a word, to specialize. If we went on in this way, it
would be a grievous obstacle to the progress of science. As we have
said, it is by unexpected union between its diverse parts that it
progresses. To specialize too much would be to forbid these drawings
together. It is to be hoped that congresses like those of Heidelberg and
Rome, by putting us in touch with one another, will open for us vistas
over neighboring domains and oblige us to compare them with our own, to
range somewhat abroad from our own little village; thus they will be the
best remedy for the danger just mentioned.

But I have lingered too long over generalities; it is time to enter into
detail.

Let us pass in review the various special sciences which combined make
mathematics; let us see what each has accomplished, whither it tends and
what we may hope from it. If the preceding views are correct, we should
see that the greatest advances in the past have happened when two of
these sciences have united, when we have become conscious of the
similarity of their form, despite the difference of their matter, when
they have so modeled themselves upon each other that each could profit
by the other's conquests. We should at the same time foresee in
combinations of the same sort the progress of the future.


ARITHMETIC

Progress in arithmetic has been much slower than in algebra and
analysis, and it is easy to see why. The feeling of continuity is a
precious guide which the arithmetician lacks; each whole number is
separated from the others--it has, so to speak, its own individuality.
Each of them is a sort of exception and this is why general theorems are
rarer in the theory of numbers; this is also why those which exist are
more hidden and longer elude the searchers.

If arithmetic is behind algebra and analysis, the best thing for it to
do is to seek to model itself upon these sciences so as to profit by
their advance. The arithmetician ought therefore to take as guide the
analogies with algebra. These analogies are numerous and if, in many
cases, they have not yet been studied sufficiently closely to become
utilizable, they at least have long been foreseen, and even the language
of the two sciences shows they have been recognized. Thus we speak of
transcendent numbers and thus we account for the future classification
of these numbers already having as model the classification of
transcendent functions, and still we do not as yet very well see how to
pass from one classification to the other; but had it been seen, it
would already have been accomplished and would no longer be the work of
the future.

The first example that comes to my mind is the theory of congruences,
where is found a perfect parallelism to the theory of algebraic
equations. Surely we shall succeed in completing this parallelism, which
must hold for instance between the theory of algebraic curves and that
of congruences with two variables. And when the problems relative to
congruences with several variables shall be solved, this will be a first
step toward the solution of many questions of indeterminate analysis.


ALGEBRA

The theory of algebraic equations will still long hold the attention of
geometers; numerous and very different are the sides whence it may be
attacked.

We need not think algebra is ended because it gives us rules to form all
possible combinations; it remains to find the interesting combinations,
those which satisfy such and such a condition. Thus will be formed a
sort of indeterminate analysis where the unknowns will no longer be
whole numbers, but polynomials. This time it is algebra which will model
itself upon arithmetic, following the analogy of the whole number to the
integral polynomial with any coefficients or to the integral polynomial
with integral coefficients.


GEOMETRY

It looks as if geometry could contain nothing which is not already
included in algebra or analysis; that geometric facts are only algebraic
or analytic facts expressed in another language. It might then be
thought that after our review there would remain nothing more for us to
say relating specially to geometry. This would be to fail to recognize
the importance of well-constructed language, not to comprehend what is
added to the things themselves by the method of expressing these things
and consequently of grouping them.

First the geometric considerations lead us to set ourselves new
problems; these may be, if you choose, analytic problems, but such as we
never would have set ourselves in connection with analysis. Analysis
profits by them however, as it profits by those it has to solve to
satisfy the needs of physics.

A great advantage of geometry lies in the fact that in it the senses can
come to the aid of thought, and help find the path to follow, and many
minds prefer to put the problems of analysis into geometric form.
Unhappily our senses can not carry us very far, and they desert us when
we wish to soar beyond the classical three dimensions. Does this mean
that, beyond the restricted domain wherein they seem to wish to imprison
us, we should rely only on pure analysis and that all geometry of more
than three dimensions is vain and objectless? The greatest masters of a
preceding generation would have answered 'yes'; to-day we are so
familiarized with this notion that we can speak of it, even in a
university course, without arousing too much astonishment.

But what good is it? That is easy to see: First it gives us a very
convenient terminology, which expresses concisely what the ordinary
analytic language would say in prolix phrases. Moreover, this language
makes us call like things by the same name and emphasize analogies it
will never again let us forget. It enables us therefore still to find
our way in this space which is too big for us and which we can not see,
always recalling visible space, which is only an imperfect image of it
doubtless, but which is nevertheless an image. Here again, as in all the
preceding examples, it is analogy with the simple which enables us to
comprehend the complex.

This geometry of more than three dimensions is not a simple analytic
geometry; it is not purely quantitative, but qualitative also, and it is
in this respect above all that it becomes interesting. There is a
science called _analysis situs_ and which has for its object the study
of the positional relations of the different elements of a figure, apart
from their sizes. This geometry is purely qualitative; its theorems
would remain true if the figures, instead of being exact, were roughly
imitated by a child. We may also make an _analysis situs_ of more than
three dimensions. The importance of _analysis situs_ is enormous and can
not be too much emphasized; the advantage obtained from it by Riemann,
one of its chief creators, would suffice to prove this. We must achieve
its complete construction in the higher spaces; then we shall have an
instrument which will enable us really to see in hyperspace and
supplement our senses.

The problems of _analysis situs_ would perhaps not have suggested
themselves if the analytic language alone had been spoken; or rather, I
am mistaken, they would have occurred surely, since their solution is
essential to a crowd of questions in analysis, but they would have come
singly, one after another, and without our being able to perceive their
common bond.


CANTORISM

I have spoken above of our need to go back continually to the first
principles of our science, and of the advantage of this for the study of
the human mind. This need has inspired two endeavors which have taken a
very prominent place in the most recent annals of mathematics. The first
is Cantorism, which has rendered our science such conspicuous service.
Cantor introduced into science a new way of considering mathematical
infinity. One of the characteristic traits of Cantorism is that in place
of going up to the general by building up constructions more and more
complicated and defining by construction, it starts from the _genus
supremum_ and defines only, as the scholastics would have said, _per
genus proximum et differentiam specificam_. Thence comes the horror it
has sometimes inspired in certain minds, for instance in Hermite, whose
favorite idea was to compare the mathematical to the natural sciences.
With most of us these prejudices have been dissipated, but it has come
to pass that we have encountered certain paradoxes, certain apparent
contradictions that would have delighted Zeno, the Eleatic and the
school of Megara. And then each must seek the remedy. For my part, I
think, and I am not the only one, that the important thing is never to
introduce entities not completely definable in a finite number of words.
Whatever be the cure adopted, we may promise ourselves the joy of the
doctor called in to follow a beautiful pathologic case.


THE INVESTIGATION OF THE POSTULATES

On the other hand, efforts have been made to enumerate the axioms and
postulates, more or less hidden, which serve as foundation to the
different theories of mathematics. Professor Hilbert has obtained the
most brilliant results. It seems at first that this domain would be very
restricted and there would be nothing more to do when the inventory
should be ended, which could not take long. But when we shall have
enumerated all, there will be many ways of classifying all; a good
librarian always finds something to do, and each new classification will
be instructive for the philosopher.

Here I end this review which I could not dream of making complete. I
think these examples will suffice to show by what mechanism the
mathematical sciences have made their progress in the past and in what
direction they must advance in the future.



CHAPTER III

MATHEMATICAL CREATION


The genesis of mathematical creation is a problem which should intensely
interest the psychologist. It is the activity in which the human mind
seems to take least from the outside world, in which it acts or seems to
act only of itself and on itself, so that in studying the procedure of
geometric thought we may hope to reach what is most essential in man's
mind.

This has long been appreciated, and some time back the journal called
_L'enseignement mathématique_, edited by Laisant and Fehr, began an
investigation of the mental habits and methods of work of different
mathematicians. I had finished the main outlines of this article when
the results of that inquiry were published, so I have hardly been able
to utilize them and shall confine myself to saying that the majority of
witnesses confirm my conclusions; I do not say all, for when the appeal
is to universal suffrage unanimity is not to be hoped.

A first fact should surprise us, or rather would surprise us if we were
not so used to it. How does it happen there are people who do not
understand mathematics? If mathematics invokes only the rules of logic,
such as are accepted by all normal minds; if its evidence is based on
principles common to all men, and that none could deny without being
mad, how does it come about that so many persons are here refractory?

That not every one can invent is nowise mysterious. That not every one
can retain a demonstration once learned may also pass. But that not
every one can understand mathematical reasoning when explained appears
very surprising when we think of it. And yet those who can follow this
reasoning only with difficulty are in the majority: that is undeniable,
and will surely not be gainsaid by the experience of secondary-school
teachers.

And further: how is error possible in mathematics? A sane mind should
not be guilty of a logical fallacy, and yet there are very fine minds
who do not trip in brief reasoning such as occurs in the ordinary doings
of life, and who are incapable of following or repeating without error
the mathematical demonstrations which are longer, but which after all
are only an accumulation of brief reasonings wholly analogous to those
they make so easily. Need we add that mathematicians themselves are not
infallible?

The answer seems to me evident. Imagine a long series of syllogisms, and
that the conclusions of the first serve as premises of the following: we
shall be able to catch each of these syllogisms, and it is not in
passing from premises to conclusion that we are in danger of deceiving
ourselves. But between the moment in which we first meet a proposition
as conclusion of one syllogism, and that in which we reencounter it as
premise of another syllogism occasionally some time will elapse, several
links of the chain will have unrolled; so it may happen that we have
forgotten it, or worse, that we have forgotten its meaning. So it may
happen that we replace it by a slightly different proposition, or that,
while retaining the same enunciation, we attribute to it a slightly
different meaning, and thus it is that we are exposed to error.

Often the mathematician uses a rule. Naturally he begins by
demonstrating this rule; and at the time when this proof is fresh in his
memory he understands perfectly its meaning and its bearing, and he is
in no danger of changing it. But subsequently he trusts his memory and
afterward only applies it in a mechanical way; and then if his memory
fails him, he may apply it all wrong. Thus it is, to take a simple
example, that we sometimes make slips in calculation because we have
forgotten our multiplication table.

According to this, the special aptitude for mathematics would be due
only to a very sure memory or to a prodigious force of attention. It
would be a power like that of the whist-player who remembers the cards
played; or, to go up a step, like that of the chess-player who can
visualize a great number of combinations and hold them in his memory.
Every good mathematician ought to be a good chess-player, and inversely;
likewise he should be a good computer. Of course that sometimes happens;
thus Gauss was at the same time a geometer of genius and a very
precocious and accurate computer.

But there are exceptions; or rather I err; I can not call them
exceptions without the exceptions being more than the rule. Gauss it is,
on the contrary, who was an exception. As for myself, I must confess, I
am absolutely incapable even of adding without mistakes. In the same way
I should be but a poor chess-player; I would perceive that by a certain
play I should expose myself to a certain danger; I would pass in review
several other plays, rejecting them for other reasons, and then finally
I should make the move first examined, having meantime forgotten the
danger I had foreseen.

In a word, my memory is not bad, but it would be insufficient to make me
a good chess-player. Why then does it not fail me in a difficult piece
of mathematical reasoning where most chess-players would lose
themselves? Evidently because it is guided by the general march of the
reasoning. A mathematical demonstration is not a simple juxtaposition of
syllogisms, it is syllogisms _placed in a certain order_, and the order
in which these elements are placed is much more important than the
elements themselves. If I have the feeling, the intuition, so to speak,
of this order, so as to perceive at a glance the reasoning as a whole, I
need no longer fear lest I forget one of the elements, for each of them
will take its allotted place in the array, and that without any effort
of memory on my part.

It seems to me then, in repeating a reasoning learned, that I could have
invented it. This is often only an illusion; but even then, even if I am
not so gifted as to create it by myself, I myself re-invent it in so far
as I repeat it.

We know that this feeling, this intuition of mathematical order, that
makes us divine hidden harmonies and relations, can not be possessed by
every one. Some will not have either this delicate feeling so difficult
to define, or a strength of memory and attention beyond the ordinary,
and then they will be absolutely incapable of understanding higher
mathematics. Such are the majority. Others will have this feeling only
in a slight degree, but they will be gifted with an uncommon memory and
a great power of attention. They will learn by heart the details one
after another; they can understand mathematics and sometimes make
applications, but they cannot create. Others, finally, will possess in a
less or greater degree the special intuition referred to, and then not
only can they understand mathematics even if their memory is nothing
extraordinary, but they may become creators and try to invent with more
or less success according as this intuition is more or less developed in
them.

In fact, what is mathematical creation? It does not consist in making
new combinations with mathematical entities already known. Any one could
do that, but the combinations so made would be infinite in number and
most of them absolutely without interest. To create consists precisely
in not making useless combinations and in making those which are useful
and which are only a small minority. Invention is discernment, choice.

How to make this choice I have before explained; the mathematical facts
worthy of being studied are those which, by their analogy with other
facts, are capable of leading us to the knowledge of a mathematical law
just as experimental facts lead us to the knowledge of a physical law.
They are those which reveal to us unsuspected kinship between other
facts, long known, but wrongly believed to be strangers to one another.

Among chosen combinations the most fertile will often be those formed of
elements drawn from domains which are far apart. Not that I mean as
sufficing for invention the bringing together of objects as disparate as
possible; most combinations so formed would be entirely sterile. But
certain among them, very rare, are the most fruitful of all.

To invent, I have said, is to choose; but the word is perhaps not wholly
exact. It makes one think of a purchaser before whom are displayed a
large number of samples, and who examines them, one after the other, to
make a choice. Here the samples would be so numerous that a whole
lifetime would not suffice to examine them. This is not the actual state
of things. The sterile combinations do not even present themselves to
the mind of the inventor. Never in the field of his consciousness do
combinations appear that are not really useful, except some that he
rejects but which have to some extent the characteristics of useful
combinations. All goes on as if the inventor were an examiner for the
second degree who would only have to question the candidates who had
passed a previous examination.

But what I have hitherto said is what may be observed or inferred in
reading the writings of the geometers, reading reflectively.

It is time to penetrate deeper and to see what goes on in the very soul
of the mathematician. For this, I believe, I can do best by recalling
memories of my own. But I shall limit myself to telling how I wrote my
first memoir on Fuchsian functions. I beg the reader's pardon; I am
about to use some technical expressions, but they need not frighten him,
for he is not obliged to understand them. I shall say, for example, that
I have found the demonstration of such a theorem under such
circumstances. This theorem will have a barbarous name, unfamiliar to
many, but that is unimportant; what is of interest for the psychologist
is not the theorem but the circumstances.

For fifteen days I strove to prove that there could not be any functions
like those I have since called Fuchsian functions. I was then very
ignorant; every day I seated myself at my work table, stayed an hour or
two, tried a great number of combinations and reached no results. One
evening, contrary to my custom, I drank black coffee and could not
sleep. Ideas rose in crowds; I felt them collide until pairs
interlocked, so to speak, making a stable combination. By the next
morning I had established the existence of a class of Fuchsian
functions, those which come from the hypergeometric series; I had only
to write out the results, which took but a few hours.

Then I wanted to represent these functions by the quotient of two
series; this idea was perfectly conscious and deliberate, the analogy
with elliptic functions guided me. I asked myself what properties these
series must have if they existed, and I succeeded without difficulty in
forming the series I have called theta-Fuchsian.

Just at this time I left Caen, where I was then living, to go on a
geologic excursion under the auspices of the school of mines. The
changes of travel made me forget my mathematical work. Having reached
Coutances, we entered an omnibus to go some place or other. At the
moment when I put my foot on the step the idea came to me, without
anything in my former thoughts seeming to have paved the way for it,
that the transformations I had used to define the Fuchsian functions
were identical with those of non-Euclidean geometry. I did not verify
the idea; I should not have had time, as, upon taking my seat in the
omnibus, I went on with a conversation already commenced, but I felt a
perfect certainty. On my return to Caen, for conscience' sake I verified
the result at my leisure.

Then I turned my attention to the study of some arithmetical questions
apparently without much success and without a suspicion of any
connection with my preceding researches. Disgusted with my failure, I
went to spend a few days at the seaside, and thought of something else.
One morning, walking on the bluff, the idea came to me, with just the
same characteristics of brevity, suddenness and immediate certainty,
that the arithmetic transformations of indeterminate ternary quadratic
forms were identical with those of non-Euclidean geometry.

Returned to Caen, I meditated on this result and deduced the
consequences. The example of quadratic forms showed me that there were
Fuchsian groups other than those corresponding to the hypergeometric
series; I saw that I could apply to them the theory of theta-Fuchsian
series and that consequently there existed Fuchsian functions other than
those from the hypergeometric series, the ones I then knew. Naturally I
set myself to form all these functions. I made a systematic attack upon
them and carried all the outworks, one after another. There was one
however that still held out, whose fall would involve that of the whole
place. But all my efforts only served at first the better to show me the
difficulty, which indeed was something. All this work was perfectly
conscious.

Thereupon I left for Mont-Valérien, where I was to go through my
military service; so I was very differently occupied. One day, going
along the street, the solution of the difficulty which had stopped me
suddenly appeared to me. I did not try to go deep into it immediately,
and only after my service did I again take up the question. I had all
the elements and had only to arrange them and put them together. So I
wrote out my final memoir at a single stroke and without difficulty.

I shall limit myself to this single example; it is useless to multiply
them. In regard to my other researches I would have to say analogous
things, and the observations of other mathematicians given in
_L'enseignement mathématique_ would only confirm them.

Most striking at first is this appearance of sudden illumination, a
manifest sign of long, unconscious prior work. The rôle of this
unconscious work in mathematical invention appears to me incontestable,
and traces of it would be found in other cases where it is less evident.
Often when one works at a hard question, nothing good is accomplished at
the first attack. Then one takes a rest, longer or shorter, and sits
down anew to the work. During the first half-hour, as before, nothing is
found, and then all of a sudden the decisive idea presents itself to the
mind. It might be said that the conscious work has been more fruitful
because it has been interrupted and the rest has given back to the mind
its force and freshness. But it is more probable that this rest has been
filled out with unconscious work and that the result of this work has
afterward revealed itself to the geometer just as in the cases I have
cited; only the revelation, instead of coming during a walk or a
journey, has happened during a period of conscious work, but
independently of this work which plays at most a rôle of excitant, as if
it were the goad stimulating the results already reached during rest,
but remaining unconscious, to assume the conscious form.

There is another remark to be made about the conditions of this
unconscious work: it is possible, and of a certainty it is only
fruitful, if it is on the one hand preceded and on the other hand
followed by a period of conscious work. These sudden inspirations (and
the examples already cited sufficiently prove this) never happen except
after some days of voluntary effort which has appeared absolutely
fruitless and whence nothing good seems to have come, where the way
taken seems totally astray. These efforts then have not been as sterile
as one thinks; they have set agoing the unconscious machine and without
them it would not have moved and would have produced nothing.

The need for the second period of conscious work, after the inspiration,
is still easier to understand. It is necessary to put in shape the
results of this inspiration, to deduce from them the immediate
consequences, to arrange them, to word the demonstrations, but above all
is verification necessary. I have spoken of the feeling of absolute
certitude accompanying the inspiration; in the cases cited this feeling
was no deceiver, nor is it usually. But do not think this a rule without
exception; often this feeling deceives us without being any the less
vivid, and we only find it out when we seek to put on foot the
demonstration. I have especially noticed this fact in regard to ideas
coming to me in the morning or evening in bed while in a semi-hypnagogic
state.

Such are the realities; now for the thoughts they force upon us. The
unconscious, or, as we say, the subliminal self plays an important rôle
in mathematical creation; this follows from what we have said. But
usually the subliminal self is considered as purely automatic. Now we
have seen that mathematical work is not simply mechanical, that it could
not be done by a machine, however perfect. It is not merely a question
of applying rules, of making the most combinations possible according to
certain fixed laws. The combinations so obtained would be exceedingly
numerous, useless and cumbersome. The true work of the inventor consists
in choosing among these combinations so as to eliminate the useless ones
or rather to avoid the trouble of making them, and the rules which must
guide this choice are extremely fine and delicate. It is almost
impossible to state them precisely; they are felt rather than
formulated. Under these conditions, how imagine a sieve capable of
applying them mechanically?

A first hypothesis now presents itself: the subliminal self is in no way
inferior to the conscious self; it is not purely automatic; it is
capable of discernment; it has tact, delicacy; it knows how to choose,
to divine. What do I say? It knows better how to divine than the
conscious self, since it succeeds where that has failed. In a word, is
not the subliminal self superior to the conscious self? You recognize
the full importance of this question. Boutroux in a recent lecture has
shown how it came up on a very different occasion, and what consequences
would follow an affirmative answer. (See also, by the same author,
_Science et Religion_, pp. 313 ff.)

Is this affirmative answer forced upon us by the facts I have just
given? I confess that, for my part, I should hate to accept it.
Reexamine the facts then and see if they are not compatible with another
explanation.

It is certain that the combinations which present themselves to the mind
in a sort of sudden illumination, after an unconscious working somewhat
prolonged, are generally useful and fertile combinations, which seem the
result of a first impression. Does it follow that the subliminal self,
having divined by a delicate intuition that these combinations would be
useful, has formed only these, or has it rather formed many others which
were lacking in interest and have remained unconscious?

In this second way of looking at it, all the combinations would be
formed in consequence of the automatism of the subliminal self, but only
the interesting ones would break into the domain of consciousness. And
this is still very mysterious. What is the cause that, among the
thousand products of our unconscious activity, some are called to pass
the threshold, while others remain below? Is it a simple chance which
confers this privilege? Evidently not; among all the stimuli of our
senses, for example, only the most intense fix our attention, unless it
has been drawn to them by other causes. More generally the privileged
unconscious phenomena, those susceptible of becoming conscious, are
those which, directly or indirectly, affect most profoundly our
emotional sensibility.

It may be surprising to see emotional sensibility invoked _à propos_ of
mathematical demonstrations which, it would seem, can interest only the
intellect. This would be to forget the feeling of mathematical beauty,
of the harmony of numbers and forms, of geometric elegance. This is a
true esthetic feeling that all real mathematicians know, and surely it
belongs to emotional sensibility.

Now, what are the mathematic entities to which we attribute this
character of beauty and elegance, and which are capable of developing in
us a sort of esthetic emotion? They are those whose elements are
harmoniously disposed so that the mind without effort can embrace their
totality while realizing the details. This harmony is at once a
satisfaction of our esthetic needs and an aid to the mind, sustaining
and guiding; And at the same time, in putting under our eyes a
well-ordered whole, it makes us foresee a mathematical law. Now, as we
have said above, the only mathematical facts worthy of fixing our
attention and capable of being useful are those which can teach us a
mathematical law. So that we reach the following conclusion: The useful
combinations are precisely the most beautiful, I mean those best able to
charm this special sensibility that all mathematicians know, but of
which the profane are so ignorant as often to be tempted to smile at it.

What happens then? Among the great numbers of combinations blindly
formed by the subliminal self, almost all are without interest and
without utility; but just for that reason they are also without effect
upon the esthetic sensibility. Consciousness will never know them; only
certain ones are harmonious, and, consequently, at once useful and
beautiful. They will be capable of touching this special sensibility of
the geometer of which I have just spoken, and which, once aroused, will
call our attention to them, and thus give them occasion to become
conscious.

This is only a hypothesis, and yet here is an observation which may
confirm it: when a sudden illumination seizes upon the mind of the
mathematician, it usually happens that it does not deceive him, but it
also sometimes happens, as I have said, that it does not stand the test
of verification; well, we almost always notice that this false idea, had
it been true, would have gratified our natural feeling for mathematical
elegance.

Thus it is this special esthetic sensibility which plays the rôle of the
delicate sieve of which I spoke, and that sufficiently explains why the
one lacking it will never be a real creator.

Yet all the difficulties have not disappeared. The conscious self is
narrowly limited, and as for the subliminal self we know not its
limitations, and this is why we are not too reluctant in supposing that
it has been able in a short time to make more different combinations
than the whole life of a conscious being could encompass. Yet these
limitations exist. Is it likely that it is able to form all the possible
combinations, whose number would frighten the imagination? Nevertheless
that would seem necessary, because if it produces only a small part of
these combinations, and if it makes them at random, there would be
small chance that the _good_, the one we should choose, would be found
among them.

Perhaps we ought to seek the explanation in that preliminary period of
conscious work which always precedes all fruitful unconscious labor.
Permit me a rough comparison. Figure the future elements of our
combinations as something like the hooked atoms of Epicurus. During the
complete repose of the mind, these atoms are motionless, they are, so to
speak, hooked to the wall; so this complete rest may be indefinitely
prolonged without the atoms meeting, and consequently without any
combination between them.

On the other hand, during a period of apparent rest and unconscious
work, certain of them are detached from the wall and put in motion. They
flash in every direction through the space (I was about to say the room)
where they are enclosed, as would, for example, a swarm of gnats or, if
you prefer a more learned comparison, like the molecules of gas in the
kinematic theory of gases. Then their mutual impacts may produce new
combinations.

What is the rôle of the preliminary conscious work? It is evidently to
mobilize certain of these atoms, to unhook them from the wall and put
them in swing. We think we have done no good, because we have moved
these elements a thousand different ways in seeking to assemble them,
and have found no satisfactory aggregate. But, after this shaking up
imposed upon them by our will, these atoms do not return to their
primitive rest. They freely continue their dance.

Now, our will did not choose them at random; it pursued a perfectly
determined aim. The mobilized atoms are therefore not any atoms
whatsoever; they are those from which we might reasonably expect the
desired solution. Then the mobilized atoms undergo impacts which make
them enter into combinations among themselves or with other atoms at
rest which they struck against in their course. Again I beg pardon, my
comparison is very rough, but I scarcely know how otherwise to make my
thought understood.

However it may be, the only combinations that have a chance of forming
are those where at least one of the elements is one of those atoms
freely chosen by our will. Now, it is evidently among these that is
found what I called the _good combination_. Perhaps this is a way of
lessening the paradoxical in the original hypothesis.

Another observation. It never happens that the unconscious work gives us
the result of a somewhat long calculation _all made_, where we have only
to apply fixed rules. We might think the wholly automatic subliminal
self particularly apt for this sort of work, which is in a way
exclusively mechanical. It seems that thinking in the evening upon the
factors of a multiplication we might hope to find the product ready made
upon our awakening, or again that an algebraic calculation, for example
a verification, would be made unconsciously. Nothing of the sort, as
observation proves. All one may hope from these inspirations, fruits of
unconscious work, is a point of departure for such calculations. As for
the calculations themselves, they must be made in the second period of
conscious work, that which follows the inspiration, that in which one
verifies the results of this inspiration and deduces their consequences.
The rules of these calculations are strict and complicated. They require
discipline, attention, will, and therefore consciousness. In the
subliminal self, on the contrary, reigns what I should call liberty, if
we might give this name to the simple absence of discipline and to the
disorder born of chance. Only, this disorder itself permits unexpected
combinations.

I shall make a last remark: when above I made certain personal
observations, I spoke of a night of excitement when I worked in spite of
myself. Such cases are frequent, and it is not necessary that the
abnormal cerebral activity be caused by a physical excitant as in that I
mentioned. It seems, in such cases, that one is present at his own
unconscious work, made partially perceptible to the over-excited
consciousness, yet without having changed its nature. Then we vaguely
comprehend what distinguishes the two mechanisms or, if you wish, the
working methods of the two egos. And the psychologic observations I have
been able thus to make seem to me to confirm in their general outlines
the views I have given.

Surely they have need of it, for they are and remain in spite of all
very hypothetical: the interest of the questions is so great that I do
not repent of having submitted them to the reader.



CHAPTER IV

CHANCE


I

"How dare we speak of the laws of chance? Is not chance the antithesis
of all law?" So says Bertrand at the beginning of his _Calcul des
probabiltités_. Probability is opposed to certitude; so it is what we do
not know and consequently it seems what we could not calculate. Here is
at least apparently a contradiction, and about it much has already been
written.

And first, what is chance? The ancients distinguished between phenomena
seemingly obeying harmonious laws, established once for all, and those
which they attributed to chance; these were the ones unpredictable
because rebellious to all law. In each domain the precise laws did not
decide everything, they only drew limits between which chance might act.
In this conception the word chance had a precise and objective meaning;
what was chance for one was also chance for another and even for the
gods.

But this conception is not ours to-day. We have become absolute
determinists, and even those who want to reserve the rights of human
free will let determinism reign undividedly in the inorganic world at
least. Every phenomenon, however minute, has a cause; and a mind
infinitely powerful, infinitely well-informed about the laws of nature,
could have foreseen it from the beginning of the centuries. If such a
mind existed, we could not play with it at any game of chance; we should
always lose.

In fact for it the word chance would not have any meaning, or rather
there would be no chance. It is because of our weakness and our
ignorance that the word has a meaning for us. And, even without going
beyond our feeble humanity, what is chance for the ignorant is not
chance for the scientist. Chance is only the measure of our ignorance.
Fortuitous phenomena are, by definition, those whose laws we do not
know.

But is this definition altogether satisfactory? When the first Chaldean
shepherds followed with their eyes the movements of the stars, they knew
not as yet the laws of astronomy; would they have dreamed of saying that
the stars move at random? If a modern physicist studies a new
phenomenon, and if he discovers its law Tuesday, would he have said
Monday that this phenomenon was fortuitous? Moreover, do we not often
invoke what Bertrand calls the laws of chance, to predict a phenomenon?
For example, in the kinetic theory of gases we obtain the known laws of
Mariotte and of Gay-Lussac by means of the hypothesis that the
velocities of the molecules of gas vary irregularly, that is to say at
random. All physicists will agree that the observable laws would be much
less simple if the velocities were ruled by any simple elementary law
whatsoever, if the molecules were, as we say, _organized_, if they were
subject to some discipline. It is due to chance, that is to say, to our
ignorance, that we can draw our conclusions; and then if the word chance
is simply synonymous with ignorance what does that mean? Must we
therefore translate as follows?

"You ask me to predict for you the phenomena about to happen. If,
unluckily, I knew the laws of these phenomena I could make the
prediction only by inextricable calculations and would have to renounce
attempting to answer you; but as I have the good fortune not to know
them, I will answer you at once. And what is most surprising, my answer
will be right."

So it must well be that chance is something other than the name we give
our ignorance, that among phenomena whose causes are unknown to us we
must distinguish fortuitous phenomena about which the calculus of
probabilities will provisionally give information, from those which are
not fortuitous and of which we can say nothing so long as we shall not
have determined the laws governing them. For the fortuitous phenomena
themselves, it is clear that the information given us by the calculus of
probabilities will not cease to be true upon the day when these
phenomena shall be better known.

The director of a life insurance company does not know when each of the
insured will die, but he relies upon the calculus of probabilities and
on the law of great numbers, and he is not deceived, since he
distributes dividends to his stockholders. These dividends would not
vanish if a very penetrating and very indiscreet physician should, after
the policies were signed, reveal to the director the life chances of the
insured. This doctor would dissipate the ignorance of the director, but
he would have no influence on the dividends, which evidently are not an
outcome of this ignorance.


II

To find a better definition of chance we must examine some of the facts
which we agree to regard as fortuitous, and to which the calculus of
probabilities seems to apply; we then shall investigate what are their
common characteristics.

The first example we select is that of unstable equilibrium; if a cone
rests upon its apex, we know well that it will fall, but we do not know
toward what side; it seems to us chance alone will decide. If the cone
were perfectly symmetric, if its axis were perfectly vertical, if it
were acted upon by no force other than gravity, it would not fall at
all. But the least defect in symmetry will make it lean slightly toward
one side or the other, and if it leans, however little, it will fall
altogether toward that side. Even if the symmetry were perfect, a very
slight tremor, a breath of air could make it incline some seconds of
arc; this will be enough to determine its fall and even the sense of its
fall which will be that of the initial inclination.

A very slight cause, which escapes us, determines a considerable effect
which we can not help seeing, and then we say this effect is due to
chance. If we could know exactly the laws of nature and the situation of
the universe at the initial instant, we should be able to predict
exactly the situation of this same universe at a subsequent instant. But
even when the natural laws should have no further secret for us, we
could know the initial situation only _approximately_. If that permits
us to foresee the subsequent situation _with the same degree of
approximation_, this is all we require, we say the phenomenon has been
predicted, that it is ruled by laws. But this is not always the case; it
may happen that slight differences in the initial conditions produce
very great differences in the final phenomena; a slight error in the
former would make an enormous error in the latter. Prediction becomes
impossible and we have the fortuitous phenomenon.

Our second example will be very analogous to the first and we shall take
it from meteorology. Why have the meteorologists such difficulty in
predicting the weather with any certainty? Why do the rains, the
tempests themselves seem to us to come by chance, so that many persons
find it quite natural to pray for rain or shine, when they would think
it ridiculous to pray for an eclipse? We see that great perturbations
generally happen in regions where the atmosphere is in unstable
equilibrium. The meteorologists are aware that this equilibrium is
unstable, that a cyclone is arising somewhere; but where they can not
tell; one-tenth of a degree more or less at any point, and the cyclone
bursts here and not there, and spreads its ravages over countries it
would have spared. This we could have foreseen if we had known that
tenth of a degree, but the observations were neither sufficiently close
nor sufficiently precise, and for this reason all seems due to the
agency of chance. Here again we find the same contrast between a very
slight cause, unappreciable to the observer, and important effects,
which are sometimes tremendous disasters.

Let us pass to another example, the distribution of the minor planets on
the zodiac. Their initial longitudes may have been any longitudes
whatever; but their mean motions were different and they have revolved
for so long a time that we may say they are now distributed _at random_
along the zodiac. Very slight initial differences between their
distances from the sun, or, what comes to the same thing, between their
mean motions, have ended by giving enormous differences between their
present longitudes. An excess of the thousandth of a second in the daily
mean motion will give in fact a second in three years, a degree in ten
thousand years, an entire circumference in three or four million years,
and what is that to the time which has passed since the minor planets
detached themselves from the nebula of Laplace? Again therefore we see a
slight cause and a great effect; or better, slight differences in the
cause and great differences in the effect.

The game of roulette does not take us as far as might seem from the
preceding example. Assume a needle to be turned on a pivot over a dial
divided into a hundred sectors alternately red and black. If it stops on
a red sector I win; if not, I lose. Evidently all depends upon the
initial impulse I give the needle. The needle will make, suppose, ten or
twenty turns, but it will stop sooner or not so soon, according as I
shall have pushed it more or less strongly. It suffices that the impulse
vary only by a thousandth or a two thousandth to make the needle stop
over a black sector or over the following red one. These are differences
the muscular sense can not distinguish and which elude even the most
delicate instruments. So it is impossible for me to foresee what the
needle I have started will do, and this is why my heart throbs and I
hope everything from luck. The difference in the cause is imperceptible,
and the difference in the effect is for me of the highest importance,
since it means my whole stake.


III

Permit me, in this connection, a thought somewhat foreign to my subject.
Some years ago a philosopher said that the future is determined by the
past, but not the past by the future; or, in other words, from knowledge
of the present we could deduce the future, but not the past; because,
said he, a cause can have only one effect, while the same effect might
be produced by several different causes. It is clear no scientist can
subscribe to this conclusion. The laws of nature bind the antecedent to
the consequent in such a way that the antecedent is as well determined
by the consequent as the consequent by the antecedent. But whence came
the error of this philosopher? We know that in virtue of Carnot's
principle physical phenomena are irreversible and the world tends toward
uniformity. When two bodies of different temperature come in contact,
the warmer gives up heat to the colder; so we may foresee that the
temperature will equalize. But once equal, if asked about the anterior
state, what can we answer? We might say that one was warm and the other
cold, but not be able to divine which formerly was the warmer.

And yet in reality the temperatures will never reach perfect equality.
The difference of the temperatures only tends asymptotically toward
zero. There comes a moment when our thermometers are powerless to make
it known. But if we had thermometers a thousand times, a hundred
thousand times as sensitive, we should recognize that there still is a
slight difference, and that one of the bodies remains a little warmer
than the other, and so we could say this it is which formerly was much
the warmer.

So then there are, contrary to what we found in the former examples,
great differences in cause and slight differences in effect. Flammarion
once imagined an observer going away from the earth with a velocity
greater than that of light; for him time would have changed sign.
History would be turned about, and Waterloo would precede Austerlitz.
Well, for this observer, effects and causes would be inverted; unstable
equilibrium would no longer be the exception. Because of the universal
irreversibility, all would seem to him to come out of a sort of chaos in
unstable equilibrium. All nature would appear to him delivered over to
chance.


IV

Now for other examples where we shall see somewhat different
characteristics. Take first the kinetic theory of gases. How should we
picture a receptacle filled with gas? Innumerable molecules, moving at
high speeds, flash through this receptacle in every direction. At every
instant they strike against its walls or each other, and these
collisions happen under the most diverse conditions. What above all
impresses us here is not the littleness of the causes, but their
complexity, and yet the former element is still found here and plays an
important rôle. If a molecule deviated right or left from its
trajectory, by a very small quantity, comparable to the radius of action
of the gaseous molecules, it would avoid a collision or sustain it under
different conditions, and that would vary the direction of its velocity
after the impact, perhaps by ninety degrees or by a hundred and eighty
degrees.

And this is not all; we have just seen that it is necessary to deflect
the molecule before the clash by only an infinitesimal, to produce its
deviation after the collision by a finite quantity. If then the molecule
undergoes two successive shocks, it will suffice to deflect it before
the first by an infinitesimal of the second order, for it to deviate
after the first encounter by an infinitesimal of the first order, and
after the second hit, by a finite quantity. And the molecule will not
undergo merely two shocks; it will undergo a very great number per
second. So that if the first shock has multiplied the deviation by a
very large number _A_, after _n_ shocks it will be multiplied by
_A_^{_n_}. It will therefore become very great not merely because _A_
is large, that is to say because little causes produce big effects, but
because the exponent _n_ is large, that is to say because the shocks are
very numerous and the causes very complex.

Take a second example. Why do the drops of rain in a shower seem to be
distributed at random? This is again because of the complexity of the
causes which determine their formation. Ions are distributed in the
atmosphere. For a long while they have been subjected to air-currents
constantly changing, they have been caught in very small whirlwinds, so
that their final distribution has no longer any relation to their
initial distribution. Suddenly the temperature falls, vapor condenses,
and each of these ions becomes the center of a drop of rain. To know
what will be the distribution of these drops and how many will fall on
each paving-stone, it would not be sufficient to know the initial
situation of the ions, it would be necessary to compute the effect of a
thousand little capricious air-currents.

And again it is the same if we put grains of powder in suspension in
water. The vase is ploughed by currents whose law we know not, we only
know it is very complicated. At the end of a certain time the grains
will be distributed at random, that is to say uniformly, in the vase;
and this is due precisely to the complexity of these currents. If they
obeyed some simple law, if for example the vase revolved and the
currents circulated around the axis of the vase, describing circles, it
would no longer be the same, since each grain would retain its initial
altitude and its initial distance from the axis.

We should reach the same result in considering the mixing of two liquids
or of two fine-grained powders. And to take a grosser example, this is
also what happens when we shuffle playing-cards. At each stroke the
cards undergo a permutation (analogous to that studied in the theory of
substitutions). What will happen? The probability of a particular
permutation (for example, that bringing to the _n_th place the card
occupying the [phi](_n_)th place before the permutation) depends upon
the player's habits. But if this player shuffles the cards long enough,
there will be a great number of successive permutations, and the
resulting final order will no longer be governed by aught but chance; I
mean to say that all possible orders will be equally probable. It is to
the great number of successive permutations, that is to say to the
complexity of the phenomenon, that this result is due.

A final word about the theory of errors. Here it is that the causes are
complex and multiple. To how many snares is not the observer exposed,
even with the best instrument! He should apply himself to finding out
the largest and avoiding them. These are the ones giving birth to
systematic errors. But when he has eliminated those, admitting that he
succeeds, there remain many small ones which, their effects
accumulating, may become dangerous. Thence come the accidental errors;
and we attribute them to chance because their causes are too complicated
and too numerous. Here again we have only little causes, but each of
them would produce only a slight effect; it is by their union and their
number that their effects become formidable.


V

We may take still a third point of view, less important than the first
two and upon which I shall lay less stress. When we seek to foresee an
event and examine its antecedents, we strive to search into the anterior
situation. This could not be done for all parts of the universe and we
are content to know what is passing in the neighborhood of the point
where the event should occur, or what would appear to have some relation
to it. An examination can not be complete and we must know how to
choose. But it may happen that we have passed by circumstances which at
first sight seemed completely foreign to the foreseen happening, to
which one would never have dreamed of attributing any influence and
which nevertheless, contrary to all anticipation, come to play an
important rôle.

A man passes in the street going to his business; some one knowing the
business could have told why he started at such a time and went by such
a street. On the roof works a tiler. The contractor employing him could
in a certain measure foresee what he would do. But the passer-by
scarcely thinks of the tiler, nor the tiler of him; they seem to belong
to two worlds completely foreign to one another. And yet the tiler drops
a tile which kills the man, and we do not hesitate to say this is
chance.

Our weakness forbids our considering the entire universe and makes us
cut it up into slices. We try to do this as little artificially as
possible. And yet it happens from time to time that two of these slices
react upon each other. The effects of this mutual action then seem to us
to be due to chance.

Is this a third way of conceiving chance? Not always; in fact most often
we are carried back to the first or the second. Whenever two worlds
usually foreign to one another come thus to react upon each other, the
laws of this reaction must be very complex. On the other hand, a very
slight change in the initial conditions of these two worlds would have
been sufficient for the reaction not to have happened. How little was
needed for the man to pass a second later or the tiler to drop his tile
a second sooner.


VI

All we have said still does not explain why chance obeys laws. Does the
fact that the causes are slight or complex suffice for our foreseeing,
if not their effects _in each case_, at least what their effects will
be, _on the average_? To answer this question we had better take up
again some of the examples already cited.

I shall begin with that of the roulette. I have said that the point
where the needle will stop depends upon the initial push given it. What
is the probability of this push having this or that value? I know
nothing about it, but it is difficult for me not to suppose that this
probability is represented by a continuous analytic function. The
probability that the push is comprised between [alpha] and [alpha] +
[epsilon] will then be sensibly equal to the probability of its being
comprised between [alpha] + [epsilon] and [alpha] + 2[epsilon],
_provided_ [epsilon] _be very small_. This is a property common to all
analytic functions. Minute variations of the function are proportional
to minute variations of the variable.

But we have assumed that an exceedingly slight variation of the push
suffices to change the color of the sector over which the needle finally
stops. From [alpha] to [alpha]+[epsilon] it is red, from
[alpha]+[epsilon] to [alpha]+2[epsilon] it is black; the probability of
each red sector is therefore the same as of the following black, and
consequently the total probability of red equals the total probability
of black.

The datum of the question is the analytic function representing the
probability of a particular initial push. But the theorem remains true
whatever be this datum, since it depends upon a property common to all
analytic functions. From this it follows finally that we no longer need
the datum.

What we have just said for the case of the roulette applies also to the
example of the minor planets. The zodiac may be regarded as an immense
roulette on which have been tossed many little balls with different
initial impulses varying according to some law. Their present
distribution is uniform and independent of this law, for the same reason
as in the preceding case. Thus we see why phenomena obey the laws of
chance when slight differences in the causes suffice to bring on great
differences in the effects. The probabilities of these slight
differences may then be regarded as proportional to these differences
themselves, just because these differences are minute, and the
infinitesimal increments of a continuous function are proportional to
those of the variable.

Take an entirely different example, where intervenes especially the
complexity of the causes. Suppose a player shuffles a pack of cards. At
each shuffle he changes the order of the cards, and he may change them
in many ways. To simplify the exposition, consider only three cards. The
cards which before the shuffle occupied respectively the places 123, may
after the shuffle occupy the places

  123, 231, 312, 321, 132, 213.

Each of these six hypotheses is possible and they have respectively for
probabilities:

  p_1, p_2, p_3, p_4, p_5, p_6.

The sum of these six numbers equals 1; but this is all we know of them;
these six probabilities depend naturally upon the habits of the player
which we do not know.

At the second shuffle and the following, this will recommence, and under
the same conditions; I mean that p_4 for example represents always the
probability that the three cards which occupied after the _n_th shuffle
and before the _n_ + 1th the places 123, occupy the places 321 after the
_n_ + 1th shuffle. And this remains true whatever be the number _n_,
since the habits of the player and his way of shuffling remain the same.

But if the number of shuffles is very great, the cards which before the
first shuffle occupied the places 123 may, after the last shuffle,
occupy the places

  123, 231, 312, 321, 132, 213

and the probability of these six hypotheses will be sensibly the same
and equal to 1/6; and this will be true whatever be the numbers
p_1 ... p_6 which we do not know. The great number of shuffles, that
is to say the complexity of the causes, has produced uniformity.

This would apply without change if there were more than three cards,
but even with three cards the demonstration would be complicated;
let it suffice to give it for only two cards. Then we have only two
possibilities 12, 21 with the probabilities p_1 and p_2 = 1 - p_1.

Suppose _n_ shuffles and suppose I win one franc if the cards are
finally in the initial order and lose one if they are finally inverted.
Then, my mathematical expectation will be (p_1 - p_2)^{_n_}.

The difference p_1 - p_2 is certainly less than 1; so that if _n_ is
very great my expectation will be zero; we need not learn p_1 and p_2
to be aware that the game is equitable.

There would always be an exception if one of the numbers p_1 and p_2
was equal to 1 and the other naught. _Then it would not apply because
our initial hypotheses would be too simple._

What we have just seen applies not only to the mixing of cards, but to
all mixings, to those of powders and of liquids; and even to those of
the molecules of gases in the kinetic theory of gases.

To return to this theory, suppose for a moment a gas whose molecules can
not mutually clash, but may be deviated by hitting the insides of the
vase wherein the gas is confined. If the form of the vase is
sufficiently complex the distribution of the molecules and that of the
velocities will not be long in becoming uniform. But this will not be so
if the vase is spherical or if it has the shape of a cuboid. Why?
Because in the first case the distance from the center to any trajectory
will remain constant; in the second case this will be the absolute value
of the angle of each trajectory with the faces of the cuboid.

So we see what should be understood by conditions _too simple_; they are
those which conserve something, which leave an invariant remaining. Are
the differential equations of the problem too simple for us to apply the
laws of chance? This question would seem at first view to lack precise
meaning; now we know what it means. They are too simple if they conserve
something, if they admit a uniform integral. If something in the initial
conditions remains unchanged, it is clear the final situation can no
longer be independent of the initial situation.

We come finally to the theory of errors. We know not to what are due the
accidental errors, and precisely because we do not know, we are aware
they obey the law of Gauss. Such is the paradox. The explanation is
nearly the same as in the preceding cases. We need know only one thing:
that the errors are very numerous, that they are very slight, that each
may be as well negative as positive. What is the curve of probability of
each of them? We do not know; we only suppose it is symmetric. We prove
then that the resultant error will follow Gauss's law, and this
resulting law is independent of the particular laws which we do not
know. Here again the simplicity of the result is born of the very
complexity of the data.


VII

But we are not through with paradoxes. I have just recalled the figment
of Flammarion, that of the man going quicker than light, for whom time
changes sign. I said that for him all phenomena would seem due to
chance. That is true from a certain point of view, and yet all these
phenomena at a given moment would not be distributed in conformity with
the laws of chance, since the distribution would be the same as for us,
who, seeing them unfold harmoniously and without coming out of a primal
chaos, do not regard them as ruled by chance.

What does that mean? For Lumen, Flammarion's man, slight causes seem to
produce great effects; why do not things go on as for us when we think
we see grand effects due to little causes? Would not the same reasoning
be applicable in his case?

Let us return to the argument. When slight differences in the causes
produce vast differences in the effects, why are these effects
distributed according to the laws of chance? Suppose a difference of a
millimeter in the cause produces a difference of a kilometer in the
effect. If I win in case the effect corresponds to a kilometer bearing
an even number, my probability of winning will be 1/2. Why? Because to
make that, the cause must correspond to a millimeter with an even
number. Now, according to all appearance, the probability of the cause
varying between certain limits will be proportional to the distance
apart of these limits, provided this distance be very small. If this
hypothesis were not admitted there would no longer be any way of
representing the probability by a continuous function.

What now will happen when great causes produce small effects? This is
the case where we should not attribute the phenomenon to chance and
where on the contrary Lumen would attribute it to chance. To a
difference of a kilometer in the cause would correspond a difference of
a millimeter in the effect. Would the probability of the cause being
comprised between two limits _n_ kilometers apart still be proportional
to _n_? We have no reason to suppose so, since this distance, _n_
kilometers, is great. But the probability that the effect lies between
two limits _n_ millimeters apart will be precisely the same, so it will
not be proportional to _n_, even though this distance, _n_ millimeters,
be small. There is no way therefore of representing the law of
probability of effects by a continuous curve. This curve, understand,
may remain continuous in the _analytic_ sense of the word; to
_infinitesimal_ variations of the abscissa will correspond infinitesimal
variations of the ordinate. But _practically_ it will not be continuous,
since _very small_ variations of the ordinate would not correspond to
very small variations of the abscissa. It would become impossible to
trace the curve with an ordinary pencil; that is what I mean.

So what must we conclude? Lumen has no right to say that the
probability of the cause (_his_ cause, our effect) should be represented
necessarily by a continuous function. But then why have we this right?
It is because this state of unstable equilibrium which we have been
calling initial is itself only the final outcome of a long previous
history. In the course of this history complex causes have worked a
great while: they have contributed to produce the mixture of elements
and they have tended to make everything uniform at least within a small
region; they have rounded off the corners, smoothed down the hills and
filled up the valleys. However capricious and irregular may have been
the primitive curve given over to them, they have worked so much toward
making it regular that finally they deliver over to us a continuous
curve. And this is why we may in all confidence assume its continuity.

Lumen would not have the same reasons for such a conclusion. For him
complex causes would not seem agents of equalization and regularity, but
on the contrary would create only inequality and differentiation. He
would see a world more and more varied come forth from a sort of
primitive chaos. The changes he could observe would be for him
unforeseen and impossible to foresee. They would seem to him due to some
caprice or another; but this caprice would be quite different from our
chance, since it would be opposed to all law, while our chance still has
its laws. All these points call for lengthy explications, which perhaps
would aid in the better comprehension of the irreversibility of the
universe.


VIII

We have sought to define chance, and now it is proper to put a question.
Has chance thus defined, in so far as this is possible, objectivity?

It may be questioned. I have spoken of very slight or very complex
causes. But what is very little for one may be very big for another, and
what seems very complex to one may seem simple to another. In part I
have already answered by saying precisely in what cases differential
equations become too simple for the laws of chance to remain applicable.
But it is fitting to examine the matter a little more closely, because
we may take still other points of view.

What means the phrase 'very slight'? To understand it we need only go
back to what has already been said. A difference is very slight, an
interval is very small, when within the limits of this interval the
probability remains sensibly constant. And why may this probability be
regarded as constant within a small interval? It is because we assume
that the law of probability is represented by a continuous curve,
continuous not only in the analytic sense, but _practically_ continuous,
as already explained. This means that it not only presents no absolute
hiatus, but that it has neither salients nor reentrants too acute or too
accentuated.

And what gives us the right to make this hypothesis? We have already
said it is because, since the beginning of the ages, there have always
been complex causes ceaselessly acting in the same way and making the
world tend toward uniformity without ever being able to turn back. These
are the causes which little by little have flattened the salients and
filled up the reentrants, and this is why our probability curves now
show only gentle undulations. In milliards of milliards of ages another
step will have been made toward uniformity, and these undulations will
be ten times as gentle; the radius of mean curvature of our curve will
have become ten times as great. And then such a length as seems to us
to-day not very small, since on our curve an arc of this length can not
be regarded as rectilineal, should on the contrary at that epoch be
called very little, since the curvature will have become ten times less
and an arc of this length may be sensibly identified with a sect.

Thus the phrase 'very slight' remains relative; but it is not relative
to such or such a man, it is relative to the actual state of the world.
It will change its meaning when the world shall have become more
uniform, when all things shall have blended still more. But then
doubtless men can no longer live and must give place to other
beings--should I say far smaller or far larger? So that our criterion,
remaining true for all men, retains an objective sense.

And on the other hand what means the phrase 'very complex'? I have
already given one solution, but there are others. Complex causes we have
said produce a blend more and more intimate, but after how long a time
will this blend satisfy us? When will it have accumulated sufficient
complexity? When shall we have sufficiently shuffled the cards? If we
mix two powders, one blue, the other white, there comes a moment when
the tint of the mixture seems to us uniform because of the feebleness of
our senses; it will be uniform for the presbyte, forced to gaze from
afar, before it will be so for the myope. And when it has become uniform
for all eyes, we still could push back the limit by the use of
instruments. There is no chance for any man ever to discern the infinite
variety which, if the kinetic theory is true, hides under the uniform
appearance of a gas. And yet if we accept Gouy's ideas on the Brownian
movement, does not the microscope seem on the point of showing us
something analogous?

This new criterion is therefore relative like the first; and if it
retains an objective character, it is because all men have approximately
the same senses, the power of their instruments is limited, and besides
they use them only exceptionally.


IX

It is just the same in the moral sciences and particularly in history.
The historian is obliged to make a choice among the events of the epoch
he studies; he recounts only those which seem to him the most important.
He therefore contents himself with relating the most momentous events of
the sixteenth century, for example, as likewise the most remarkable
facts of the seventeenth century. If the first suffice to explain the
second, we say these conform to the laws of history. But if a great
event of the seventeenth century should have for cause a small fact of
the sixteenth century which no history reports, which all the world has
neglected, then we say this event is due to chance. This word has
therefore the same sense as in the physical sciences; it means that
slight causes have produced great effects.

The greatest bit of chance is the birth of a great man. It is only by
chance that meeting of two germinal cells, of different sex, containing
precisely, each on its side, the mysterious elements whose mutual
reaction must produce the genius. One will agree that these elements
must be rare and that their meeting is still more rare. How slight a
thing it would have required to deflect from its route the carrying
spermatozoon. It would have sufficed to deflect it a tenth of a
millimeter and Napoleon would not have been born and the destinies of a
continent would have been changed. No example can better make us
understand the veritable characteristics of chance.

One more word about the paradoxes brought out by the application of the
calculus of probabilities to the moral sciences. It has been proven that
no Chamber of Deputies will ever fail to contain a member of the
opposition, or at least such an event would be so improbable that we
might without fear wager the contrary, and bet a million against a sou.

Condorcet has striven to calculate how many jurors it would require to
make a judicial error practically impossible. If we had used the results
of this calculation, we should certainly have been exposed to the same
disappointments as in betting, on the faith of the calculus, that the
opposition would never be without a representative.

The laws of chance do not apply to these questions. If justice be not
always meted out to accord with the best reasons, it uses less than we
think the method of Bridoye. This is perhaps to be regretted, for then
the system of Condorcet would shield us from judicial errors.

What is the meaning of this? We are tempted to attribute facts of this
nature to chance because their causes are obscure; but this is not true
chance. The causes are unknown to us, it is true, and they are even
complex; but they are not sufficiently so, since they conserve
something. We have seen that this it is which distinguishes causes 'too
simple.' When men are brought together they no longer decide at random
and independently one of another; they influence one another. Multiplex
causes come into action. They worry men, dragging them to right or left,
but one thing there is they can not destroy, this is their Panurge
flock-of-sheep habits. And this is an invariant.


X

Difficulties are indeed involved in the application of the calculus of
probabilities to the exact sciences. Why are the decimals of a table of
logarithms, why are those of the number [pi] distributed in accordance
with the laws of chance? Elsewhere I have already studied the question
in so far as it concerns logarithms, and there it is easy. It is clear
that a slight difference of argument will give a slight difference of
logarithm, but a great difference in the sixth decimal of the logarithm.
Always we find again the same criterion.

But as for the number [pi], that presents more difficulties, and I have
at the moment nothing worth while to say.

There would be many other questions to resolve, had I wished to attack
them before solving that which I more specially set myself. When we
reach a simple result, when we find for example a round number, we say
that such a result can not be due to chance, and we seek, for its
explanation, a non-fortuitous cause. And in fact there is only a very
slight probability that among 10,000 numbers chance will give a round
number; for example, the number 10,000. This has only one chance in
10,000. But there is only one chance in 10,000 for the occurrence of any
other one number; and yet this result will not astonish us, nor will it
be hard for us to attribute it to chance; and that simply because it
will be less striking.

Is this a simple illusion of ours, or are there cases where this way of
thinking is legitimate? We must hope so, else were all science
impossible. When we wish to check a hypothesis, what do we do? We can
not verify all its consequences, since they would be infinite in number;
we content ourselves with verifying certain ones and if we succeed we
declare the hypothesis confirmed, because so much success could not be
due to chance. And this is always at bottom the same reasoning.

I can not completely justify it here, since it would take too much time;
but I may at least say that we find ourselves confronted by two
hypotheses, either a simple cause or that aggregate of complex causes we
call chance. We find it natural to suppose that the first should produce
a simple result, and then, if we find that simple result, the round
number for example, it seems more likely to us to be attributable to the
simple cause which must give it almost certainly, than to chance which
could only give it once in 10,000 times. It will not be the same if we
find a result which is not simple; chance, it is true, will not give
this more than once in 10,000 times; but neither has the simple cause
any more chance of producing it.



BOOK II


MATHEMATICAL REASONING



CHAPTER I

THE RELATIVITY OF SPACE


I

It is impossible to represent to oneself empty space; all our efforts to
imagine a pure space, whence should be excluded the changing images of
material objects, can result only in a representation where vividly
colored surfaces, for example, are replaced by lines of faint
coloration, and we can not go to the very end in this way without all
vanishing and terminating in nothingness. Thence comes the irreducible
relativity of space.

Whoever speaks of absolute space uses a meaningless phrase. This is a
truth long proclaimed by all who have reflected upon the matter, but
which we are too often led to forget.

I am at a determinate point in Paris, place du Panthéon for instance,
and I say: I shall come back _here_ to-morrow. If I be asked: Do you
mean you will return to the same point of space, I shall be tempted to
answer: yes; and yet I shall be wrong, since by to-morrow the earth will
have journeyed hence, carrying with it the place du Panthéon, which will
have traveled over more than two million kilometers. And if I tried to
speak more precisely, I should gain nothing, since our globe has run
over these two million kilometers in its motion with relation to the
sun, while the sun in its turn is displaced with reference to the Milky
Way, while the Milky Way itself is doubtless in motion without our being
able to perceive its velocity. So that we are completely ignorant, and
always shall be, of how much the place du Panthéon is displaced in a
day.

In sum, I meant to say: To-morrow I shall see again the dome and the
pediment of the Panthéon, and if there were no Panthéon my phrase would
be meaningless and space would vanish.

This is one of the most commonplace forms of the principle of the
relativity of space; but there is another, upon which Delbeuf has
particularly insisted. Suppose that in the night all the dimensions of
the universe become a thousand times greater: the world will have
remained _similar_ to itself, giving to the word _similitude_ the same
meaning as in Euclid, Book VI. Only what was a meter long will measure
thenceforth a kilometer, what was a millimeter long will become a meter.
The bed whereon I lie and my body itself will be enlarged in the same
proportion.

When I awake to-morrow morning, what sensation shall I feel in presence
of such an astounding transformation? Well, I shall perceive nothing at
all. The most precise measurements will be incapable of revealing to me
anything of this immense convulsion, since the measures I use will have
varied precisely in the same proportion as the objects I seek to
measure. In reality, this convulsion exists only for those who reason as
if space were absolute. If I for a moment have reasoned as they do, it
is the better to bring out that their way of seeing implies
contradiction. In fact it would be better to say that, space being
relative, nothing at all has happened, which is why we have perceived
nothing.

Has one the right, therefore, to say he knows the distance between two
points? No, since this distance could undergo enormous variations
without our being able to perceive them, provided the other distances
have varied in the same proportion. We have just seen that when I say: I
shall be here to-morrow, this does not mean: To-morrow I shall be at the
same point of space where I am to-day, but rather: To-morrow I shall be
at the same distance from the Panthéon as to-day. And we see that this
statement is no longer sufficient and that I should say: To-morrow and
to-day my distance from the Panthéon will be equal to the same number of
times the height of my body.

But this is not all; I have supposed the dimensions of the world to
vary, but that at least the world remained always similar to itself. We
might go much further, and one of the most astonishing theories of
modern physics furnishes us the occasion.

According to Lorentz and Fitzgerald, all the bodies borne along in the
motion of the earth undergo a deformation.

This deformation is, in reality, very slight, since all dimensions
parallel to the movement of the earth diminish by a hundred millionth,
while the dimensions perpendicular to this movement are unchanged. But
it matters little that it is slight, that it exists suffices for the
conclusion I am about to draw. And besides, I have said it was slight,
but in reality I know nothing about it; I have myself been victim of the
tenacious illusion which makes us believe we conceive an absolute space;
I have thought of the motion of the earth in its elliptic orbit around
the sun, and I have allowed thirty kilometers as its velocity. But its
real velocity (I mean, this time, not its absolute velocity, which is
meaningless, but its velocity with relation to the ether), I do not know
that, and have no means of knowing it: it is perhaps, 10, 100 times
greater, and then the deformation will be 100, 10,000 times more.

Can we show this deformation? Evidently not; here is a cube with edge
one meter; in consequence of the earth's displacement it is deformed,
one of its edges, that parallel to the motion, becomes smaller, the
others do not change. If I wish to assure myself of it by aid of a meter
measure, I shall measure first one of the edges perpendicular to the
motion and shall find that my standard meter fits this edge exactly; and
in fact neither of these two lengths is changed, since both are
perpendicular to the motion. Then I wish to measure the other edge, that
parallel to the motion; to do this I displace my meter and turn it so as
to apply it to the edge. But the meter, having changed orientation and
become parallel to the motion, has undergone, in its turn, the
deformation, so that though the edge be not a meter long, it will fit
exactly, I shall find out nothing.

You ask then of what use is the hypothesis of Lorentz and of Fitzgerald
if no experiment can permit of its verification? It is my exposition
that has been incomplete; I have spoken only of measurements that can be
made with a meter; but we can also measure a length by the time it takes
light to traverse it, on condition we suppose the velocity of light
constant and independent of direction. Lorentz could have accounted for
the facts by supposing the velocity of light greater in the direction
of the earth's motion than in the perpendicular direction. He preferred
to suppose that the velocity is the same in these different directions
but that the bodies are smaller in the one than in the other. If the
wave surfaces of light had undergone the same deformations as the
material bodies we should never have perceived the Lorentz-Fitzgerald
deformation.

In either case, it is not a question of absolute magnitude, but of the
measure of this magnitude by means of some instrument; this instrument
may be a meter, or the path traversed by light; it is only the relation
of the magnitude to the instrument that we measure; and if this relation
is altered, we have no way of knowing whether it is the magnitude or the
instrument which has changed.

But what I wish to bring out is, that in this deformation the world has
not remained similar to itself; squares have become rectangles, circles
ellipses, spheres ellipsoids. And yet we have no way of knowing whether
this deformation be real.

Evidently one could go much further: in place of the Lorentz-Fitzgerald
deformation, whose laws are particularly simple, we could imagine any
deformation whatsoever. Bodies could be deformed according to any laws,
as complicated as we might wish, we never should notice it provided all
bodies without exception were deformed according to the same laws. In
saying, all bodies without exception, I include of course our own body
and the light rays emanating from different objects.

If we look at the world in one of those mirrors of complicated shape
which deform objects in a bizarre way, the mutual relations of the
different parts of this world would not be altered; if, in fact two real
objects touch, their images likewise seem to touch. Of course when we
look in such a mirror we see indeed the deformation, but this is because
the real world subsists alongside of its deformed image; and then even
were this real world hidden from us, something there is could not be
hidden, ourself; we could not cease to see, or at least to feel, our
body and our limbs which have not been deformed and which continue to
serve us as instruments of measure.

But if we imagine our body itself deformed in the same way as if seen
in the mirror, these instruments of measure in their turn will fail us
and the deformation will no longer be ascertainable.

Consider in the same way two worlds images of one another; to each
object _P_ of the world _A_ corresponds in the world _B_ an object _P'_,
its image; the coordinates of this image _P'_ are determinate functions
of those of the object _P_; moreover these functions may be any
whatsoever; I only suppose them chosen once for all. Between the
position of _P_ and that of _P'_ there is a constant relation; what this
relation is, matters not; enough that it be constant.

Well, these two worlds will be indistinguishable one from the other. I
mean the first will be for its inhabitants what the second is for its.
And so it will be as long as the two worlds remain strangers to each
other. Suppose we lived in world _A_, we shall have constructed our
science and in particular our geometry; during this time the inhabitants
of world _B_ will have constructed a science, and as their world is the
image of ours, their geometry will also be the image of ours or, better,
it will be the same. But if for us some day a window is opened upon
world _B_, how we shall pity them: "Poor things," we shall say, "they
think they have made a geometry, but what they call so is only a
grotesque image of ours; their straights are all twisted, their circles
are humped, their spheres have capricious inequalities." And we shall
never suspect they say the same of us, and one never will know who is
right.

We see in how broad a sense should be understood the relativity of
space; space is in reality amorphous and the things which are therein
alone give it a form. What then should be thought of that direct
intuition we should have of the straight or of distance? So little have
we intuition of distance in itself that in the night, as we have said, a
distance might become a thousand times greater without our being able to
perceive it, if all other distances had undergone the same alteration.
And even in a night the world _B_ might be substituted for the world _A_
without our having any way of knowing it, and then the straight lines of
yesterday would have ceased to be straight and we should never notice.

One part of space is not by itself and in the absolute sense of the word
equal to another part of space; because if so it is for us, it would not
be for the dwellers in world _B_; and these have just as much right to
reject our opinion as we to condemn theirs.

I have elsewhere shown what are the consequences of these facts from the
viewpoint of the idea we should form of non-Euclidean geometry and other
analogous geometries; to that I do not care to return; and to-day I
shall take a somewhat different point of view.


II

If this intuition of distance, of direction, of the straight line, if
this direct intuition of space in a word does not exist, whence comes
our belief that we have it? If this is only an illusion, why is this
illusion so tenacious? It is proper to examine into this. We have said
there is no direct intuition of size and we can only arrive at the
relation of this magnitude to our instruments of measure. We should
therefore not have been able to construct space if we had not had an
instrument to measure it; well, this instrument to which we relate
everything, which we use instinctively, it is our own body. It is in
relation to our body that we place exterior objects, and the only
spatial relations of these objects that we can represent are their
relations to our body. It is our body which serves us, so to speak, as
system of axes of coordinates.

For example, at an instant [alpha], the presence of the object _A_ is
revealed to me by the sense of sight; at another instant, [beta], the
presence of another object, _B_, is revealed to me by another sense,
that of hearing or of touch, for instance. I judge that this object _B_
occupies the same place as the object _A_. What does that mean? First
that does not signify that these two objects occupy, at two different
moments, the same point of an absolute space, which even if it existed
would escape our cognition, since, between the instants [alpha] and
[beta], the solar system has moved and we can not know its displacement.
That means these two objects occupy the same relative position with
reference to our body.

But even this, what does it mean? The impressions that have come to us
from these objects have followed paths absolutely different, the optic
nerve for the object _A_, the acoustic nerve for the object _B_.
They have nothing in common from the qualitative point of view. The
representations we are able to make of these two objects are absolutely
heterogeneous, irreducible one to the other. Only I know that to reach
the object _A_ I have just to extend the right arm in a certain way;
even when I abstain from doing it, I represent to myself the muscular
sensations and other analogous sensations which would accompany this
extension, and this representation is associated with that of the
object _A_.

Now, I likewise know I can reach the object _B_ by extending my right
arm in the same manner, an extension accompanied by the same train of
muscular sensations. And when I say these two objects occupy the same
place, I mean nothing more.

I also know I could have reached the object _A_ by another appropriate
motion of the left arm and I represent to myself the muscular sensations
which would have accompanied this movement; and by this same motion of
the left arm, accompanied by the same sensations, I likewise could have
reached the object _B_.

And that is very important, since thus I can defend myself against
dangers menacing me from the object _A_ or the object _B_. With each of
the blows we can be hit, nature has associated one or more parries which
permit of our guarding ourselves. The same parry may respond to several
strokes; and so it is, for instance, that the same motion of the right
arm would have allowed us to guard at the instant [alpha] against the
object _A_ and at the instant [beta] against the object _B_. Just so,
the same stroke can be parried in several ways, and we have said, for
instance, the object _A_ could be reached indifferently either by a
certain movement of the right arm or by a certain movement of the left
arm.

All these parries have nothing in common except warding off the same
blow, and this it is, and nothing else, which is meant when we say they
are movements terminating at the same point of space. Just so, these
objects, of which we say they occupy the same point of space, have
nothing in common, except that the same parry guards against them.

Or, if you choose, imagine innumerable telegraph wires, some
centripetal, others centrifugal. The centripetal wires warn us of
accidents happening without; the centrifugal wires carry the reparation.
Connections are so established that when a centripetal wire is traversed
by a current this acts on a relay and so starts a current in one of the
centrifugal wires, and things are so arranged that several centripetal
wires may act on the same centrifugal wire if the same remedy suits
several ills, and that a centripetal wire may agitate different
centrifugal wires, either simultaneously or in lieu one of the other
when the same ill may be cured by several remedies.

It is this complex system of associations, it is this table of
distribution, so to speak, which is all our geometry or, if you wish,
all in our geometry that is instinctive. What we call our intuition of
the straight line or of distance is the consciousness we have of these
associations and of their imperious character.

And it is easy to understand whence comes this imperious character
itself. An association will seem to us by so much the more
indestructible as it is more ancient. But these associations are not,
for the most part, conquests of the individual, since their trace is
seen in the new-born babe: they are conquests of the race. Natural
selection had to bring about these conquests by so much the more quickly
as they were the more necessary.

On this account, those of which we speak must have been of the earliest
in date, since without them the defense of the organism would have been
impossible. From the time when the cellules were no longer merely
juxtaposed, but were called upon to give mutual aid, it was needful that
a mechanism organize analogous to what we have described, so that this
aid miss not its way, but forestall the peril.

When a frog is decapitated, and a drop of acid is placed on a point of
its skin, it seeks to wipe off the acid with the nearest foot, and, if
this foot be amputated, it sweeps it off with the foot of the opposite
side. There we have the double parry of which I have just spoken,
allowing the combating of an ill by a second remedy, if the first fails.
And it is this multiplicity of parries, and the resulting coordination,
which is space.

We see to what depths of the unconscious we must descend to find the
first traces of these spatial associations, since only the inferior
parts of the nervous system are involved. Why be astonished then at the
resistance we oppose to every attempt made to dissociate what so long
has been associated? Now, it is just this resistance that we call the
evidence for the geometric truths; this evidence is nothing but the
repugnance we feel toward breaking with very old habits which have
always proved good.


III

The space so created is only a little space extending no farther than my
arm can reach; the intervention of the memory is necessary to push back
its limits. There are points which will remain out of my reach, whatever
effort I make to stretch forth my hand; if I were fastened to the ground
like a hydra polyp, for instance, which can only extend its tentacles,
all these points would be outside of space, since the sensations we
could experience from the action of bodies there situated, would be
associated with the idea of no movement allowing us to reach them, of no
appropriate parry. These sensations would not seem to us to have any
spatial character and we should not seek to localize them.

But we are not fixed to the ground like the lower animals; we can, if
the enemy be too far away, advance toward him first and extend the hand
when we are sufficiently near. This is still a parry, but a parry at
long range. On the other hand, it is a complex parry, and into the
representation we make of it enter the representation of the muscular
sensations caused by the movements of the legs, that of the muscular
sensations caused by the final movement of the arm, that of the
sensations of the semicircular canals, etc. We must, besides, represent
to ourselves, not a complex of simultaneous sensations, but a complex of
successive sensations, following each other in a determinate order, and
this is why I have just said the intervention of memory was necessary.
Notice moreover that, to reach the same point, I may approach nearer the
mark to be attained, so as to have to stretch my arm less. What more? It
is not one, it is a thousand parries I can oppose to the same danger.
All these parries are made of sensations which may have nothing in
common and yet we regard them as defining the same point of space, since
they may respond to the same danger and are all associated with the
notion of this danger. It is the potentiality of warding off the same
stroke which makes the unity of these different parries, as it is the
possibility of being parried in the same way which makes the unity of
the strokes so different in kind, which may menace us from the same
point of space. It is this double unity which makes the individuality of
each point of space, and, in the notion of point, there is nothing else.

The space before considered, which might be called _restricted space_,
was referred to coordinate axes bound to my body; these axes were fixed,
since my body did not move and only my members were displaced. What are
the axes to which we naturally refer the _extended space_? that is to
say the new space just defined. We define a point by the sequence of
movements to be made to reach it, starting from a certain initial
position of the body. The axes are therefore fixed to this initial
position of the body.

But the position I call initial may be arbitrarily chosen among all the
positions my body has successively occupied; if the memory more or less
unconscious of these successive positions is necessary for the genesis
of the notion of space, this memory may go back more or less far into
the past. Thence results in the definition itself of space a certain
indetermination, and it is precisely this indetermination which
constitutes its relativity.

There is no absolute space, there is only space relative to a certain
initial position of the body. For a conscious being fixed to the ground
like the lower animals, and consequently knowing only restricted space,
space would still be relative (since it would have reference to his
body), but this being would not be conscious of this relativity, because
the axes of reference for this restricted space would be unchanging!
Doubtless the rock to which this being would be fettered would not be
motionless, since it would be carried along in the movement of our
planet; for us consequently these axes would change at each instant; but
for him they would be changeless. We have the faculty of referring our
extended space now to the position _A_ of our body, considered as
initial, again to the position _B_, which it had some moments afterward,
and which we are free to regard in its turn as initial; we make
therefore at each instant unconscious transformations of coordinates.
This faculty would be lacking in our imaginary being, and from not
having traveled, he would think space absolute. At every instant, his
system of axes would be imposed upon him; this system would have to
change greatly in reality, but for him it would be always the same,
since it would be always the _only_ system. Quite otherwise is it with
us, who at each instant have many systems between which we may choose at
will, on condition of going back by memory more or less far into the
past.

This is not all; restricted space would not be homogeneous; the
different points of this space could not be regarded as equivalent,
since some could be reached only at the cost of the greatest efforts,
while others could be easily attained. On the contrary, our extended
space seems to us homogeneous, and we say all its points are equivalent.
What does that mean?

If we start from a certain place _A_, we can, from this position, make
certain movements, _M_, characterized by a certain complex of muscular
sensations. But, starting from another position, _B_, we make movements
_M'_ characterized by the same muscular sensations. Let _a_, then, be
the situation of a certain point of the body, the end of the index
finger of the right hand for example, in the initial position _A_, and
_b_ the situation of this same index when, starting from this position
_A_, we have made the motions _M_. Afterwards, let _a'_ be the situation
of this index in the position _B_, and _b'_ its situation when, starting
from the position _B_, we have made the motions _M'_.

Well, I am accustomed to say that the points of space _a_ and _b_ are
related to each other just as the points _a'_ and _b'_, and this simply
means that the two series of movements _M_ and _M'_ are accompanied by
the same muscular sensations. And as I am conscious that, in passing
from the position _A_ to the position _B_, my body has remained capable
of the same movements, I know there is a point of space related to the
point _a'_ just as any point _b_ is to the point _a_, so that the two
points _a_ and _a'_ are equivalent. This is what is called the
homogeneity of space. And, at the same time, this is why space is
relative, since its properties remain the same whether it be referred to
the axes _A_ or to the axes _B_. So that the relativity of space and its
homogeneity are one sole and same thing.

Now, if I wish to pass to the great space, which no longer serves only
for me, but where I may lodge the universe, I get there by an act of
imagination. I imagine how a giant would feel who could reach the
planets in a few steps; or, if you choose, what I myself should feel in
presence of a miniature world where these planets were replaced by
little balls, while on one of these little balls moved a liliputian I
should call myself. But this act of imagination would be impossible for
me had I not previously constructed my restricted space and my extended
space for my own use.


IV

Why now have all these spaces three dimensions? Go back to the "table of
distribution" of which we have spoken. We have on the one side the list
of the different possible dangers; designate them by _A1_, _A2_, etc.;
and, on the other side, the list of the different remedies which I shall
call in the same way _B1_, _B2_, etc. We have then connections between
the contact studs or push buttons of the first list and those of the
second, so that when, for instance, the announcer of danger _A3_
functions, it will put or may put in action the relay corresponding to
the parry _B4_.

As I have spoken above of centripetal or centrifugal wires, I fear lest
one see in all this, not a simple comparison, but a description of the
nervous system. Such is not my thought, and that for several reasons:
first I should not permit myself to put forth an opinion on the
structure of the nervous system which I do not know, while those who
have studied it speak only circumspectly; again because, despite my
incompetence, I well know this scheme would be too simplistic; and
finally because on my list of parries, some would figure very complex,
which might even, in the case of extended space, as we have seen above,
consist of many steps followed by a movement of the arm. It is not a
question then of physical connection between two real conductors but of
psychologic association between two series of sensations.

If _A1_ and _A2_ for instance are both associated with the parry _B1_,
and if _A1_ is likewise associated with the parry _B2_, it will
generally happen that _A2_ and _B2_ will also themselves be associated.
If this fundamental law were not generally true, there would exist only
an immense confusion and there would be nothing resembling a conception
of space or a geometry. How in fact have we defined a point of space. We
have done it in two ways: it is on the one hand the aggregate of
announcers _A_ in connection with the same parry _B_; it is on the other
hand the aggregate of parries _B_ in connection with the same announcer
_A_. If our law was not true, we should say _A1_ and _A2_ correspond to
the same point since they are both in connection with _B1_; but we
should likewise say they do not correspond to the same point, since _A1_
would be in connection with _B2_ and the same would not be true of _A2_.
This would be a contradiction.

But, from another side, if the law were rigorously and always true,
space would be very different from what it is. We should have categories
strongly contrasted between which would be portioned out on the one hand
the announcers _A_, on the other hand the parries _B_; these categories
would be excessively numerous, but they would be entirely separated one
from another. Space would be composed of points very numerous, but
discrete; it would be _discontinuous_. There would be no reason for
ranging these points in one order rather than another, nor consequently
for attributing to space three dimensions.

But it is not so; permit me to resume for a moment the language of those
who already know geometry; this is quite proper since this is the
language best understood by those I wish to make understand me.

When I desire to parry the stroke, I seek to attain the point whence
comes this blow, but it suffices that I approach quite near. Then the
parry _B1_ may answer for _A1_ and for _A2_, if the point which
corresponds to _B1_ is sufficiently near both to that corresponding to
_A1_ and to that corresponding to _A2_. But it may happen that the point
corresponding to another parry _B2_ may be sufficiently near to the
point corresponding to A1 and not sufficiently near the point
corresponding to _A2_; so that the parry _B2_ may answer for _A1_
without answering for _A2_. For one who does not yet know geometry, this
translates itself simply by a derogation of the law stated above. And
then things will happen thus:

Two parries _B1_ and _B2_ will be associated with the same warning _A1_
and with a large number of warnings which we shall range in the same
category as _A1_ and which we shall make correspond to the same point of
space. But we may find warnings _A2_ which will be associated with _B2_
without being associated with _B1_, and which in compensation will be
associated with _B3_, which _B3_ was not associated with _A1_, and so
forth, so that we may write the series

  _B1_, _A1_, _B2_, _A2_, _B3_, _A3_, _B4_, _A4_,

where each term is associated with the following and the preceding, but
not with the terms several places away.

Needless to add that each of the terms of these series is not isolated,
but forms part of a very numerous category of other warnings or of other
parries which have the same connections as it, and which may be regarded
as belonging to the same point of space.

The fundamental law, though admitting of exceptions, remains therefore
almost always true. Only, in consequence of these exceptions, these
categories, in place of being entirely separated, encroach partially one
upon another and mutually penetrate in a certain measure, so that space
becomes continuous.

On the other hand, the order in which these categories are to be ranged
is no longer arbitrary, and if we refer to the preceding series, we see
it is necessary to put _B2_ between _A1_ and _A2_ and consequently
between _B1_ and _B3_ and that we could not for instance put it between
_B3_ and _B4_.

There is therefore an order in which are naturally arranged our
categories which correspond to the points of space, and experience
teaches us that this order presents itself under the form of a table
of triple entry, and this is why space has three dimensions.


V

So the characteristic property of space, that of having three
dimensions, is only a property of our table of distribution, an internal
property of the human intelligence, so to speak. It would suffice to
destroy certain of these connections, that is to say of the associations
of ideas to give a different table of distribution, and that might be
enough for space to acquire a fourth dimension.

Some persons will be astonished at such a result. The external world,
they will think, should count for something. If the number of dimensions
comes from the way we are made, there might be thinking beings living in
our world, but who might be made differently from us and who would
believe space has more or less than three dimensions. Has not M. de Cyon
said that the Japanese mice, having only two pair of semicircular
canals, believe that space is two-dimensional? And then this thinking
being, if he is capable of constructing a physics, would he not make a
physics of two or of four dimensions, and which in a sense would still
be the same as ours, since it would be the description of the same world
in another language?

It seems in fact that it would be possible to translate our physics into
the language of geometry of four dimensions; to attempt this translation
would be to take great pains for little profit, and I shall confine
myself to citing the mechanics of Hertz where we have something
analogous. However, it seems that the translation would always be less
simple than the text, and that it would always have the air of a
translation, that the language of three dimensions seems the better
fitted to the description of our world, although this description can be
rigorously made in another idiom. Besides, our table of distribution was
not made at random. There is connection between the warning _A1_ and the
parry _B1_, this is an internal property of our intelligence; but why
this connection? It is because the parry _B1_ affords means effectively
to guard against the danger _A1_; and this is a fact exterior to us,
this is a property of the exterior world. Our table of distribution is
therefore only the translation of an aggregate of exterior facts; if it
has three dimensions, this is because it has adapted itself to a world
having certain properties; and the chief of these properties is that
there exist natural solids whose displacements follow sensibly the laws
we call laws of motion of rigid solids. If therefore the language of
three dimensions is that which permits us most easily to describe our
world, we should not be astonished; this language is copied from our
table of distribution; and it is in order to be able to live in this
world that this table has been established.

I have said we could conceive, living in our world, thinking beings
whose table of distribution would be four-dimensional and who
consequently would think in hyperspace. It is not certain however that
such beings, admitting they were born there, could live there and defend
themselves against the thousand dangers by which they would there be
assailed.


VI

A few remarks to end with. There is a striking contrast between the
roughness of this primitive geometry, reducible to what I call a table
of distribution, and the infinite precision of the geometers' geometry.
And yet this is born of that; but not of that alone; it must be made
fecund by the faculty we have of constructing mathematical concepts,
such as that of group, for instance; it was needful to seek among the
pure concepts that which best adapts itself to this rough space whose
genesis I have sought to explain and which is common to us and the
higher animals.

The evidence for certain geometric postulates, we have said, is only our
repugnance to renouncing very old habits. But these postulates are
infinitely precise, while these habits have something about them
essentially pliant. When we wish to think, we need postulates infinitely
precise, since this is the only way to avoid contradiction; but among
all the possible systems of postulates, there are some we dislike to
choose because they are not sufficiently in accord with our habits;
however pliant, however elastic they may be, these have a limit of
elasticity.

We see that if geometry is not an experimental science, it is a science
born apropos of experience; that we have created the space it studies,
but adapting it to the world wherein we live. We have selected the most
convenient space, but experience has guided our choice; as this choice
has been unconscious, we think it has been imposed upon us; some say
experience imposes it, others that we are born with our space ready
made; we see from the preceding considerations, what in these two
opinions is the part of truth, what of error.

In this progressive education whose outcome has been the construction of
space, it is very difficult to determine what is the part of the
individual, what the part of the race. How far could one of us,
transported from birth to an entirely different world, where were
dominant, for instance, bodies moving in conformity to the laws of
motion of non-Euclidean solids, renounce the ancestral space to build a
space completely new?

The part of the race seems indeed preponderant; yet if to it we owe
rough space, the soft space I have spoken of, the space of the higher
animals, is it not to the unconscious experience of the individual we
owe the infinitely precise space of the geometer? This is a question not
easy to solve. Yet we cite a fact showing that the space our ancestors
have bequeathed us still retains a certain plasticity. Some hunters
learn to shoot fish under water, though the image of these fish be
turned up by refraction. Besides they do it instinctively: they
therefore have learned to modify their old instinct of direction; or, if
you choose, to substitute for the association _A1_, _B1_, another
association _A1_, _B2_, because experience showed them the first would
not work.



CHAPTER II

MATHEMATICAL DEFINITIONS AND TEACHING


1. I should speak here of general definitions in mathematics; at least
that is the title, but it will be impossible to confine myself to the
subject as strictly as the rule of unity of action would require; I
shall not be able to treat it without touching upon a few other related
questions, and if thus I am forced from time to time to walk on the
bordering flower-beds on the right or left, I pray you bear with me.

What is a good definition? For the philosopher or the scientist it is a
definition which applies to all the objects defined, and only those; it
is the one satisfying the rules of logic. But in teaching it is not
that; a good definition is one understood by the scholars.

How does it happen that so many refuse to understand mathematics? Is
that not something of a paradox? Lo and behold! a science appealing only
to the fundamental principles of logic, to the principle of
contradiction, for instance, to that which is the skeleton, so to speak,
of our intelligence, to that of which we can not divest ourselves
without ceasing to think, and there are people who find it obscure! and
they are even in the majority! That they are incapable of inventing may
pass, but that they do not understand the demonstrations shown them,
that they remain blind when we show them a light which seems to us
flashing pure flame, this it is which is altogether prodigious.

And yet there is no need of a wide experience with examinations to know
that these blind men are in no wise exceptional beings. This is a
problem not easy to solve, but which should engage the attention of all
those wishing to devote themselves to teaching.

What is it, to understand? Has this word the same meaning for all the
world? To understand the demonstration of a theorem, is that to examine
successively each of the syllogisms composing it and to ascertain its
correctness, its conformity to the rules of the game? Likewise, to
understand a definition, is this merely to recognize that one already
knows the meaning of all the terms employed and to ascertain that it
implies no contradiction?

For some, yes; when they have done this, they will say: I understand.

For the majority, no. Almost all are much more exacting; they wish to
know not merely whether all the syllogisms of a demonstration are
correct, but why they link together in this order rather than another.
In so far as to them they seem engendered by caprice and not by an
intelligence always conscious of the end to be attained, they do not
believe they understand.

Doubtless they are not themselves just conscious of what they crave and
they could not formulate their desire, but if they do not get
satisfaction, they vaguely feel that something is lacking. Then what
happens? In the beginning they still perceive the proofs one puts under
their eyes; but as these are connected only by too slender a thread to
those which precede and those which follow, they pass without leaving
any trace in their head; they are soon forgotten; a moment bright, they
quickly vanish in night eternal. When they are farther on, they will no
longer see even this ephemeral light, since the theorems lean one upon
another and those they would need are forgotten; thus it is they become
incapable of understanding mathematics.

This is not always the fault of their teacher; often their mind, which
needs to perceive the guiding thread, is too lazy to seek and find it.
But to come to their aid, we first must know just what hinders them.

Others will always ask of what use is it; they will not have understood
if they do not find about them, in practise or in nature, the
justification of such and such a mathematical concept. Under each word
they wish to put a sensible image; the definition must evoke this image,
so that at each stage of the demonstration they may see it transform and
evolve. Only upon this condition do they comprehend and retain. Often
these deceive themselves; they do not listen to the reasoning, they look
at the figures; they think they have understood and they have only seen.

2. How many different tendencies! Must we combat them? Must we use them?
And if we wish to combat them, which should be favored? Must we show
those content with the pure logic that they have seen only one side of
the matter? Or need we say to those not so cheaply satisfied that what
they demand is not necessary?

In other words, should we constrain the young people to change the
nature of their minds? Such an attempt would be vain; we do not possess
the philosopher's stone which would enable us to transmute one into
another the metals confided to us; all we can do is to work with them,
adapting ourselves to their properties.

Many children are incapable of becoming mathematicians, to whom however
it is necessary to teach mathematics; and the mathematicians themselves
are not all cast in the same mold. To read their works suffices to
distinguish among them two sorts of minds, the logicians like
Weierstrass for example, the intuitives like Riemann. There is the same
difference among our students. The one sort prefer to treat their
problems 'by analysis' as they say, the others 'by geometry.'

It is useless to seek to change anything of that, and besides would it
be desirable? It is well that there are logicians and that there are
intuitives; who would dare say whether he preferred that Weierstrass had
never written or that there never had been a Riemann? We must therefore
resign ourselves to the diversity of minds, or better we must rejoice in
it.

3. Since the word understand has many meanings, the definitions which
will be best understood by some will not be best suited to others. We
have those which seek to produce an image, and those where we confine
ourselves to combining empty forms, perfectly intelligible, but purely
intelligible, which abstraction has deprived of all matter.

I know not whether it be necessary to cite examples. Let us cite them,
anyhow, and first the definition of fractions will furnish us an extreme
case. In the primary schools, to define a fraction, one cuts up an apple
or a pie; it is cut up mentally of course and not in reality, because I
do not suppose the budget of the primary instruction allows of such
prodigality. At the Normal School, on the other hand, or at the college,
it is said: a fraction is the combination of two whole numbers separated
by a horizontal bar; we define by conventions the operations to which
these symbols may be submitted; it is proved that the rules of these
operations are the same as in calculating with whole numbers, and we
ascertain finally that multiplying the fraction, according to these
rules, by the denominator gives the numerator. This is all very well
because we are addressing young people long familiarized with the notion
of fractions through having cut up apples or other objects, and whose
mind, matured by a hard mathematical education, has come little by
little to desire a purely logical definition. But the débutant to whom
one should try to give it, how dumfounded!

Such also are the definitions found in a book justly admired and greatly
honored, the _Foundations of Geometry_ by Hilbert. See in fact how he
begins: _We think three systems of_ THINGS _which we shall call points,
straights and planes_. What are these 'things'?

We know not, nor need we know; it would even be a pity to seek to know;
all we have the right to know of them is what the assumptions tell us;
this for example: _Two distinct points always determine a straight_,
which is followed by this remark: _in place of determine, we may say the
two points are on the straight, or the straight goes through these two
points or joins the two points_.

Thus 'to be on a straight' is simply defined as synonymous with
'determine a straight.' Behold a book of which I think much good, but
which I should not recommend to a school boy. Yet I could do so without
fear, he would not read much of it. I have taken extreme examples and no
teacher would dream of going that far. But even stopping short of such
models, does he not already expose himself to the same danger?

Suppose we are in a class; the professor dictates: the circle is the
locus of points of the plane equidistant from an interior point called
the center. The good scholar writes this phrase in his note-book; the
bad scholar draws faces; but neither understands; then the professor
takes the chalk and draws a circle on the board. "Ah!" think the
scholars, "why did he not say at once: a circle is a ring, we should
have understood." Doubtless the professor is right. The scholars'
definition would have been of no avail, since it could serve for no
demonstration, since besides it would not give them the salutary habit
of analyzing their conceptions. But one should show them that they do
not comprehend what they think they know, lead them to be conscious of
the roughness of their primitive conception, and of themselves to wish
it purified and made precise.

4. I shall return to these examples; I only wished to show you the two
opposed conceptions; they are in violent contrast. This contrast the
history of science explains. If we read a book written fifty years ago,
most of the reasoning we find there seems lacking in rigor. Then it was
assumed a continuous function can change sign only by vanishing; to-day
we prove it. It was assumed the ordinary rules of calculation are
applicable to incommensurable numbers; to-day we prove it. Many other
things were assumed which sometimes were false.

We trusted to intuition; but intuition can not give rigor, nor even
certainty; we see this more and more. It tells us for instance that
every curve has a tangent, that is to say that every continuous function
has a derivative, and that is false. And as we sought certainty, we had
to make less and less the part of intuition.

What has made necessary this evolution? We have not been slow to
perceive that rigor could not be established in the reasonings, if it
were not first put into the definitions.

The objects occupying mathematicians were long ill defined; we thought
we knew them because we represented them with the senses or the
imagination; but we had of them only a rough image and not a precise
concept upon which reasoning could take hold. It is there that the
logicians would have done well to direct their efforts.

So for the incommensurable number, the vague idea of continuity, which
we owe to intuition, has resolved itself into a complicated system of
inequalities bearing on whole numbers. Thus have finally vanished all
those difficulties which frightened our fathers when they reflected upon
the foundations of the infinitesimal calculus. To-day only whole numbers
are left in analysis, or systems finite or infinite of whole numbers,
bound by a plexus of equalities and inequalities. Mathematics we say is
arithmetized.

5. But do you think mathematics has attained absolute rigor without
making any sacrifice? Not at all; what it has gained in rigor it has
lost in objectivity. It is by separating itself from reality that it has
acquired this perfect purity. We may freely run over its whole domain,
formerly bristling with obstacles, but these obstacles have not
disappeared. They have only been moved to the frontier, and it would be
necessary to vanquish them anew if we wished to break over this frontier
to enter the realm of the practical.

We had a vague notion, formed of incongruous elements, some _a priori_,
others coming from experiences more or less digested; we thought we
knew, by intuition, its principal properties. To-day we reject the
empiric elements, retaining only the _a priori_; one of the properties
serves as definition and all the others are deduced from it by rigorous
reasoning. This is all very well, but it remains to be proved that this
property, which has become a definition, pertains to the real objects
which experience had made known to us and whence we drew our vague
intuitive notion. To prove that, it would be necessary to appeal to
experience, or to make an effort of intuition, and if we could not prove
it, our theorems would be perfectly rigorous, but perfectly useless.

Logic sometimes makes monsters. Since half a century we have seen arise
a crowd of bizarre functions which seem to try to resemble as little as
possible the honest functions which serve some purpose. No longer
continuity, or perhaps continuity, but no derivatives, etc. Nay more,
from the logical point of view, it is these strange functions which are
the most general, those one meets without seeking no longer appear
except as particular case. There remains for them only a very small
corner.

Heretofore when a new function was invented, it was for some practical
end; to-day they are invented expressly to put at fault the reasonings
of our fathers, and one never will get from them anything more than
that.

If logic were the sole guide of the teacher, it would be necessary to
begin with the most general functions, that is to say with the most
bizarre. It is the beginner that would have to be set grappling with
this teratologic museum. If you do not do it, the logicians might say,
you will achieve rigor only by stages.

6. Yes, perhaps, but we can not make so cheap of reality, and I mean not
only the reality of the sensible world, which however has its worth,
since it is to combat against it that nine tenths of your students ask
of you weapons. There is a reality more subtile, which makes the very
life of the mathematical beings, and which is quite other than logic.

Our body is formed of cells, and the cells of atoms; are these cells and
these atoms then all the reality of the human body? The way these cells
are arranged, whence results the unity of the individual, is it not also
a reality and much more interesting?

A naturalist who never had studied the elephant except in the
microscope, would he think he knew the animal adequately? It is the same
in mathematics. When the logician shall have broken up each
demonstration into a multitude of elementary operations, all correct, he
still will not possess the whole reality; this I know not what which
makes the unity of the demonstration will completely escape him.

In the edifices built up by our masters, of what use to admire the work
of the mason if we can not comprehend the plan of the architect? Now
pure logic can not give us this appreciation of the total effect; this
we must ask of intuition.

Take for instance the idea of continuous function. This is at first only
a sensible image, a mark traced by the chalk on the blackboard. Little
by little it is refined; we use it to construct a complicated system of
inequalities, which reproduces all the features of the primitive image;
when all is done, we have _removed the centering_, as after the
construction of an arch; this rough representation, support thenceforth
useless, has disappeared and there remains only the edifice itself,
irreproachable in the eyes of the logician. And yet, if the professor
did not recall the primitive image, if he did not restore momentarily
the _centering_, how could the student divine by what caprice all these
inequalities have been scaffolded in this fashion one upon another? The
definition would be logically correct, but it would not show him the
veritable reality.

7. So back we must return; doubtless it is hard for a master to teach
what does not entirely satisfy him; but the satisfaction of the master
is not the unique object of teaching; we should first give attention to
what the mind of the pupil is and to what we wish it to become.

Zoologists maintain that the embryonic development of an animal
recapitulates in brief the whole history of its ancestors throughout
geologic time. It seems it is the same in the development of minds. The
teacher should make the child go over the path his fathers trod; more
rapidly, but without skipping stations. For this reason, the history of
science should be our first guide.

Our fathers thought they knew what a fraction was, or continuity, or the
area of a curved surface; we have found they did not know it. Just so
our scholars think they know it when they begin the serious study of
mathematics. If without warning I tell them: "No, you do not know it;
what you think you understand, you do not understand; I must prove to
you what seems to you evident," and if in the demonstration I support
myself upon premises which to them seem less evident than the
conclusion, what shall the unfortunates think? They will think that the
science of mathematics is only an arbitrary mass of useless subtilities;
either they will be disgusted with it, or they will play it as a game
and will reach a state of mind like that of the Greek sophists.

Later, on the contrary, when the mind of the scholar, familiarized with
mathematical reasoning, has been matured by this long frequentation, the
doubts will arise of themselves and then your demonstration will be
welcome. It will awaken new doubts, and the questions will arise
successively to the child, as they arose successively to our fathers,
until perfect rigor alone can satisfy him. To doubt everything does not
suffice, one must know why he doubts.

8. The principal aim of mathematical teaching is to develop certain
faculties of the mind, and among them intuition is not the least
precious. It is through it that the mathematical world remains in
contact with the real world, and if pure mathematics could do without
it, it would always be necessary to have recourse to it to fill up the
chasm which separates the symbol from reality. The practician will
always have need of it, and for one pure geometer there should be a
hundred practicians.


The engineer should receive a complete mathematical education, but for
what should it serve him?

To see the different aspects of things and see them quickly; he has no
time to hunt mice. It is necessary that, in the complex physical objects
presented to him, he should promptly recognize the point where the
mathematical tools we have put in his hands can take hold. How could he
do it if we should leave between instruments and objects the deep chasm
hollowed out by the logicians?

9. Besides the engineers, other scholars, less numerous, are in their
turn to become teachers; they therefore must go to the very bottom; a
knowledge deep and rigorous of the first principles is for them before
all indispensable. But this is no reason not to cultivate in them
intuition; for they would get a false idea of the science if they never
looked at it except from a single side, and besides they could not
develop in their students a quality they did not themselves possess.

For the pure geometer himself, this faculty is necessary; it is by logic
one demonstrates, by intuition one invents. To know how to criticize is
good, to know how to create is better. You know how to recognize if a
combination is correct; what a predicament if you have not the art of
choosing among all the possible combinations. Logic tells us that on
such and such a way we are sure not to meet any obstacle; it does not
say which way leads to the end. For that it is necessary to see the end
from afar, and the faculty which teaches us to see is intuition. Without
it the geometer would be like a writer who should be versed in grammar
but had no ideas. Now how could this faculty develop if, as soon as it
showed itself, we chase it away and proscribe it, if we learn to set it
at naught before knowing the good of it.

And here permit a parenthesis to insist upon the importance of written
exercises. Written compositions are perhaps not sufficiently emphasized
in certain examinations, at the polytechnic school, for instance. I am
told they would close the door against very good scholars who have
mastered the course, thoroughly understanding it, and who nevertheless
are incapable of making the slightest application. I have just said the
word understand has several meanings: such students only understand in
the first way, and we have seen that suffices neither to make an
engineer nor a geometer. Well, since choice must be made, I prefer those
who understand completely.

10. But is the art of sound reasoning not also a precious thing, which
the professor of mathematics ought before all to cultivate? I take good
care not to forget that. It should occupy our attention and from the
very beginning. I should be distressed to see geometry degenerate into I
know not what tachymetry of low grade and I by no means subscribe to the
extreme doctrines of certain German Oberlehrer. But there are occasions
enough to exercise the scholars in correct reasoning in the parts of
mathematics where the inconveniences I have pointed out do not present
themselves. There are long chains of theorems where absolute logic has
reigned from the very first and, so to speak, quite naturally, where the
first geometers have given us models we should constantly imitate and
admire.

It is in the exposition of first principles that it is necessary to
avoid too much subtility; there it would be most discouraging and
moreover useless. We can not prove everything and we can not define
everything; and it will always be necessary to borrow from intuition;
what does it matter whether it be done a little sooner or a little
later, provided that in using correctly premises it has furnished us, we
learn to reason soundly.

11. Is it possible to fulfill so many opposing conditions? Is this
possible in particular when it is a question of giving a definition? How
find a concise statement satisfying at once the uncompromising rules of
logic, our desire to grasp the place of the new notion in the totality
of the science, our need of thinking with images? Usually it will not be
found, and this is why it is not enough to state a definition; it must
be prepared for and justified.

What does that mean? You know it has often been said: every definition
implies an assumption, since it affirms the existence of the object
defined. The definition then will not be justified, from the purely
logical point of view, until one shall have _proved_ that it involves no
contradiction, neither in the terms, nor with the verities previously
admitted.

But this is not enough; the definition is stated to us as a convention;
but most minds will revolt if we wish to impose it upon them as an
_arbitrary_ convention. They will be satisfied only when you have
answered numerous questions.

Usually mathematical definitions, as M. Liard has shown, are veritable
constructions built up wholly of more simple notions. But why assemble
these elements in this way when a thousand other combinations were
possible?

Is it by caprice? If not, why had this combination more right to exist
than all the others? To what need does it respond? How was it foreseen
that it would play an important rôle in the development of the science,
that it would abridge our reasonings and our calculations? Is there in
nature some familiar object which is so to speak the rough and vague
image of it?

This is not all; if you answer all these questions in a satisfactory
manner, we shall see indeed that the new-born had the right to be
baptized; but neither is the choice of a name arbitrary; it is needful
to explain by what analogies one has been guided and that if analogous
names have been given to different things, these things at least differ
only in material and are allied in form; that their properties are
analogous and so to say parallel.

At this cost we may satisfy all inclinations. If the statement is
correct enough to please the logician, the justification will satisfy
the intuitive. But there is still a better procedure; wherever possible,
the justification should precede the statement and prepare for it; one
should be led on to the general statement by the study of some
particular examples.

Still another thing: each of the parts of the statement of a definition
has as aim to distinguish the thing to be defined from a class of other
neighboring objects. The definition will be understood only when you
have shown, not merely the object defined, but the neighboring objects
from which it is proper to distinguish it, when you have given a grasp
of the difference and when you have added explicitly: this is why in
stating the definition I have said this or that.

But it is time to leave generalities and examine how the somewhat
abstract principles I have expounded may be applied in arithmetic,
geometry, analysis and mechanics.


ARITHMETIC

12. The whole number is not to be defined; in return, one ordinarily
defines the operations upon whole numbers; I believe the scholars learn
these definitions by heart and attach no meaning to them. For that there
are two reasons: first they are made to learn them too soon, when their
mind as yet feels no need of them; then these definitions are not
satisfactory from the logical point of view. A good definition for
addition is not to be found just simply because we must stop and can not
define everything. It is not defining addition to say it consists in
adding. All that can be done is to start from a certain number of
concrete examples and say: the operation we have performed is called
addition.

For subtraction it is quite otherwise; it may be logically defined as
the operation inverse to addition; but should we begin in that way? Here
also start with examples, show on these examples the reciprocity of the
two operations; thus the definition will be prepared for and justified.

Just so again for multiplication; take a particular problem; show that
it may be solved by adding several equal numbers; then show that we
reach the result more quickly by a multiplication, an operation the
scholars already know how to do by routine and out of that the logical
definition will issue naturally.

Division is defined as the operation inverse to multiplication; but
begin by an example taken from the familiar notion of partition and show
on this example that multiplication reproduces the dividend.

There still remain the operations on fractions. The only difficulty is
for multiplication. It is best to expound first the theory of
proportion; from it alone can come a logical definition; but to make
acceptable the definitions met at the beginning of this theory, it is
necessary to prepare for them by numerous examples taken from classic
problems of the rule of three, taking pains to introduce fractional
data.

Neither should we fear to familiarize the scholars with the notion of
proportion by geometric images, either by appealing to what they
remember if they have already studied geometry, or in having recourse to
direct intuition, if they have not studied it, which besides will
prepare them to study it. Finally I shall add that after defining
multiplication of fractions, it is needful to justify this definition by
showing that it is commutative, associative and distributive, and
calling to the attention of the auditors that this is established to
justify the definition.

One sees what a rôle geometric images play in all this; and this rôle is
justified by the philosophy and the history of the science. If
arithmetic had remained free from all admixture of geometry, it would
have known only the whole number; it is to adapt itself to the needs of
geometry that it invented anything else.


GEOMETRY

In geometry we meet forthwith the notion of the straight line. Can the
straight line be defined? The well-known definition, the shortest path
from one point to another, scarcely satisfies me. I should start simply
with the _ruler_ and show at first to the scholar how one may verify a
ruler by turning; this verification is the true definition of the
straight line; the straight line is an axis of rotation. Next he should
be shown how to verify the ruler by sliding and he would have one of the
most important properties of the straight line.

As to this other property of being the shortest path from one point to
another, it is a theorem which can be demonstrated apodictically, but
the demonstration is too delicate to find a place in secondary teaching.
It will be worth more to show that a ruler previously verified fits on a
stretched thread. In presence of difficulties like these one need not
dread to multiply assumptions, justifying them by rough experiments.

It is needful to grant these assumptions, and if one admits a few more
of them than is strictly necessary, the evil is not very great; the
essential thing is to learn to reason soundly on the assumptions
admitted. Uncle Sarcey, who loved to repeat, often said that at the
theater the spectator accepts willingly all the postulates imposed upon
him at the beginning, but the curtain once raised, he becomes
uncompromising on the logic. Well, it is just the same in mathematics.

For the circle, we may start with the compasses; the scholars will
recognize at the first glance the curve traced; then make them observe
that the distance of the two points of the instrument remains constant,
that one of these points is fixed and the other movable, and so we shall
be led naturally to the logical definition.

The definition of the plane implies an axiom and this need not be
hidden. Take a drawing board and show that a moving ruler may be kept
constantly in complete contact with this plane and yet retain three
degrees of freedom. Compare with the cylinder and the cone, surfaces on
which an applied straight retains only two degrees of freedom; next take
three drawing boards; show first that they will glide while remaining
applied to one another and this with three degrees of freedom; and
finally to distinguish the plane from the sphere, show that two of these
boards which fit a third will fit each other.

Perhaps you are surprised at this incessant employment of moving things;
this is not a rough artifice; it is much more philosophic than one would
at first think. What is geometry for the philosopher? It is the study of
a group. And what group? That of the motions of solid bodies. How define
this group then without moving some solids?

Should we retain the classic definition of parallels and say parallels
are two coplanar straights which do not meet, however far they be
prolonged? No, since this definition is negative, since it is
unverifiable by experiment, and consequently can not be regarded as an
immediate datum of intuition. No, above all because it is wholly strange
to the notion of group, to the consideration of the motion of solid
bodies which is, as I have said, the true source of geometry. Would it
not be better to define first the rectilinear translation of an
invariable figure, as a motion wherein all the points of this figure
have rectilinear trajectories; to show that such a translation is
possible by making a square glide on a ruler?

From this experimental ascertainment, set up as an assumption, it would
be easy to derive the notion of parallel and Euclid's postulate itself.



MECHANICS

I need not return to the definition of velocity, or acceleration, or
other kinematic notions; they may be advantageously connected with that
of the derivative.

I shall insist, on the other hand, upon the dynamic notions of force and
mass.

I am struck by one thing: how very far the young people who have
received a high-school education are from applying to the real world the
mechanical laws they have been taught. It is not only that they are
incapable of it; they do not even think of it. For them the world of
science and the world of reality are separated by an impervious
partition wall.

If we try to analyze the state of mind of our scholars, this will
astonish us less. What is for them the real definition of force? Not
that which they recite, but that which, crouching in a nook of their
mind, from there directs it wholly. Here is the definition: forces are
arrows with which one makes parallelograms. These arrows are imaginary
things which have nothing to do with anything existing in nature. This
would not happen if they had been shown forces in reality before
representing them by arrows.

How shall we define force?

I think I have elsewhere sufficiently shown there is no good logical
definition. There is the anthropomorphic definition, the sensation of
muscular effort; this is really too rough and nothing useful can be
drawn from it.

Here is how we should go: first, to make known the genus force, we must
show one after the other all the species of this genus; they are very
numerous and very different; there is the pressure of fluids on the
insides of the vases wherein they are contained; the tension of threads;
the elasticity of a spring; the gravity working on all the molecules of
a body; friction; the normal mutual action and reaction of two solids in
contact.

This is only a qualitative definition; it is necessary to learn to
measure force. For that begin by showing that one force may be replaced
by another without destroying equilibrium; we may find the first example
of this substitution in the balance and Borda's double weighing.

Then show that a weight may be replaced, not only by another weight,
but by force of a different nature; for instance, Prony's brake permits
replacing weight by friction.

From all this arises the notion of the equivalence of two forces.

The direction of a force must be defined. If a force _F_ is equivalent
to another force _F'_ applied to the body considered by means of a
stretched string, so that _F_ may be replaced by _F'_ without affecting
the equilibrium, then the point of attachment of the string will be by
definition the point of application of the force _F'_, and that of the
equivalent force _F_; the direction of the string will be the direction
of the force _F'_ and that of the equivalent force _F_.

From that, pass to the comparison of the magnitude of forces. If a force
can replace two others with the same direction, it equals their sum;
show for example that a weight of 20 grams may replace two 10-gram
weights.

Is this enough? Not yet. We now know how to compare the intensity of two
forces which have the same direction and same point of application; we
must learn to do it when the directions are different. For that, imagine
a string stretched by a weight and passing over a pulley; we shall say
that the tensor of the two legs of the string is the same and equal to
the tension weight.

This definition of ours enables us to compare the tensions of the two
pieces of our string, and, using the preceding definitions, to compare
any two forces having the same direction as these two pieces. It should
be justified by showing that the tension of the last piece of the string
remains the same for the same tensor weight, whatever be the number and
the disposition of the reflecting pulleys. It has still to be completed
by showing this is only true if the pulleys are frictionless.

Once master of these definitions, it is to be shown that the point of
application, the direction and the intensity suffice to determine a
force; that two forces for which these three elements are the same are
_always_ equivalent and may _always_ be replaced by one another, whether
in equilibrium or in movement, and this whatever be the other forces
acting.

It must be shown that two concurrent forces may always be replaced by a
unique resultant; and that _this resultant remains the same_, whether
the body be at rest or in motion and whatever be the other forces
applied to it.

Finally it must be shown that forces thus defined satisfy the principle
of the equality of action and reaction.

Experiment it is, and experiment alone, which can teach us all that. It
will suffice to cite certain common experiments, which the scholars make
daily without suspecting it, and to perform before them a few
experiments, simple and well chosen.

It is after having passed through all these meanders that one may
represent forces by arrows, and I should even wish that in the
development of the reasonings return were made from time to time from
the symbol to the reality. For instance it would not be difficult to
illustrate the parallelogram of forces by aid of an apparatus formed of
three strings, passing over pulleys, stretched by weights and in
equilibrium while pulling on the same point.

Knowing force, it is easy to define mass; this time the definition
should be borrowed from dynamics; there is no way of doing otherwise,
since the end to be attained is to give understanding of the distinction
between mass and weight. Here again, the definition should be led up to
by experiments; there is in fact a machine which seems made expressly to
show what mass is, Atwood's machine; recall also the laws of the fall of
bodies, that the acceleration of gravity is the same for heavy as for
light bodies, and that it varies with the latitude, etc.

Now, if you tell me that all the methods I extol have long been applied
in the schools, I shall rejoice over it more than be surprised at it. I
know that on the whole our mathematical teaching is good. I do not wish
it overturned; that would even distress me. I only desire betterments
slowly progressive. This teaching should not be subjected to brusque
oscillations under the capricious blast of ephemeral fads. In such
tempests its high educative value would soon founder. A good and sound
logic should continue to be its basis. The definition by example is
always necessary, but it should prepare the way for the logical
definition, it should not replace it; it should at least make this
wished for, in the cases where the true logical definition can be
advantageously given only in advanced teaching.

Understand that what I have here said does not imply giving up what I
have written elsewhere. I have often had occasion to criticize certain
definitions I extol to-day. These criticisms hold good completely. These
definitions can only be provisory. But it is by way of them that we must
pass.



CHAPTER III

MATHEMATICS AND LOGIC


INTRODUCTION

Can mathematics be reduced to logic without having to appeal to
principles peculiar to mathematics? There is a whole school, abounding
in ardor and full of faith, striving to prove it. They have their own
special language, which is without words, using only signs. This
language is understood only by the initiates, so that commoners are
disposed to bow to the trenchant affirmations of the adepts. It is
perhaps not unprofitable to examine these affirmations somewhat closely,
to see if they justify the peremptory tone with which they are
presented.

But to make clear the nature of the question it is necessary to enter
upon certain historical details and in particular to recall the
character of the works of Cantor.

Since long ago the notion of infinity had been introduced into
mathematics; but this infinite was what philosophers call a _becoming_.
The mathematical infinite was only a quantity capable of increasing
beyond all limit: it was a variable quantity of which it could not be
said that it _had passed_ all limits, but only that it _could pass_
them.

Cantor has undertaken to introduce into mathematics an _actual
infinite_, that is to say a quantity which not only is capable of
passing all limits, but which is regarded as having already passed them.
He has set himself questions like these: Are there more points in space
than whole numbers? Are there more points in space than points in a
plane? etc.

And then the number of whole numbers, that of the points of space, etc.,
constitutes what he calls a _transfinite cardinal number_, that is to
say a cardinal number greater than all the ordinary cardinal numbers.
And he has occupied himself in comparing these transfinite cardinal
numbers. In arranging in a proper order the elements of an aggregate
containing an infinity of them, he has also imagined what he calls
transfinite ordinal numbers upon which I shall not dwell.

Many mathematicians followed his lead and set a series of questions of
the sort. They so familiarized themselves with transfinite numbers that
they have come to make the theory of finite numbers depend upon that of
Cantor's cardinal numbers. In their eyes, to teach arithmetic in a way
truly logical, one should begin by establishing the general properties
of transfinite cardinal numbers, then distinguish among them a very
small class, that of the ordinary whole numbers. Thanks to this détour,
one might succeed in proving all the propositions relative to this
little class (that is to say all our arithmetic and our algebra) without
using any principle foreign to logic. This method is evidently contrary
to all sane psychology; it is certainly not in this way that the human
mind proceeded in constructing mathematics; so its authors do not dream,
I think, of introducing it into secondary teaching. But is it at least
logic, or, better, is it correct? It may be doubted.

The geometers who have employed it are however very numerous. They have
accumulated formulas and they have thought to free themselves from what
was not pure logic by writing memoirs where the formulas no longer
alternate with explanatory discourse as in the books of ordinary
mathematics, but where this discourse has completely disappeared.

Unfortunately they have reached contradictory results, what are called
the _cantorian antinomies_, to which we shall have occasion to return.
These contradictions have not discouraged them and they have tried to
modify their rules so as to make those disappear which had already shown
themselves, without being sure, for all that, that new ones would not
manifest themselves.

It is time to administer justice on these exaggerations. I do not hope
to convince them; for they have lived too long in this atmosphere.
Besides, when one of their demonstrations has been refuted, we are sure
to see it resurrected with insignificant alterations, and some of them
have already risen several times from their ashes. Such long ago was the
Lernæan hydra with its famous heads which always grew again. Hercules
got through, since his hydra had only nine heads, or eleven; but here
there are too many, some in England, some in Germany, in Italy, in
France, and he would have to give up the struggle. So I appeal only to
men of good judgment unprejudiced.


I

In these latter years numerous works have been published on pure
mathematics and the philosophy of mathematics, trying to separate and
isolate the logical elements of mathematical reasoning. These works have
been analyzed and expounded very clearly by M. Couturat in a book
entitled: _The Principles of Mathematics_.

For M. Couturat, the new works, and in particular those of Russell and
Peano, have finally settled the controversy, so long pending between
Leibnitz and Kant. They have shown that there are no synthetic judgments
a priori (Kant's phrase to designate judgments which can neither be
demonstrated analytically, nor reduced to identities, nor established
experimentally), they have shown that mathematics is entirely reducible
to logic and that intuition here plays no rôle.

This is what M. Couturat has set forth in the work just cited; this he
says still more explicitly in his Kant jubilee discourse, so that I
heard my neighbor whisper: "I well see this is the centenary of Kant's
_death_."

Can we subscribe to this conclusive condemnation? I think not, and I
shall try to show why.


II

What strikes us first in the new mathematics is its purely formal
character: "We think," says Hilbert, "three sorts of _things_, which we
shall call points, straights and planes. We convene that a straight
shall be determined by two points, and that in place of saying this
straight is determined by these two points, we may say it passes through
these two points, or that these two points are situated on this
straight." What these _things_ are, not only we do not know, but we
should not seek to know. We have no need to, and one who never had seen
either point or straight or plane could geometrize as well as we. That
the phrase _to pass through_, or the phrase _to be situated upon_ may
arouse in us no image, the first is simply a synonym of to _be
determined_ and the second of _to determine_.

Thus, be it understood, to demonstrate a theorem, it is neither
necessary nor even advantageous to know what it means. The geometer
might be replaced by the _logic piano_ imagined by Stanley Jevons; or,
if you choose, a machine might be imagined where the assumptions were
put in at one end, while the theorems came out at the other, like the
legendary Chicago machine where the pigs go in alive and come out
transformed into hams and sausages. No more than these machines need the
mathematician know what he does.

I do not make this formal character of his geometry a reproach to
Hilbert. This is the way he should go, given the problem he set himself.
He wished to reduce to a minimum the number of the fundamental
assumptions of geometry and completely enumerate them; now, in
reasonings where our mind remains active, in those where intuition still
plays a part, in living reasonings, so to speak, it is difficult not to
introduce an assumption or a postulate which passes unperceived. It is
therefore only after having carried back all the geometric reasonings to
a form purely mechanical that he could be sure of having accomplished
his design and finished his work.

What Hilbert did for geometry, others have tried to do for arithmetic
and analysis. Even if they had entirely succeeded, would the Kantians be
finally condemned to silence? Perhaps not, for in reducing mathematical
thought to an empty form, it is certainly mutilated.

Even admitting it were established that all the theorems could be
deduced by procedures purely analytic, by simple logical combinations of
a finite number of assumptions, and that these assumptions are only
conventions; the philosopher would still have the right to investigate
the origins of these conventions, to see why they have been judged
preferable to the contrary conventions.

And then the logical correctness of the reasonings leading from the
assumptions to the theorems is not the only thing which should occupy
us. The rules of perfect logic, are they the whole of mathematics? As
well say the whole art of playing chess reduces to the rules of the
moves of the pieces. Among all the constructs which can be built up of
the materials furnished by logic, choice must be made; the true geometer
makes this choice judiciously because he is guided by a sure instinct,
or by some vague consciousness of I know not what more profound and more
hidden geometry, which alone gives value to the edifice constructed.

To seek the origin of this instinct, to study the laws of this deep
geometry, felt, not stated, would also be a fine employment for the
philosophers who do not want logic to be all. But it is not at this
point of view I wish to put myself, it is not thus I wish to consider
the question. The instinct mentioned is necessary for the inventor, but
it would seem at first we might do without it in studying the science
once created. Well, what I wish to investigate is if it be true that,
the principles of logic once admitted, one can, I do not say discover,
but demonstrate, all the mathematical verities without making a new
appeal to intuition.


III

I once said no to this question:[12] should our reply be modified by the
recent works? My saying no was because "the principle of complete
induction" seemed to me at once necessary to the mathematician and
irreducible to logic. The statement of this principle is: "If a property
be true of the number 1, and if we establish that it is true of _n_ + 1
provided it be of _n_, it will be true of all the whole numbers."
Therein I see the mathematical reasoning par excellence. I did not mean
to say, as has been supposed, that all mathematical reasonings can be
reduced to an application of this principle. Examining these reasonings
closely, we there should see applied many other analogous principles,
presenting the same essential characteristics. In this category of
principles, that of complete induction is only the simplest of all and
this is why I have chosen it as type.

  [12] See _Science and Hypothesis_, chapter I.

The current name, principle of complete induction, is not justified.
This mode of reasoning is none the less a true mathematical induction
which differs from ordinary induction only by its certitude.


IV

DEFINITIONS AND ASSUMPTIONS

The existence of such principles is a difficulty for the uncompromising
logicians; how do they pretend to get out of it? The principle of
complete induction, they say, is not an assumption properly so called or
a synthetic judgment _a priori_; it is just simply the definition of
whole number. It is therefore a simple convention. To discuss this way
of looking at it, we must examine a little closely the relations between
definitions and assumptions.

Let us go back first to an article by M. Couturat on mathematical
definitions which appeared in _l'Enseignement mathématique_, a magazine
published by Gauthier-Villars and by Georg at Geneva. We shall see there
a distinction between the _direct definition and the definition by
postulates_.

"The definition by postulates," says M. Couturat, "applies not to a
single notion, but to a system of notions; it consists in enumerating
the fundamental relations which unite them and which enable us to
demonstrate all their other properties; these relations are postulates."

If previously have been defined all these notions but one, then this
last will be by definition the thing which verifies these postulates.
Thus certain indemonstrable assumptions of mathematics would be only
disguised definitions. This point of view is often legitimate; and I
have myself admitted it in regard for instance to Euclid's postulate.

The other assumptions of geometry do not suffice to completely define
distance; the distance then will be, by definition, among all the
magnitudes which satisfy these other assumptions, that which is such as
to make Euclid's postulate true.

Well the logicians suppose true for the principle of complete induction
what I admit for Euclid's postulate; they want to see in it only a
disguised definition.

But to give them this right, two conditions must be fulfilled. Stuart
Mill says every definition implies an assumption, that by which the
existence of the defined object is affirmed. According to that, it
would no longer be the assumption which might be a disguised definition,
it would on the contrary be the definition which would be a disguised
assumption. Stuart Mill meant the word existence in a material and
empirical sense; he meant to say that in defining the circle we affirm
there are round things in nature.

Under this form, his opinion is inadmissible. Mathematics is independent
of the existence of material objects; in mathematics the word exist can
have only one meaning, it means free from contradiction. Thus rectified,
Stuart Mill's thought becomes exact; in defining a thing, we affirm that
the definition implies no contradiction.

If therefore we have a system of postulates, and if we can demonstrate
that these postulates imply no contradiction, we shall have the right to
consider them as representing the definition of one of the notions
entering therein. If we can not demonstrate that, it must be admitted
without proof, and that then will be an assumption; so that, seeking the
definition under the postulate, we should find the assumption under the
definition.

Usually, to show that a definition implies no contradiction, we proceed
by _example_, we try to make an example of a thing satisfying the
definition. Take the case of a definition by postulates; we wish to
define a notion _A_, and we say that, by definition, an _A_ is anything
for which certain postulates are true. If we can prove directly that all
these postulates are true of a certain object _B_, the definition will
be justified; the object _B_ will be an _example_ of an _A_. We shall be
certain that the postulates are not contradictory, since there are cases
where they are all true at the same time.

But such a direct demonstration by example is not always possible.

To establish that the postulates imply no contradiction, it is then
necessary to consider all the propositions deducible from these
postulates considered as premises, and to show that, among these
propositions, no two are contradictory. If these propositions are finite
in number, a direct verification is possible. This case is infrequent
and uninteresting. If these propositions are infinite in number, this
direct verification can no longer be made; recourse must be had to
procedures where in general it is necessary to invoke just this
principle of complete induction which is precisely the thing to be
proved.

This is an explanation of one of the conditions the logicians should
satisfy, _and further on we shall see they have not done it_.


V

There is a second. When we give a definition, it is to use it.

We therefore shall find in the sequel of the exposition the word
defined; have we the right to affirm, of the thing represented by this
word, the postulate which has served for definition? Yes, evidently, if
the word has retained its meaning, if we do not attribute to it
implicitly a different meaning. Now this is what sometimes happens and
it is usually difficult to perceive it; it is needful to see how this
word comes into our discourse, and if the gate by which it has entered
does not imply in reality a definition other than that stated.

This difficulty presents itself in all the applications of mathematics.
The mathematical notion has been given a definition very refined and
very rigorous; and for the pure mathematician all doubt has disappeared;
but if one wishes to apply it to the physical sciences for instance, it
is no longer a question of this pure notion, but of a concrete object
which is often only a rough image of it. To say that this object
satisfies, at least approximately, the definition, is to state a new
truth, which experience alone can put beyond doubt, and which no longer
has the character of a conventional postulate.

But without going beyond pure mathematics, we also meet the same
difficulty.

You give a subtile definition of numbers; then, once this definition
given, you think no more of it; because, in reality, it is not it which
has taught you what number is; you long ago knew that, and when the word
number further on is found under your pen, you give it the same sense as
the first comer. To know what is this meaning and whether it is the same
in this phrase or that, it is needful to see how you have been led to
speak of number and to introduce this word into these two phrases. I
shall not for the moment dilate upon this point, because we shall have
occasion to return to it.

Thus consider a word of which we have given explicitly a definition _A_;
afterwards in the discourse we make a use of it which implicitly
supposes another definition _B_. It is possible that these two
definitions designate the same thing. But that this is so is a new truth
which must either be demonstrated or admitted as an independent
assumption.

_We shall see farther on that the logicians have not fulfilled the
second condition any better than the first._


VI

The definitions of number are very numerous and very different; I forego
the enumeration even of the names of their authors. We should not be
astonished that there are so many. If one among them was satisfactory,
no new one would be given. If each new philosopher occupying himself
with this question has thought he must invent another one, this was
because he was not satisfied with those of his predecessors, and he was
not satisfied with them because he thought he saw a petitio principii.

I have always felt, in reading the writings devoted to this problem, a
profound feeling of discomfort; I was always expecting to run against a
petitio principii, and when I did not immediately perceive it, I feared
I had overlooked it.

This is because it is impossible to give a definition without using a
sentence, and difficult to make a sentence without using a number word,
or at least the word several, or at least a word in the plural. And then
the declivity is slippery and at each instant there is risk of a fall
into petitio principii.

I shall devote my attention in what follows only to those of these
definitions where the petitio principii is most ably concealed.


VII

PASIGRAPHY

The symbolic language created by Peano plays a very grand rôle in these
new researches. It is capable of rendering some service, but I think M.
Couturat attaches to it an exaggerated importance which must astonish
Peano himself.

The essential element of this language is certain algebraic signs which
represent the different conjunctions: if, and, or, therefore. That these
signs may be convenient is possible; but that they are destined to
revolutionize all philosophy is a different matter. It is difficult to
admit that the word _if_ acquires, when written C, a virtue it had not
when written if. This invention of Peano was first called _pasigraphy_,
that is to say the art of writing a treatise on mathematics without
using a single word of ordinary language. This name defined its range
very exactly. Later, it was raised to a more eminent dignity by
conferring on it the title of _logistic_. This word is, it appears,
employed at the Military Academy, to designate the art of the
quartermaster of cavalry, the art of marching and cantoning troops; but
here no confusion need be feared, and it is at once seen that this new
name implies the design of revolutionizing logic.

We may see the new method at work in a mathematical memoir by
Burali-Forti, entitled: _Una Questione sui numeri transfiniti_, inserted
in Volume XI of the _Rendiconti del circolo matematico di Palermo_.

I begin by saying this memoir is very interesting, and my taking it here
as example is precisely because it is the most important of all those
written in the new language. Besides, the uninitiated may read it,
thanks to an Italian interlinear translation.

What constitutes the importance of this memoir is that it has given the
first example of those antinomies met in the study of transfinite
numbers and making since some years the despair of mathematicians. The
aim, says Burali-Forti, of this note is to show there may be two
transfinite numbers (ordinals), _a_ and _b_, such that _a_ is neither
equal to, greater than, nor less than _b_.

To reassure the reader, to comprehend the considerations which follow,
he has no need of knowing what a transfinite ordinal number is.

Now, Cantor had precisely proved that between two transfinite numbers as
between two finite, there can be no other relation than equality or
inequality in one sense or the other. But it is not of the substance of
this memoir that I wish to speak here; that would carry me much too far
from my subject; I only wish to consider the form, and just to ask if
this form makes it gain much in rigor and whether it thus compensates
for the efforts it imposes upon the writer and the reader.

First we see Burali-Forti define the number 1 as follows:

  1 = [iota]T'{Ko[(n_](u, h)[epsilon](u[epsilon]Un)},

a definition eminently fitted to give an idea of the number 1 to persons
who had never heard speak of it.

I understand Peanian too ill to dare risk a critique, but still I fear
this definition contains a petitio principii, considering that I see the
figure 1 in the first member and Un in letters in the second.

However that may be, Burali-Forti starts from this definition and, after
a short calculation, reaches the equation:

  (27)  1[epsilon]No,

which tells us that One is a number.

And since we are on these definitions of the first numbers, we recall
that M. Couturat has also defined 0 and 1.

What is zero? It is the number of elements of the null class. And what
is the null class? It is that containing no element.

To define zero by null, and null by no, is really to abuse the wealth of
language; so M. Couturat has introduced an improvement in his
definition, by writing:

  0 = [iota][Lambda]:[phi]x = [Lambda]·[inverted c]·[Lambda]
                            = (x[epsilon][phi]x),

which means: zero is the number of things satisfying a condition never
satisfied.

But as never means _in no case_ I do not see that the progress is great.

I hasten to add that the definition M. Couturat gives of the number 1 is
more satisfactory.

One, says he in substance, is the number of elements in a class in which
any two elements are identical.

It is more satisfactory, I have said, in this sense that to define 1, he
does not use the word one; in compensation, he uses the word two. But I
fear, if asked what is two, M. Couturat would have to use the word one.



VIII

But to return to the memoir of Burali-Forti; I have said his conclusions
are in direct opposition to those of Cantor. Now, one day M. Hadamard
came to see me and the talk fell upon this antinomy.

"Burali-Forti's reasoning," I said, "does it not seem to you
irreproachable?" "No, and on the contrary I find nothing to object to in
that of Cantor. Besides, Burali-Forti had no right to speak of the
aggregate of _all_ the ordinal numbers."

"Pardon, he had the right, since he could always put

  [Omega] = T'(No,[epsilon]>).

I should like to know who was to prevent him, and can it be said a thing
does not exist, when we have called it [Omega]?"

It was in vain, I could not convince him (which besides would have been
sad, since he was right). Was it merely because I do not speak the
Peanian with enough eloquence? Perhaps; but between ourselves I do not
think so.

Thus, despite all this pasigraphic apparatus, the question was not
solved. What does that prove? In so far as it is a question only of
proving one a number, pasigraphy suffices, but if a difficulty presents
itself, if there is an antinomy to solve, pasigraphy becomes impotent.



CHAPTER IV

THE NEW LOGICS


I

_The Russell Logic_

To justify its pretensions, logic had to change. We have seen new logics
arise of which the most interesting is that of Russell. It seems he has
nothing new to write about formal logic, as if Aristotle there had
touched bottom. But the domain Russell attributes to logic is infinitely
more extended than that of the classic logic, and he has put forth on
the subject views which are original and at times well warranted.

First, Russell subordinates the logic of classes to that of
propositions, while the logic of Aristotle was above all the logic of
classes and took as its point of departure the relation of subject to
predicate. The classic syllogism, "Socrates is a man," etc., gives place
to the hypothetical syllogism: "If _A_ is true, _B_ is true; now if _B_
is true, _C_ is true," etc. And this is, I think, a most happy idea,
because the classic syllogism is easy to carry back to the hypothetical
syllogism, while the inverse transformation is not without difficulty.

And then this is not all. Russell's logic of propositions is the study
of the laws of combination of the conjunctions _if_, _and_, _or_, and
the negation _not_.

In adding here two other conjunctions, _and_ and _or_, Russell opens to
logic a new field. The symbols _and_, _or_ follow the same laws as the
two signs × and +, that is to say the commutative associative and
distributive laws. Thus _and_ represents logical multiplication, while
_or_ represents logical addition. This also is very interesting.

Russell reaches the conclusion that any false proposition implies all
other propositions true or false. M. Couturat says this conclusion will
at first seem paradoxical. It is sufficient however to have corrected a
bad thesis in mathematics to recognize how right Russell is. The
candidate often is at great pains to get the first false equation; but
that once obtained, it is only sport then for him to accumulate the most
surprising results, some of which even may be true.


II

We see how much richer the new logic is than the classic logic; the
symbols are multiplied and allow of varied combinations _which are no
longer limited in number_. Has one the right to give this extension to
the meaning of the word _logic_? It would be useless to examine this
question and to seek with Russell a mere quarrel about words. Grant him
what he demands; but be not astonished if certain verities declared
irreducible to logic in the old sense of the word find themselves now
reducible to logic in the new sense--something very different.

A great number of new notions have been introduced, and these are not
simply combinations of the old. Russell knows this, and not only at the
beginning of the first chapter, 'The Logic of Propositions,' but at the
beginning of the second and third, 'The Logic of Classes' and 'The Logic
of Relations,' he introduces new words that he declares indefinable.

And this is not all; he likewise introduces principles he declares
indemonstrable. But these indemonstrable principles are appeals to
intuition, synthetic judgments _a priori_. We regard them as intuitive
when we meet them more or less explicitly enunciated in mathematical
treatises; have they changed character because the meaning of the word
logic has been enlarged and we now find them in a book entitled
_Treatise on Logic_? _They have not changed nature; they have only
changed place._


III

Could these principles be considered as disguised definitions? It would
then be necessary to have some way of proving that they imply no
contradiction. It would be necessary to establish that, however far one
followed the series of deductions, he would never be exposed to
contradicting himself.

We might attempt to reason as follows: We can verify that the
operations of the new logic applied to premises exempt from
contradiction can only give consequences equally exempt from
contradiction. If therefore after _n_ operations we have not met
contradiction, we shall not encounter it after _n_ + 1. Thus it is
impossible that there should be a moment when contradiction _begins_,
which shows we shall never meet it. Have we the right to reason in this
way? No, for this would be to make use of complete induction; and
_remember, we do not yet know the principle of complete induction_.

We therefore have not the right to regard these assumptions as disguised
definitions and only one resource remains for us, to admit a new act of
intuition for each of them. Moreover I believe this is indeed the
thought of Russell and M. Couturat.

Thus each of the nine indefinable notions and of the twenty
indemonstrable propositions (I believe if it were I that did the
counting, I should have found some more) which are the foundation of the
new logic, logic in the broad sense, presupposes a new and independent
act of our intuition and (why not say it?) a veritable synthetic
judgment _a priori_. On this point all seem agreed, but what Russell
claims, and _what seems to me doubtful, is that after these appeals to
intuition, that will be the end of it; we need make no others and can
build all mathematics without the intervention of any new element_.


IV

M. Couturat often repeats that this new logic is altogether independent
of the idea of number. I shall not amuse myself by counting how many
numeral adjectives his exposition contains, both cardinal and ordinal,
or indefinite adjectives such as several. We may cite, however, some
examples:

"The logical product of _two_ or _more_ propositions is....";

"All propositions are capable only of _two_ values, true and false";

"The relative product of _two_ relations is a relation";

"A relation exists between two terms," etc., etc.

Sometimes this inconvenience would not be unavoidable, but sometimes
also it is essential. A relation is incomprehensible without two terms;
it is impossible to have the intuition of the relation, without having
at the same time that of its two terms, and without noticing they are
two, because, if the relation is to be conceivable, it is necessary that
there be two and only two.


V

_Arithmetic_

I reach what M. Couturat calls the _ordinal theory_ which is the
foundation of arithmetic properly so called. M. Couturat begins by
stating Peano's five assumptions, which are independent, as has been
proved by Peano and Padoa.

1. Zero is an integer.

2. Zero is not the successor of any integer.

3. The successor of an integer is an integer. To this it would be proper
to add,

Every integer has a successor.

4. Two integers are equal if their successors are.

The fifth assumption is the principle of complete induction.

M. Couturat considers these assumptions as disguised definitions; they
constitute the definition by postulates of zero, of successor, and of
integer.

But we have seen that for a definition by postulates to be acceptable we
must be able to prove that it implies no contradiction.

Is this the case here? Not at all.

The demonstration can not be made _by example_. We can not take a part
of the integers, for instance the first three, and prove they satisfy
the definition.

If I take the series 0, 1, 2, I see it fulfils the assumptions 1, 2, 4
and 5; but to satisfy assumption 3 it still is necessary that 3 be an
integer, and consequently that the series 0, 1, 2, 3, fulfil the
assumptions; we might prove that it satisfies assumptions 1, 2, 4, 5,
but assumption 3 requires besides that 4 be an integer and that the
series 0, 1, 2, 3, 4 fulfil the assumptions, and so on.

It is therefore impossible to demonstrate the assumptions for certain
integers without proving them for all; we must give up proof by
example.

It is necessary then to take all the consequences of our assumptions and
see if they contain no contradiction.

If these consequences were finite in number, this would be easy; but
they are infinite in number; they are the whole of mathematics, or at
least all arithmetic.

What then is to be done? Perhaps strictly we could repeat the reasoning
of number III.

But as we have said, this reasoning is complete induction, and it is
precisely the principle of complete induction whose justification would
be the point in question.


VI

_The Logic of Hilbert_

I come now to the capital work of Hilbert which he communicated to the
Congress of Mathematicians at Heidelberg, and of which a French
translation by M. Pierre Boutroux appeared in _l'Enseignement
mathématique_, while an English translation due to Halsted appeared in
_The Monist_.[13] In this work, which contains profound thoughts, the
author's aim is analogous to that of Russell, but on many points he
diverges from his predecessor.

  [13] 'The Foundations of Logic and Arithmetic,' _Monist_, XV.,
       338-352.

"But," he says (_Monist_, p. 340), "on attentive consideration we become
aware that in the usual exposition of the laws of logic certain
fundamental concepts of arithmetic are already employed; for example,
the concept of the aggregate, in part also the concept of number.

"We fall thus into a vicious circle and therefore to avoid paradoxes a
partly simultaneous development of the laws of logic and arithmetic is
requisite."

We have seen above that what Hilbert says of the principles of logic _in
the usual exposition_ applies likewise to the logic of Russell. So for
Russell logic is prior to arithmetic; for Hilbert they are
'simultaneous.' We shall find further on other differences still
greater, but we shall point them out as we come to them. I prefer to
follow step by step the development of Hilbert's thought, quoting
textually the most important passages.

"Let us take as the basis of our consideration first of all a
thought-thing 1 (one)" (p. 341). Notice that in so doing we in no wise
imply the notion of number, because it is understood that 1 is here only
a symbol and that we do not at all seek to know its meaning. "The taking
of this thing together with itself respectively two, three or more
times...." Ah! this time it is no longer the same; if we introduce the
words 'two,' 'three,' and above all 'more,' 'several,' we introduce the
notion of number; and then the definition of finite whole number which
we shall presently find, will come too late. Our author was too
circumspect not to perceive this begging of the question. So at the end
of his work he tries to proceed to a truly patching-up process.

Hilbert then introduces two simple objects 1 and =, and considers all
the combinations of these two objects, all the combinations of their
combinations, etc. It goes without saying that we must forget the
ordinary meaning of these two signs and not attribute any to them.

Afterwards he separates these combinations into two classes, the class
of the existent and the class of the non-existent, and till further
orders this separation is entirely arbitrary. Every affirmative
statement tells us that a certain combination belongs to the class of
the existent; every negative statement tells us that a certain
combination belongs to the class of the non-existent.


VII

Note now a difference of the highest importance. For Russell any object
whatsoever, which he designates by _x_, is an object absolutely
undetermined and about which he supposes nothing; for Hilbert it is one
of the combinations formed with the symbols 1 and =; he could not
conceive of the introduction of anything other than combinations of
objects already defined. Moreover Hilbert formulates his thought in the
neatest way, and I think I must reproduce _in extenso_ his statement (p.
348):

"In the assumptions the arbitraries (as equivalent for the concept
'every' and 'all' in the customary logic) represent only those
thought-things and their combinations with one another, which at this
stage are laid down as fundamental or are to be newly defined.
Therefore in the deduction of inferences from the assumptions, the
arbitraries, which occur in the assumptions, can be replaced only by
such thought-things and their combinations.

"Also we must duly remember, that through the super-addition and making
fundamental of a new thought-thing the preceding assumptions undergo an
enlargement of their validity, and where necessary, are to be subjected
to a change in conformity with the sense."

The contrast with Russell's view-point is complete. For this philosopher
we may substitute for _x_ not only objects already known, but anything.

Russell is faithful to his point of view, which is that of
comprehension. He starts from the general idea of being, and enriches it
more and more while restricting it, by adding new qualities. Hilbert on
the contrary recognizes as possible beings only combinations of objects
already known; so that (looking at only one side of his thought) we
might say he takes the view-point of extension.


VIII

Let us continue with the exposition of Hilbert's ideas. He introduces
two assumptions which he states in his symbolic language but which
signify, in the language of the uninitiated, that every quality is equal
to itself and that every operation performed upon two identical
quantities gives identical results.

So stated, they are evident, but thus to present them would be to
misrepresent Hilbert's thought. For him mathematics has to combine only
pure symbols, and a true mathematician should reason upon them without
preconceptions as to their meaning. So his assumptions are not for him
what they are for the common people.

He considers them as representing the definition by postulates of the
symbol (=) heretofore void of all signification. But to justify this
definition we must show that these two assumptions lead to no
contradiction. For this Hilbert used the reasoning of our number III,
without appearing to perceive that he is using complete induction.


IX

The end of Hilbert's memoir is altogether enigmatic and I shall not lay
stress upon it. Contradictions accumulate; we feel that the author is
dimly conscious of the _petitio principii_ he has committed, and that he
seeks vainly to patch up the holes in his argument.

What does this mean? At the point of proving that the definition of the
whole number by the assumption of complete induction implies no
contradiction, Hilbert withdraws as Russell and Couturat withdrew,
because the difficulty is too great.


X

_Geometry_

Geometry, says M. Couturat, is a vast body of doctrine wherein the
principle of complete induction does not enter. That is true in a
certain measure; we can not say it is entirely absent, but it enters
very slightly. If we refer to the _Rational Geometry_ of Dr. Halsted
(New York, John Wiley and Sons, 1904) built up in accordance with the
principles of Hilbert, we see the principle of induction enter for the
first time on page 114 (unless I have made an oversight, which is quite
possible).[14]

  [14] Second ed., 1907, p. 86; French ed., 1911, p. 97. G. B. H.

So geometry, which only a few years ago seemed the domain where the
reign of intuition was uncontested, is to-day the realm where the
logicians seem to triumph. Nothing could better measure the importance
of the geometric works of Hilbert and the profound impress they have
left on our conceptions.

But be not deceived. What is after all the fundamental theorem of
geometry? It is that the assumptions of geometry imply no contradiction,
and this we can not prove without the principle of induction.

How does Hilbert demonstrate this essential point? By leaning upon
analysis and through it upon arithmetic and through it upon the
principle of induction.

And if ever one invents another demonstration, it will still be
necessary to lean upon this principle, since the possible consequences
of the assumptions, of which it is necessary to show that they are not
contradictory, are infinite in number.


XI

_Conclusion_

Our conclusion straightway is that the principle of induction can not be
regarded as the disguised definition of the entire world.

Here are three truths: (1) The principle of complete induction; (2)
Euclid's postulate; (3) the physical law according to which phosphorus
melts at 44° (cited by M. Le Roy).

These are said to be three disguised definitions: the first, that of the
whole number; the second, that of the straight line; the third, that of
phosphorus.

I grant it for the second; I do not admit it for the other two. I must
explain the reason for this apparent inconsistency.

First, we have seen that a definition is acceptable only on condition
that it implies no contradiction. We have shown likewise that for the
first definition this demonstration is impossible; on the other hand, we
have just recalled that for the second Hilbert has given a complete
proof.

As to the third, evidently it implies no contradiction. Does this mean
that the definition guarantees, as it should, the existence of the
object defined? We are here no longer in the mathematical sciences, but
in the physical, and the word existence has no longer the same meaning.
It no longer signifies absence of contradiction; it means objective
existence.

You already see a first reason for the distinction I made between the
three cases; there is a second. In the applications we have to make of
these three concepts, do they present themselves to us as defined by
these three postulates?

The possible applications of the principle of induction are innumerable;
take, for example, one of those we have expounded above, and where it is
sought to prove that an aggregate of assumptions can lead to no
contradiction. For this we consider one of the series of syllogisms we
may go on with in starting from these assumptions as premises. When we
have finished the _n_th syllogism, we see we can make still another and
this is the _n_ + 1th. Thus the number _n_ serves to count a series of
successive operations; it is a number obtainable by successive
additions. This therefore is a number from which we may go back to
unity by _successive subtractions_. Evidently we could not do this if we
had _n_ = _n_ - 1, since then by subtraction we should always obtain
again the same number. So the way we have been led to consider this
number _n_ implies a definition of the finite whole number and this
definition is the following: A finite whole number is that which can be
obtained by successive additions; it is such that _n_ is not equal to
_n_ - 1.

That granted, what do we do? We show that if there has been no
contradiction up to the _n_th syllogism, no more will there be up to the
_n_ + 1th, and we conclude there never will be. You say: I have the
right to draw this conclusion, since the whole numbers are by definition
those for which a like reasoning is legitimate. But that implies another
definition of the whole number, which is as follows: A whole number is
that on which we may reason by recurrence. In the particular case it is
that of which we may say that, if the absence of contradiction up to the
time of a syllogism of which the number is an integer carries with it
the absence of contradiction up to the time of the syllogism whose
number is the following integer, we need fear no contradiction for any
of the syllogisms whose number is an integer.

The two definitions are not identical; they are doubtless equivalent,
but only in virtue of a synthetic judgment _a priori_; we can not pass
from one to the other by a purely logical procedure. Consequently we
have no right to adopt the second, after having introduced the whole
number by a way that presupposes the first.

On the other hand, what happens with regard to the straight line? I have
already explained this so often that I hesitate to repeat it again, and
shall confine myself to a brief recapitulation of my thought. We have
not, as in the preceding case, two equivalent definitions logically
irreducible one to the other. We have only one expressible in words.
Will it be said there is another which we feel without being able to
word it, since we have the intuition of the straight line or since we
represent to ourselves the straight line? First of all, we can not
represent it to ourselves in geometric space, but only in representative
space, and then we can represent to ourselves just as well the objects
which possess the other properties of the straight line, save that of
satisfying Euclid's postulate. These objects are 'the non-Euclidean
straights,' which from a certain point of view are not entities void of
sense, but circles (true circles of true space) orthogonal to a certain
sphere. If, among these objects equally capable of representation, it is
the first (the Euclidean straights) which we call straights, and not the
latter (the non-Euclidean straights), this is properly by definition.

And arriving finally at the third example, the definition of phosphorus,
we see the true definition would be: Phosphorus is the bit of matter I
see in yonder flask.


XII

And since I am on this subject, still another word. Of the phosphorus
example I said: "This proposition is a real verifiable physical law,
because it means that all bodies having all the other properties of
phosphorus, save its point of fusion, melt like it at 44°." And it was
answered: "No, this law is not verifiable, because if it were shown that
two bodies resembling phosphorus melt one at 44° and the other at 50°,
it might always be said that doubtless, besides the point of fusion,
there is some other unknown property by which they differ."

That was not quite what I meant to say. I should have written, "All
bodies possessing such and such properties finite in number (to wit, the
properties of phosphorus stated in the books on chemistry, the
fusion-point excepted) melt at 44°."

And the better to make evident the difference between the case of the
straight and that of phosphorus, one more remark. The straight has in
nature many images more or less imperfect, of which the chief are the
light rays and the rotation axis of the solid. Suppose we find the ray
of light does not satisfy Euclid's postulate (for example by showing
that a star has a negative parallax), what shall we do? Shall we
conclude that the straight being by definition the trajectory of light
does not satisfy the postulate, or, on the other hand, that the straight
by definition satisfying the postulate, the ray of light is not
straight?

Assuredly we are free to adopt the one or the other definition and
consequently the one or the other conclusion; but to adopt the first
would be stupid, because the ray of light probably satisfies only
imperfectly not merely Euclid's postulate, but the other properties of
the straight line, so that if it deviates from the Euclidean straight,
it deviates no less from the rotation axis of solids which is another
imperfect image of the straight line; while finally it is doubtless
subject to change, so that such a line which yesterday was straight will
cease to be straight to-morrow if some physical circumstance has
changed.

Suppose now we find that phosphorus does not melt at 44°, but at 43.9°.
Shall we conclude that phosphorus being by definition that which melts
at 44°, this body that we did call phosphorus is not true phosphorus,
or, on the other hand, that phosphorous melts at 43.9°? Here again we
are free to adopt the one or the other definition and consequently the
one or the other conclusion; but to adopt the first would be stupid
because we can not be changing the name of a substance every time we
determine a new decimal of its fusion-point.


XIII

To sum up, Russell and Hilbert have each made a vigorous effort; they
have each written a work full of original views, profound and often well
warranted. These two works give us much to think about and we have much
to learn from them. Among their results, some, many even, are solid and
destined to live.

But to say that they have finally settled the debate between Kant and
Leibnitz and ruined the Kantian theory of mathematics is evidently
incorrect. I do not know whether they really believed they had done it,
but if they believed so, they deceived themselves.



CHAPTER V

THE LATEST EFFORTS OF THE LOGISTICIANS


I

The logicians have attempted to answer the preceding considerations. For
that, a transformation of logistic was necessary, and Russell in
particular has modified on certain points his original views. Without
entering into the details of the debate, I should like to return to the
two questions to my mind most important: Have the rules of logistic
demonstrated their fruitfulness and infallibility? Is it true they
afford means of proving the principle of complete induction without any
appeal to intuition?


II

_The Infallibility of Logistic_

On the question of fertility, it seems M. Couturat has naïve illusions.
Logistic, according to him, lends invention 'stilts and wings,' and on
the next page: "_Ten years ago_, Peano published the first edition of
his _Formulaire_." How is that, ten years of wings and not to have
flown!

I have the highest esteem for Peano, who has done very pretty things
(for instance his 'space-filling curve,' a phrase now discarded); but
after all he has not gone further nor higher nor quicker than the
majority of wingless mathematicians, and would have done just as well
with his legs.

On the contrary I see in logistic only shackles for the inventor. It is
no aid to conciseness--far from it, and if twenty-seven equations were
necessary to establish that 1 is a number, how many would be needed to
prove a real theorem? If we distinguish, with Whitehead, the individual
_x_, the class of which the only member is _x_ and which shall be called
[iota]_x_, then the class of which the only member is the class of which
the only member is _x_ and which shall be called [mu]_x_, do you think
these distinctions, useful as they may be, go far to quicken our pace?

Logistic forces us to say all that is ordinarily left to be understood;
it makes us advance step by step; this is perhaps surer but not quicker.

It is not wings you logisticians give us, but leading-strings. And then
we have the right to require that these leading-strings prevent our
falling. This will be their only excuse. When a bond does not bear much
interest, it should at least be an investment for a father of a family.

Should your rules be followed blindly? Yes, else only intuition could
enable us to distinguish among them; but then they must be infallible;
for only in an infallible authority can one have a blind confidence.
This, therefore, is for you a necessity. Infallible you shall be, or not
at all.

You have no right to say to us: "It is true we make mistakes, but so do
you." For us to blunder is a misfortune, a very great misfortune; for
you it is death.

Nor may you ask: Does the infallibility of arithmetic prevent errors in
addition? The rules of calculation are infallible, and yet we see those
blunder _who do not apply these rules_; but in checking their
calculation it is at once seen where they went wrong. Here it is not at
all the case; the logicians _have applied_ their rules, and they have
fallen into contradiction; and so true is this, that they are preparing
to change these rules and to "sacrifice the notion of class." Why change
them if they were infallible?

"We are not obliged," you say, "to solve _hic et nunc_ all possible
problems." Oh, we do not ask so much of you. If, in face of a problem,
you would give _no_ solution, we should have nothing to say; but on the
contrary you give us _two_ of them and those contradictory, and
consequently at least one false; this it is which is failure.

Russell seeks to reconcile these contradictions, which can only be done,
according to him, "by restricting or even sacrificing the notion of
class." And M. Couturat, discovering the success of his attempt, adds:
"If the logicians succeed where others have failed, M. Poincaré will
remember this phrase, and give the honor of the solution to logistic."

But no! Logistic exists, it has its code which has already had four
editions; or rather this code is logistic itself. Is Mr. Russell
preparing to show that one at least of the two contradictory reasonings
has transgressed the code? Not at all; he is preparing to change these
laws and to abrogate a certain number of them. If he succeeds, I shall
give the honor of it to Russell's intuition and not to the Peanian
logistic which he will have destroyed.


III

_The Liberty of Contradiction_

I made two principal objections to the definition of whole number
adopted in logistic. What says M. Couturat to the first of these
objections?

What does the word _exist_ mean in mathematics? It means, I said, to be
free from contradiction. This M. Couturat contests. "Logical existence,"
says he, "is quite another thing from the absence of contradiction. It
consists in the fact that a class is not empty." To say: _a_'s exist,
is, by definition, to affirm that the class _a_ is not null.

And doubtless to affirm that the class _a_ is not null, is, by
definition, to affirm that _a_'s exist. But one of the two affirmations
is as denuded of meaning as the other, if they do not both signify,
either that one may see or touch _a_'s which is the meaning physicists
or naturalists give them, or that one may conceive an _a_ without being
drawn into contradictions, which is the meaning given them by logicians
and mathematicians.

For M. Couturat, "it is not non-contradiction that proves existence, but
it is existence that proves non-contradiction." To establish the
existence of a class, it is necessary therefore to establish, by an
_example_, that there is an individual belonging to this class: "But, it
will be said, how is the existence of this individual proved? Must not
this existence be established, in order that the existence of the class
of which it is a part may be deduced? Well, no; however paradoxical may
appear the assertion, we never demonstrate the existence of an
individual. Individuals, just because they are individuals, are always
considered as existent.... We never have to express that an individual
exists, absolutely speaking, but only that it exists in a class." M.
Couturat finds his own assertion paradoxical, and he will certainly not
be the only one. Yet it must have a meaning. It doubtless means that the
existence of an individual, alone in the world, and of which nothing is
affirmed, can not involve contradiction; in so far as it is all alone it
evidently will not embarrass any one. Well, so let it be; we shall admit
the existence of the individual, 'absolutely speaking,' but nothing
more. It remains to prove the existence of the individual 'in a class,'
and for that it will always be necessary to prove that the affirmation,
"Such an individual belongs to such a class," is neither contradictory
in itself, nor to the other postulates adopted.

"It is then," continues M. Couturat, "arbitrary and misleading to
maintain that a definition is valid only if we first prove it is not
contradictory." One could not claim in prouder and more energetic terms
the liberty of contradiction. "In any case, the _onus probandi_ rests
upon those who believe that these principles are contradictory."
Postulates are presumed to be compatible until the contrary is proved,
just as the accused person is presumed innocent. Needless to add that I
do not assent to this claim. But, you say, the demonstration you require
of us is impossible, and you can not ask us to jump over the moon.
Pardon me; that is impossible for you, but not for us, who admit the
principle of induction as a synthetic judgment _a priori_. And that
would be necessary for you, as for us.

To demonstrate that a system of postulates implies no contradiction, it
is necessary to apply the principle of complete induction; this mode of
reasoning not only has nothing 'bizarre' about it, but it is the only
correct one. It is not 'unlikely' that it has ever been employed; and it
is not hard to find 'examples and precedents' of it. I have cited two
such instances borrowed from Hilbert's article. He is not the only one
to have used it, and those who have not done so have been wrong. What I
have blamed Hilbert for is not his having recourse to it (a born
mathematician such as he could not fail to see a demonstration was
necessary and this the only one possible), but his having recourse
without recognizing the reasoning by recurrence.


IV

_The Second Objection_

I pointed out a second error of logistic in Hilbert's article. To-day
Hilbert is excommunicated and M. Couturat no longer regards him as of
the logistic cult; so he asks if I have found the same fault among the
orthodox. No, I have not seen it in the pages I have read; I know not
whether I should find it in the three hundred pages they have written
which I have no desire to read.

Only, they must commit it the day they wish to make any application of
mathematics. This science has not as sole object the eternal
contemplation of its own navel; it has to do with nature and some day it
will touch it. Then it will be necessary to shake off purely verbal
definitions and to stop paying oneself with words.

To go back to the example of Hilbert: always the point at issue is
reasoning by recurrence and the question of knowing whether a system of
postulates is not contradictory. M. Couturat will doubtless say that
then this does not touch him, but it perhaps will interest those who do
not claim, as he does, the liberty of contradiction.

We wish to establish, as above, that we shall never encounter
contradiction after any number of deductions whatever, provided this
number be finite. For that, it is necessary to apply the principle of
induction. Should we here understand by finite number every number to
which by definition the principle of induction applies? Evidently not,
else we should be led to most embarrassing consequences. To have the
right to lay down a system of postulates, we must be sure they are not
contradictory. This is a truth admitted by _most_ scientists; I should
have written _by all_ before reading M. Couturat's last article. But
what does this signify? Does it mean that we must be sure of not meeting
contradiction after a _finite_ number of propositions, the _finite_
number being by definition that which has all properties of recurrent
nature, so that if one of these properties fails--if, for instance, we
come upon a contradiction--we shall agree to say that the number in
question is not finite? In other words, do we mean that we must be sure
not to meet contradictions, on condition of agreeing to stop just when
we are about to encounter one? To state such a proposition is enough to
condemn it.

So, Hilbert's reasoning not only assumes the principle of induction, but
it supposes that this principle is given us not as a simple definition,
but as a synthetic judgment _a priori_.

To sum up:

A demonstration is necessary.

The only demonstration possible is the proof by recurrence.

This is legitimate only if we admit the principle of induction and if we
regard it not as a definition but as a synthetic judgment.


V

_The Cantor Antinomies_

Now to examine Russell's new memoir. This memoir was written with the
view to conquer the difficulties raised by those Cantor antinomies to
which frequent allusion has already been made. Cantor thought he could
construct a science of the infinite; others went on in the way he
opened, but they soon ran foul of strange contradictions. These
antinomies are already numerous, but the most celebrated are:

1. The Burali-Forti antinomy;

2. The Zermelo-König antinomy;

3. The Richard antinomy.

Cantor proved that the ordinal numbers (the question is of transfinite
ordinal numbers, a new notion introduced by him) can be ranged in a
linear series; that is to say that of two unequal ordinals one is always
less than the other. Burali-Forti proves the contrary; and in fact he
says in substance that if one could range _all_ the ordinals in a linear
series, this series would define an ordinal greater than _all_ the
others; we could afterwards adjoin 1 and would obtain again an ordinal
which would be _still greater_, and this is contradictory.

We shall return later to the Zermelo-König antinomy which is of a
slightly different nature. The Richard antinomy[15] is as follows:
Consider all the decimal numbers definable by a finite number of words;
these decimal numbers form an aggregate _E_, and it is easy to see that
this aggregate is countable, that is to say we can _number_ the
different decimal numbers of this assemblage from 1 to infinity. Suppose
the numbering effected, and define a number _N_ as follows: If the _n_th
decimal of the _n_th number of the assemblage _E_ is

  0, 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6, 7, 8, 9

the _n_th decimal of _N_ shall be:

  1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6, 7, 8, 1, 1

  [15] _Revue générale des sciences_, June 30, 1905.

As we see, _N_ is not equal to the _n_th number of _E_, and as _n_ is
arbitrary, _N_ does not appertain to _E_ and yet _N_ should belong to
this assemblage since we have defined it with a finite number of words.

We shall later see that M. Richard has himself given with much sagacity
the explanation of his paradox and that this extends, _mutatis
mutandis_, to the other like paradoxes. Again, Russell cites another
quite amusing paradox: _What is the least whole number which can not be
defined by a phrase composed of less than a hundred English words_?

This number exists; and in fact the numbers capable of being defined by
a like phrase are evidently finite in number since the words of the
English language are not infinite in number. Therefore among them will
be one less than all the others. And, on the other hand, this number
does not exist, because its definition implies contradiction. This
number, in fact, is defined by the phrase in italics which is composed
of less than a hundred English words; and by definition this number
should not be capable of definition by a like phrase.


VI

_Zigzag Theory and No-class Theory_

What is Mr. Russell's attitude in presence of these contradictions?
After having analyzed those of which we have just spoken, and cited
still others, after having given them a form recalling Epimenides, he
does not hesitate to conclude: "A propositional function of one
variable does not always determine a class." A propositional function
(that is to say a definition) does not always determine a class. A
'propositional function' or 'norm' may be 'non-predicative.' And this
does not mean that these non-predicative propositions determine an empty
class, a null class; this does not mean that there is no value of x
satisfying the definition and capable of being one of the elements of
the class. The elements exist, but they have no right to unite in a
syndicate to form a class.

But this is only the beginning and it is needful to know how to
recognize whether a definition is or is not predicative. To solve this
problem Russell hesitates between three theories which he calls

A. The zigzag theory;

B. The theory of limitation of size;

C. The no-class theory.

According to the zigzag theory "definitions (propositional functions)
determine a class when they are very simple and cease to do so only when
they are complicated and obscure." Who, now, is to decide whether a
definition may be regarded as simple enough to be acceptable? To this
question there is no answer, if it be not the loyal avowal of a complete
inability: "The rules which enable us to recognize whether these
definitions are predicative would be extremely complicated and can not
commend themselves by any plausible reason. This is a fault which might
be remedied by greater ingenuity or by using distinctions not yet
pointed out. But hitherto in seeking these rules, I have not been able
to find any other directing principle than the absence of
contradiction."

This theory therefore remains very obscure; in this night a single
light--the word zigzag. What Russell calls the 'zigzaginess' is
doubtless the particular characteristic which distinguishes the argument
of Epimenides.

According to the theory of limitation of size, a class would cease to
have the right to exist if it were too extended. Perhaps it might be
infinite, but it should not be too much so. But we always meet again the
same difficulty; at what precise moment does it begin to be too much
so? Of course this difficulty is not solved and Russell passes on to the
third theory.

In the no-classes theory it is forbidden to speak the word 'class' and
this word must be replaced by various periphrases. What a change for
logistic which talks only of classes and classes of classes! It becomes
necessary to remake the whole of logistic. Imagine how a page of
logistic would look upon suppressing all the propositions where it is a
question of class. There would only be some scattered survivors in the
midst of a blank page. _Apparent rari nantes in gurgite vasto._

Be that as it may, we see how Russell hesitates and the modifications to
which he submits the fundamental principles he has hitherto adopted.
Criteria are needed to decide whether a definition is too complex or too
extended, and these criteria can only be justified by an appeal to
intuition.

It is toward the no-classes theory that Russell finally inclines. Be
that as it may, logistic is to be remade and it is not clear how much of
it can be saved. Needless to add that Cantorism and logistic are alone
under consideration; real mathematics, that which is good for something,
may continue to develop in accordance with its own principles without
bothering about the storms which rage outside it, and go on step by step
with its usual conquests which are final and which it never has to
abandon.


VII

_The True Solution_

What choice ought we to make among these different theories? It seems to
me that the solution is contained in a letter of M. Richard of which I
have spoken above, to be found in the _Revue générale des sciences_ of
June 30, 1905. After having set forth the antinomy we have called
Richard's antinomy, he gives its explanation. Recall what has already
been said of this antinomy. _E_ is the aggregate of _all_ the numbers
definable by a finite number of words, _without introducing the notion
of the aggregate E itself_. Else the definition of _E_ would contain a
vicious circle; we must not define _E_ by the aggregate _E_ itself.

Now we have defined _N_ with a finite number of words, it is true, but
with the aid of the notion of the aggregate _E_. And this is why _N_ is
not part of _E_. In the example selected by M. Richard, the conclusion
presents itself with complete evidence and the evidence will appear
still stronger on consulting the text of the letter itself. But the same
explanation holds good for the other antinomies, as is easily verified.
Thus _the definitions which should be regarded as not predicative are
those which contain a vicious circle_. And the preceding examples
sufficiently show what I mean by that. Is it this which Russell calls
the 'zigzaginess'? I put the question without answering it.


VIII

_The Demonstrations of the Principle of Induction_

Let us now examine the pretended demonstrations of the principle of
induction and in particular those of Whitehead and of Burali-Forti.

We shall speak of Whitehead's first, and take advantage of certain new
terms happily introduced by Russell in his recent memoir. Call
_recurrent class_ every class containing zero, and containing _n_ + 1 if
it contains _n_. Call _inductive number_ every number which is a part of
_all_ the recurrent classes. Upon what condition will this latter
definition, which plays an essential rôle in Whitehead's proof, be
'predicative' and consequently acceptable?

In accordance with what has been said, it is necessary to understand by
_all_ the recurrent classes, all those in whose definition the notion of
inductive number does not enter. Else we fall again upon the vicious
circle which has engendered the antinomies.

Now _Whitehead has not taken this precaution_. Whitehead's reasoning is
therefore fallacious; it is the same which led to the antinomies. It was
illegitimate when it gave false results; it remains illegitimate when by
chance it leads to a true result.

A definition containing a vicious circle defines nothing. It is of no
use to say, we are sure, whatever meaning we may give to our definition,
zero at least belongs to the class of inductive numbers; it is not a
question of knowing whether this class is void, but whether it can be
rigorously deliminated. A 'non-predicative' class is not an empty
class, it is a class whose boundary is undetermined. Needless to add
that this particular objection leaves in force the general objections
applicable to all the demonstrations.


IX

Burali-Forti has given another demonstration.[16] But he is obliged to
assume two postulates: First, there always exists at least one infinite
class. The second is thus expressed:

  u[epsilon]K(K - [iota][Lambda]) · [inverted c] · u < v'u.

The first postulate is not more evident than the principle to be proved.
The second not only is not evident, but it is false, as Whitehead has
shown; as moreover any recruit would see at the first glance, if the
axiom had been stated in intelligible language, since it means that the
number of combinations which can be formed with several objects is less
than the number of these objects.

  [16] In his article 'Le classi finite,' _Atti di Torino_, Vol. XXXII.


X

_Zermelo's Assumption_

A famous demonstration by Zermelo rests upon the following assumption:
In any aggregate (or the same in each aggregate of an assemblage of
aggregates) we can always choose _at random_ an element (even if this
assemblage of aggregates should contain an infinity of aggregates). This
assumption had been applied a thousand times without being stated, but,
once stated, it aroused doubts. Some mathematicians, for instance
M. Borel, resolutely reject it; others admire it. Let us see what,
according to his last article, Russell thinks of it. He does not speak
out, but his reflections are very suggestive.

And first a picturesque example: Suppose we have as many pairs of shoes
as there are whole numbers, and so that we can number _the pairs_ from
one to infinity, how many shoes shall we have? Will the number of shoes
be equal to the number of pairs? Yes, if in each pair the right shoe is
distinguishable from the left; it will in fact suffice to give the
number 2_n_ - 1 to the right shoe of the _n_th pair, and the number 2_n_
to the left shoe of the _n_th pair. No, if the right shoe is just like
the left, because a similar operation would become impossible--unless we
admit Zermelo's assumption, since then we could choose _at random_ in
each pair the shoe to be regarded as the right.


XI

_Conclusions_

A demonstration truly founded upon the principles of analytic logic will
be composed of a series of propositions. Some, serving as premises, will
be identities or definitions; the others will be deduced from the
premises step by step. But though the bond between each proposition and
the following is immediately evident, it will not at first sight appear
how we get from the first to the last, which we may be tempted to regard
as a new truth. But if we replace successively the different expressions
therein by their definition and if this operation be carried as far as
possible, there will finally remain only identities, so that all will
reduce to an immense tautology. Logic therefore remains sterile unless
made fruitful by intuition.

This I wrote long ago; logistic professes the contrary and thinks it has
proved it by actually proving new truths. By what mechanism? Why in
applying to their reasonings the procedure just described--namely,
replacing the terms defined by their definitions--do we not see them
dissolve into identities like ordinary reasonings? It is because this
procedure is not applicable to them. And why? Because their definitions
are not predicative and present this sort of hidden vicious circle which
I have pointed out above; non-predicative definitions can not be
substituted for the terms defined. Under these conditions _logistic is
not sterile, it engenders antinomies_.

It is the belief in the existence of the actual infinite which has given
birth to those non-predicative definitions. Let me explain. In these
definitions the word 'all' figures, as is seen in the examples cited
above. The word 'all' has a very precise meaning when it is a question
of a finite number of objects; to have another one, when the objects are
infinite in number, would require there being an actual (given complete)
infinity. Otherwise _all_ these objects could not be conceived as
postulated anteriorly to their definition, and then if the definition of
a notion _N_ depends upon _all_ the objects _A_, it may be infected with
a vicious circle, if among the objects _A_ are some indefinable without
the intervention of the notion _N_ itself.

The rules of formal logic express simply the properties of all possible
classifications. But for them to be applicable it is necessary that
these classifications be immutable and that we have no need to modify
them in the course of the reasoning. If we have to classify only a
finite number of objects, it is easy to keep our classifications without
change. If the objects are _indefinite_ in number, that is to say if one
is constantly exposed to seeing new and unforeseen objects arise, it may
happen that the appearance of a new object may require the
classification to be modified, and thus it is we are exposed to
antinomies. _There is no actual (given complete) infinity._ The
Cantorians have forgotten this, and they have fallen into contradiction.
It is true that Cantorism has been of service, but this was when applied
to a real problem whose terms were precisely defined, and then we could
advance without fear.

Logistic also forgot it, like the Cantorians, and encountered the same
difficulties. But the question is to know whether they went this way by
accident or whether it was a necessity for them. For me, the question is
not doubtful; belief in an actual infinity is essential in the Russell
logic. It is just this which distinguishes it from the Hilbert logic.
Hilbert takes the view-point of extension, precisely in order to avoid
the Cantorian antinomies. Russell takes the view-point of comprehension.
Consequently for him the genus is anterior to the species, and the
_summum genus_ is anterior to all. That would not be inconvenient if the
_summum genus_ was finite; but if it is infinite, it is necessary to
postulate the infinite, that is to say to regard the infinite as actual
(given complete). And we have not only infinite classes; when we pass
from the genus to the species in restricting the concept by new
conditions, these conditions are still infinite in number. Because they
express generally that the envisaged object presents such or such a
relation with all the objects of an infinite class.

But that is ancient history. Russell has perceived the peril and takes
counsel. He is about to change everything, and, what is easily
understood, he is preparing not only to introduce new principles which
shall allow of operations formerly forbidden, but he is preparing to
forbid operations he formerly thought legitimate. Not content to adore
what he burned, he is about to burn what he adored, which is more
serious. He does not add a new wing to the building, he saps its
foundation.

The old logistic is dead, so much so that already the zigzag theory and
the no-classes theory are disputing over the succession. To judge of the
new, we shall await its coming.



BOOK III


THE NEW MECHANICS



CHAPTER I

MECHANICS AND RADIUM


I

_Introduction_

The general principles of Dynamics, which have, since Newton, served as
foundation for physical science, and which appeared immovable, are they
on the point of being abandoned or at least profoundly modified? This is
what many people have been asking themselves for some years. According
to them, the discovery of radium has overturned the scientific dogmas we
believed the most solid: on the one hand, the impossibility of the
transmutation of metals; on the other hand, the fundamental postulates
of mechanics.

Perhaps one is too hasty in considering these novelties as finally
established, and breaking our idols of yesterday; perhaps it would be
proper, before taking sides, to await experiments more numerous and more
convincing. None the less is it necessary, from to-day, to know the new
doctrines and the arguments, already very weighty, upon which they rest.

In few words let us first recall in what those principles consist:

_A._ The motion of a material point isolated and apart from all exterior
force is straight and uniform; this is the principle of inertia: without
force no acceleration;

_B._ The acceleration of a moving point has the same direction as the
resultant of all the forces to which it is subjected; it is equal to the
quotient of this resultant by a coefficient called _mass_ of the moving
point.

The mass of a moving point, so defined, is a constant; it does not
depend upon the velocity acquired by this point; it is the same whether
the force, being parallel to this velocity, tends only to accelerate or
to retard the motion of the point, or whether, on the contrary, being
perpendicular to this velocity, it tends to make this motion deviate
toward the right, or the left, that is to say to _curve_ the trajectory;

_C._ All the forces affecting a material point come from the action of
other material points; they depend only upon the _relative_ positions
and velocities of these different material points.

Combining the two principles _B_ and _C_, we reach the _principle of
relative motion_, in virtue of which the laws of the motion of a system
are the same whether we refer this system to fixed axes, or to moving
axes animated by a straight and uniform motion of translation, so that
it is impossible to distinguish absolute motion from a relative motion
with reference to such moving axes;

_D._ If a material point _A_ acts upon another material point _B_, the
body _B_ reacts upon _A_, and these two actions are two equal and
directly opposite forces. This is _the principle of the equality of
action and reaction_, or, more briefly, the _principle of reaction_.

Astronomic observations and the most ordinary physical phenomena seem to
have given of these principles a confirmation complete, constant and
very precise. This is true, it is now said, but it is because we have
never operated with any but very small velocities; Mercury, for example,
the fastest of the planets, goes scarcely 100 kilometers a second. Would
this planet act the same if it went a thousand times faster? We see
there is yet no need to worry; whatever may be the progress of
automobilism, it will be long before we must give up applying to our
machines the classic principles of dynamics.

How then have we come to make actual speeds a thousand times greater
than that of Mercury, equal, for instance, to a tenth or a third of the
velocity of light, or approaching still more closely to that velocity?
It is by aid of the cathode rays and the rays from radium.

We know that radium emits three kinds of rays, designated by the three
Greek letters [alpha], [beta], [gamma]; in what follows, unless the
contrary be expressly stated, it will always be a question of the [beta]
rays, which are analogous to the cathode rays.

After the discovery of the cathode rays two theories appeared. Crookes
attributed the phenomena to a veritable molecular bombardment; Hertz, to
special undulations of the ether. This was a renewal of the debate which
divided physicists a century ago about light; Crookes took up the
emission theory, abandoned for light; Hertz held to the undulatory
theory. The facts seem to decide in favor of Crookes.

It has been recognized, in the first place, that the cathode rays carry
with them a negative electric charge; they are deviated by a magnetic
field and by an electric field; and these deviations are precisely such
as these same fields would produce upon projectiles animated by a very
high velocity and strongly charged with electricity. These two
deviations depend upon two quantities: one the velocity, the other the
relation of the electric charge of the projectile to its mass; we cannot
know the absolute value of this mass, nor that of the charge, but only
their relation; in fact, it is clear that if we double at the same time
the charge and the mass, without changing the velocity, we shall double
the force which tends to deviate the projectile, but, as its mass is
also doubled, the acceleration and deviation observable will not be
changed. The observation of the two deviations will give us therefore
two equations to determine these two unknowns. We find a velocity of
from 10,000 to 30,000 kilometers a second; as to the ratio of the charge
to the mass, it is very great. We may compare it to the corresponding
ratio in regard to the hydrogen ion in electrolysis; we then find that a
cathodic projectile carries about a thousand times more electricity than
an equal mass of hydrogen would carry in an electrolyte.

To confirm these views, we need a direct measurement of this velocity to
compare with the velocity so calculated. Old experiments of J. J.
Thomson had given results more than a hundred times too small; but they
were exposed to certain causes of error. The question was taken up again
by Wiechert in an arrangement where the Hertzian oscillations were
utilized; results were found agreeing with the theory, at least as to
order of magnitude; it would be of great interest to repeat these
experiments. However that may be, the theory of undulations appears
powerless to account for this complex of facts.

The same calculations made with reference to the [beta] rays of radium
have given velocities still greater: 100,000 or 200,000 kilometers or
more yet. These velocities greatly surpass all those we know. It is true
that light has long been known to go 300,000 kilometers a second; but it
is not a carrying of matter, while, if we adopt the emission theory for
the cathode rays, there would be material molecules really impelled at
the velocities in question, and it is proper to investigate whether the
ordinary laws of mechanics are still applicable to them.


II

_Mass Longitudinal and Mass Transversal_

We know that electric currents produce the phenomena of induction, in
particular _self-induction_. When a current increases, there develops an
electromotive force of self-induction which tends to oppose the current;
on the contrary, when the current decreases, the electromotive force of
self-induction tends to maintain the current. The self-induction
therefore opposes every variation of the intensity of the current, just
as in mechanics the inertia of a body opposes every variation of its
velocity.

_Self-induction is a veritable inertia._ Everything happens as if the
current could not establish itself without putting in motion the
surrounding ether and as if the inertia of this ether tended, in
consequence, to keep constant the intensity of this current. It would be
requisite to overcome this inertia to establish the current, it would be
necessary to overcome it again to make the current cease.

A cathode ray, which is a rain of projectiles charged with negative
electricity, may be likened to a current; doubtless this current
differs, at first sight at least, from the currents of ordinary
conduction, where the matter does not move and where the electricity
circulates through the matter. This is a _current of convection_, where
the electricity, attached to a material vehicle, is carried along by the
motion of this vehicle. But Rowland has proved that currents of
convection produce the same magnetic effects as currents of conduction;
they should produce also the same effects of induction. First, if this
were not so, the principle of the conservation of energy would be
violated; besides, Crémieu and Pender have employed a method putting in
evidence _directly_ these effects of induction.

If the velocity of a cathode corpuscle varies, the intensity of the
corresponding current will likewise vary; and there will develop effects
of self-induction which will tend to oppose this variation. These
corpuscles should therefore possess a double inertia: first their own
proper inertia, and then the apparent inertia, due to self-induction,
which produces the same effects. They will therefore have a total
apparent mass, composed of their real mass and of a fictitious mass of
electromagnetic origin. Calculation shows that this fictitious mass
varies with the velocity, and that the force of inertia of
self-induction is not the same when the velocity of the projectile
accelerates or slackens, or when it is deviated; therefore so it is with
the force of the total apparent inertia.

The total apparent mass is therefore not the same when the real force
applied to the corpuscle is parallel to its velocity and tends to
accelerate the motion as when it is perpendicular to this velocity and
tends to make the direction vary. It is necessary therefore to
distinguish the _total longitudinal mass_ from the _total transversal
mass_. These two total masses depend, moreover, upon the velocity. This
follows from the theoretical work of Abraham.

In the measurements of which we speak in the preceding section, what is
it we determine in measuring the two deviations? It is the velocity on
the one hand, and on the other hand the ratio of the charge to the
_total transversal mass_. How, under these conditions, can we make out
in this total mass the part of the real mass and that of the fictitious
electromagnetic mass? If we had only the cathode rays properly so
called, it could not be dreamed of; but happily we have the rays of
radium which, as we have seen, are notably swifter. These rays are not
all identical and do not behave in the same way under the action of an
electric field and a magnetic field. It is found that the electric
deviation is a function of the magnetic deviation, and we are able, by
receiving on a sensitive plate radium rays which have been subjected to
the action of the two fields, to photograph the curve which represents
the relation between these two deviations. This is what Kaufmann has
done, deducing from it the relation between the velocity and the ratio
of the charge to the total apparent mass, a ratio we shall call
[epsilon].

One might suppose there are several species of rays, each characterized
by a fixed velocity, by a fixed charge and by a fixed mass. But this
hypothesis is improbable; why, in fact, would all the corpuscles of the
same mass take always the same velocity? It is more natural to suppose
that the charge as well as the _real_ mass are the same for all the
projectiles, and that these differ only by their velocity. If the ratio
[epsilon] is a function of the velocity, this is not because the real
mass varies with this velocity; but, since the fictitious
electromagnetic mass depends upon this velocity, the total apparent
mass, alone observable, must depend upon it, though the real mass does
not depend upon it and may be constant.

The calculations of Abraham let us know the law according to which the
_fictitious_ mass varies as a function of the velocity; Kaufmann's
experiment lets us know the law of variation of the _total_ mass.

The comparison of these two laws will enable us therefore to determine
the ratio of the real mass to the total mass.

Such is the method Kaufmann used to determine this ratio. The result is
highly surprising: _the real mass is naught_.

This has led to conceptions wholly unexpected. What had only been proved
for cathode corpuscles was extended to all bodies. What we call mass
would be only semblance; all inertia would be of electromagnetic origin.
But then mass would no longer be constant, it would augment with the
velocity; sensibly constant for velocities up to 1,000 kilometers a
second, it then would increase and would become infinite for the
velocity of light. The transversal mass would no longer be equal to the
longitudinal: they would only be nearly equal if the velocity is not too
great. The principle _B_ of mechanics would no longer be true.


III

_The Canal Rays_

At the point where we now are, this conclusion might seem premature. Can
one apply to all matter what has been proved only for such light
corpuscles, which are a mere emanation of matter and perhaps not true
matter? But before entering upon this question, a word must be said of
another sort of rays. I refer to the _canal rays_, the _Kanalstrahlen_
of Goldstein.

The cathode, together with the cathode rays charged with negative
electricity, emits canal rays charged with positive electricity. In
general, these canal rays not being repelled by the cathode, are
confined to the immediate neighborhood of this cathode, where they
constitute the `chamois cushion,' not very easy to perceive; but, if the
cathode is pierced with holes and if it almost completely blocks up the
tube, the canal rays spread _back_ of the cathode, in the direction
opposite to that of the cathode rays, and it becomes possible to study
them. It is thus that it has been possible to show their positive charge
and to show that the magnetic and electric deviations still exist, as
for the cathode rays, but are much feebler.

Radium likewise emits rays analogous to the canal rays, and relatively
very absorbable, called [alpha] rays.

We can, as for the cathode rays, measure the two deviations and thence
deduce the velocity and the ratio [epsilon]. The results are less
constant than for the cathode rays, but the velocity is less, as well as
the ratio [epsilon]; the positive corpuscles are less charged than the
negative; or if, which is more natural, we suppose the charges equal and
of opposite sign, the positive corpuscles are much the larger. These
corpuscles, charged the ones positively, the others negatively, have
been called _electrons_.


IV

_The Theory of Lorentz_

But the electrons do not merely show us their existence in these rays
where they are endowed with enormous velocities. We shall see them in
very different rôles, and it is they that account for the principal
phenomena of optics and electricity. The brilliant synthesis about to be
noticed is due to Lorentz.

Matter is formed solely of electrons carrying enormous charges, and, if
it seems to us neutral, this is because the charges of opposite sign of
these electrons compensate each other. We may imagine, for example, a
sort of solar system formed of a great positive electron, around which
gravitate numerous little planets, the negative electrons, attracted by
the electricity of opposite name which charges the central electron. The
negative charges of these planets would balance the positive charge of
this sun, so that the algebraic sum of all these charges would be
naught.

All these electrons swim in the ether. The ether is everywhere
identically the same, and perturbations in it are propagated according
to the same laws as light or the Hertzian oscillations _in vacuo_. There
is nothing but electrons and ether. When a luminous wave enters a part
of the ether where electrons are numerous, these electrons are put in
motion under the influence of the perturbation of the ether, and they
then react upon the ether. So would be explained refraction, dispersion,
double refraction and absorption. Just so, if for any cause an electron
be put in motion, it would trouble the ether around it and would give
rise to luminous waves, and this would explain the emission of light by
incandescent bodies.

In certain bodies, the metals for example, we should have fixed
electrons, between which would circulate moving electrons enjoying
perfect liberty, save that of going out from the metallic body and
breaking the surface which separates it from the exterior void or from
the air, or from any other non-metallic body.

These movable electrons behave then, within the metallic body, as do,
according to the kinetic theory of gases, the molecules of a gas within
the vase where this gas is confined. But, under the influence of a
difference of potential, the negative movable electrons would tend to go
all to one side, and the positive movable electrons to the other. This
is what would produce electric currents, and _this is why these bodies
would be conductors_. On the other hand, the velocities of our electrons
would be the greater the higher the temperature, if we accept the
assimilation with the kinetic theory of gases. When one of these movable
electrons encounters the surface of the metallic body, whose boundary it
can not pass, it is reflected like a billiard ball which has hit the
cushion, and its velocity undergoes a sudden change of direction. But
when an electron changes direction, as we shall see further on, it
becomes the source of a luminous wave, and this is why hot metals are
incandescent.

In other bodies, the dielectrics and the transparent bodies, the movable
electrons enjoy much less freedom. They remain as if attached to fixed
electrons which attract them. The farther they go away from them the
greater becomes this attraction and tends to pull them back. They
therefore can make only small excursions; they can no longer circulate,
but only oscillate about their mean position. This is why these bodies
would not be conductors; moreover they would most often be transparent,
and they would be refractive, since the luminous vibrations would be
communicated to the movable electrons, susceptible of oscillation, and
thence a perturbation would result.

I can not here give the details of the calculations; I confine myself to
saying that this theory accounts for all the known facts, and has
predicted new ones, such as the Zeeman effect.


V

_Mechanical Consequences_

We now may face two hypotheses:

1º The positive electrons have a real mass, much greater than their
fictitious electromagnetic mass; the negative electrons alone lack real
mass. We might even suppose that apart from electrons of the two signs,
there are neutral atoms which have only their real mass. In this case,
mechanics is not affected; there is no need of touching its laws; the
real mass is constant; simply, motions are deranged by the effects of
self-induction, as has always been known; moreover, these perturbations
are almost negligible, except for the negative electrons which, not
having real mass, are not true matter.

2º But there is another point of view; we may suppose there are no
neutral atoms, and the positive electrons lack real mass just as the
negative electrons. But then, real mass vanishing, either the word
_mass_ will no longer have any meaning, or else it must designate the
fictitious electromagnetic mass; in this case, mass will no longer be
constant, the transversal _mass_ will no longer be equal to the
longitudinal, the principles of mechanics will be overthrown.

First a word of explanation. We have said that, for the same charge, the
_total_ mass of a positive electron is much greater than that of a
negative. And then it is natural to think that this difference is
explained by the positive electron having, besides its fictitious mass,
a considerable real mass; which takes us back to the first hypothesis.
But we may just as well suppose that the real mass is null for these as
for the others, but that the fictitious mass of the positive electron is
much the greater since this electron is much the smaller. I say
advisedly: much the smaller. And, in fact, in this hypothesis inertia is
exclusively electromagnetic in origin; it reduces itself to the inertia
of the ether; the electrons are no longer anything by themselves; they
are solely holes in the ether and around which the ether moves; the
smaller these holes are, the more will there be of ether, the greater,
consequently, will be the inertia of the ether.

How shall we decide between these two hypotheses? By operating upon the
canal rays as Kaufmann did upon the [beta] rays? This is impossible; the
velocity of these rays is much too slight. Should each therefore decide
according to his temperament, the conservatives going to one side and
the lovers of the new to the other? Perhaps, but, to fully understand
the arguments of the innovators, other considerations must come in.



CHAPTER II

MECHANICS AND OPTICS


I

_Aberration_

You know in what the phenomenon of aberration, discovered by Bradley,
consists. The light issuing from a star takes a certain time to go
through a telescope; during this time, the telescope, carried along by
the motion of the earth, is displaced. If therefore the telescope were
pointed in the _true_ direction of the star, the image would be formed
at the point occupied by the crossing of the threads of the network when
the light has reached the objective; and this crossing would no longer
be at this same point when the light reached the plane of the network.
We would therefore be led to mis-point the telescope to bring the image
upon the crossing of the threads. Thence results that the astronomer
will not point the telescope in the direction of the absolute velocity
of the light, that is to say toward the true position of the star, but
just in the direction of the relative velocity of the light with
reference to the earth, that is to say toward what is called the
apparent position of the star.

The velocity of light is known; we might therefore suppose that we have
the means of calculating the _absolute_ velocity of the earth. (I shall
soon explain my use here of the word absolute.) Nothing of the sort; we
indeed know the apparent position of the star we observe; but we do not
know its true position; we know the velocity of the light only in
magnitude and not in direction.

If therefore the absolute velocity of the earth were straight and
uniform, we should never have suspected the phenomenon of aberration;
but it is variable; it is composed of two parts: the velocity of the
solar system, which is straight and uniform; the velocity of the earth
with reference to the sun, which is variable. If the velocity of the
solar system, that is to say if the constant part existed alone, the
observed direction would be invariable. This position that one would
thus observe is called the _mean_ apparent position of the star.

Taking account now at the same time of the two parts of the velocity of
the earth, we shall have the actual apparent position, which describes a
little ellipse around the mean apparent position, and it is this ellipse
that we observe.

Neglecting very small quantities, we shall see that the dimensions of
this ellipse depend only upon the ratio of the velocity of the earth
with reference to the sun to the velocity of light, so that the relative
velocity of the earth with regard to the sun has alone come in.

But wait! This result is not exact, it is only approximate; let us push
the approximation a little farther. The dimensions of the ellipse will
depend then upon the absolute velocity of the earth. Let us compare the
major axes of the ellipse for the different stars: we shall have,
theoretically at least, the means of determining this absolute velocity.

That would be perhaps less shocking than it at first seems; it is a
question, in fact, not of the velocity with reference to an absolute
void, but of the velocity with regard to the ether, which is taken _by
definition_ as being absolutely at rest.

Besides, this method is purely theoretical. In fact, the aberration is
very small; the possible variations of the ellipse of aberration are
much smaller yet, and, if we consider the aberration as of the first
order, they should therefore be regarded as of the second order: about a
millionth of a second; they are absolutely inappreciable for our
instruments. We shall finally see, further on, why the preceding theory
should be rejected, and why we could not determine this absolute
velocity even if our instruments were ten thousand times more precise!

One might imagine some other means, and in fact, so one has. The
velocity of light is not the same in water as in air; could we not
compare the two apparent positions of a star seen through a telescope
first full of air, then full of water? The results have been negative;
the apparent laws of reflection and refraction are not altered by the
motion of the earth. This phenomenon is capable of two explanations:

1º It might be supposed that the ether is not at rest, but that it is
carried along by the body in motion. It would then not be astonishing
that the phenomena of refraction are not altered by the motion of the
earth, since all, prisms, telescopes and ether, are carried along
together in the same translation. As to the aberration itself, it would
be explained by a sort of refraction happening at the surface of
separation of the ether at rest in the interstellar spaces and the ether
carried along by the motion of the earth. It is upon this hypothesis
(bodily carrying along of the ether) that is founded the _theory of
Hertz_ on the electrodynamics of moving bodies.

2º Fresnel, on the contrary, supposes that the ether is at absolute rest
in the void, at rest almost absolute in the air, whatever be the
velocity of this air, and that it is partially carried along by
refractive media. Lorentz has given to this theory a more satisfactory
form. For him, the ether is at rest, only the electrons are in motion;
in the void, where it is only a question of the ether, in the air, where
this is almost the case, the carrying along is null or almost null; in
refractive media, where perturbation is produced at the same time by
vibrations of the ether and those of electrons put in swing by the
agitation of the ether, the undulations are _partially_ carried along.

To decide between the two hypotheses, we have Fizeau's experiment,
comparing by measurements of the fringes of interference, the velocity
of light in air at rest or in motion. These experiments have confirmed
Fresnel's hypothesis of partial carrying along. They have been repeated
with the same result by Michelson. _The theory of Hertz must therefore
be rejected._


II

_The Principle of Relativity_

But if the ether is not carried along by the motion of the earth, is it
possible to show, by means of optical phenomena, the absolute velocity
of the earth, or rather its velocity with respect to the unmoving ether?
Experiment has answered negatively, and yet the experimental procedures
have been varied in all possible ways. Whatever be the means employed
there will never be disclosed anything but relative velocities; I mean
the velocities of certain material bodies with reference to other
material bodies. In fact, if the source of light and the apparatus of
observation are on the earth and participate in its motion, the
experimental results have always been the same, whatever be the
orientation of the apparatus with reference to the orbital motion of the
earth. If astronomic aberration happens, it is because the source, a
star, is in motion with reference to the observer.

The hypotheses so far made perfectly account for this general result,
_if we neglect very small quantities of the order of the square of the
aberration_. The explanation rests upon the notion of _local time_,
introduced by Lorentz, which I shall try to make clear. Suppose two
observers, placed one at _A_, the other at _B_, and wishing to set their
watches by means of optical signals. They agree that _B_ shall send a
signal to _A_ when his watch marks an hour determined upon, and _A_ is
to put his watch to that hour the moment he sees the signal. If this
alone were done, there would be a systematic error, because as the light
takes a certain time _t_ to go from _B_ to _A_, _A_'s watch would be
behind _B_'s the time _t_. This error is easily corrected. It suffices
to cross the signals. _A_ in turn must signal _B_, and, after this new
adjustment, _B_'s watch will be behind _A_'s the time _t_. Then it will
be sufficient to take the arithmetic mean of the two adjustments.

But this way of doing supposes that light takes the same time to go from
_A_ to _B_ as to return from _B_ to _A_. That is true if the observers
are motionless; it is no longer so if they are carried along in a common
translation, since then _A_, for example, will go to meet the light
coming from _B_, while _B_ will flee before the light coming from _A_.
If therefore the observers are borne along in a common translation and
if they do not suspect it, their adjustment will be defective; their
watches will not indicate the same time; each will show the _local time_
belonging to the point where it is.

The two observers will have no way of perceiving this, if the unmoving
ether can transmit to them only luminous signals all of the same
velocity, and if the other signals they might send are transmitted by
media carried along with them in their translation. The phenomenon each
observes will be too soon or too late; it would be seen at the same
instant only if the translation did not exist; but as it will be
observed with a watch that is wrong, this will not be perceived and the
appearances will not be altered.

It results from this that the compensation is easy to explain so long as
we neglect the square of the aberration, and for a long time the
experiments were not sufficiently precise to warrant taking account of
it. But the day came when Michelson imagined a much more delicate
procedure: he made rays interfere which had traversed different courses,
after being reflected by mirrors; each of the paths approximating a
meter and the fringes of interference permitting the recognition of a
fraction of a thousandth of a millimeter, the square of the aberration
could no longer be neglected, and _yet the results were still negative_.
Therefore the theory required to be completed, and it has been by the
_Lorentz-Fitzgerald hypothesis_.

These two physicists suppose that all bodies carried along in a
translation undergo a contraction in the sense of this translation,
while their dimensions perpendicular to this translation remain
unchanged. _This contraction is the same for all bodies_; moreover, it
is very slight, about one two-hundred-millionth for a velocity such as
that of the earth. Furthermore our measuring instruments could not
disclose it, even if they were much more precise; our measuring rods in
fact undergo the same contraction as the objects to be measured. If the
meter exactly fits when applied to a body, if we point the body and
consequently the meter in the sense of the motion of the earth, it will
not cease to exactly fit in another orientation, and that although the
body and the meter have changed in length as well as orientation, and
precisely because the change is the same for one as for the other. But
it is quite different if we measure a length, not now with a meter, but
by the time taken by light to pass along it, and this is just what
Michelson has done.

A body, spherical when at rest, will take thus the form of a flattened
ellipsoid of revolution when in motion; but the observer will always
think it spherical, since he himself has undergone an analogous
deformation, as also all the objects serving as points of reference. On
the contrary, the surfaces of the waves of light, remaining rigorously
spherical, will seem to him elongated ellipsoids.

What happens then? Suppose an observer and a source of light carried
along together in the translation: the wave surfaces emanating from the
source will be spheres having as centers the successive positions of the
source; the distance from this center to the actual position of the
source will be proportional to the time elapsed after the emission, that
is to say to the radius of the sphere. All these spheres are therefore
homothetic one to the other, with relation to the actual position _S_ of
the source. But, for our observer, because of the contraction, all these
spheres will seem elongated ellipsoids, and all these ellipsoids will
moreover be homothetic, with reference to the point _S_; the
excentricity of all these ellipsoids is the same and depends solely upon
the velocity of the earth. _We shall so select the law of contraction
that the point S may be at the focus of the meridian section of the
ellipsoid._

This time the compensation is _rigorous_, and this it is which explains
Michelson's experiment.

I have said above that, according to the ordinary theories, observations
of the astronomic aberration would give us the absolute velocity of the
earth, if our instruments were a thousand times more precise. I must
modify this statement. Yes, the observed angles would be modified by the
effect of this absolute velocity, but the graduated circles we use to
measure the angles would be deformed by the translation: they would
become ellipses; thence would result an error in regard to the angle
measured, and _this second error would exactly compensate the first_.

This Lorentz-Fitzgerald hypothesis seems at first very extraordinary;
all we can say for the moment, in its favor, is that it is only the
immediate translation of Michelson's experimental result, if we _define_
lengths by the time taken by light to run along them.

However that may be, it is impossible to escape the impression that the
principle of relativity is a general law of nature, that one will never
be able by any imaginable means to show any but relative velocities, and
I mean by that not only the velocities of bodies with reference to the
ether, but the velocities of bodies with regard to one another. Too many
different experiments have given concordant results for us not to feel
tempted to attribute to this principle of relativity a value comparable
to that, for example, of the principle of equivalence. In any case, it
is proper to see to what consequences this way of looking at things
would lead us and then to submit these consequences to the control of
experiment.


III

_The Principle of Reaction_

Let us see what the principle of the equality of action and reaction
becomes in the theory of Lorentz. Consider an electron _A_ which for any
cause begins to move; it produces a perturbation in the ether; at the
end of a certain time, this perturbation reaches another electron _B_,
which will be disturbed from its position of equilibrium. In these
conditions there can not be equality between action and reaction, at
least if we do not consider the ether, but only the electrons, _which
alone are observable_, since our matter is made of electrons.

In fact it is the electron _A_ which has disturbed the electron _B_;
even in case the electron _B_ should react upon _A_, this reaction could
be equal to the action, but in no case simultaneous, since the electron
_B_ can begin to move only after a certain time, necessary for the
propagation. Submitting the problem to a more exact calculation, we
reach the following result: Suppose a Hertz discharger placed at the
focus of a parabolic mirror to which it is mechanically attached; this
discharger emits electromagnetic waves, and the mirror reflects all
these waves in the same direction; the discharger therefore will radiate
energy in a determinate direction. Well, the calculation shows that _the
discharger recoils_ like a cannon which has shot out a projectile. In
the case of the cannon, the recoil is the natural result of the equality
of action and reaction. The cannon recoils because the projectile upon
which it has acted reacts upon it. But here it is no longer the same.
What has been sent out is no longer a material projectile: it is energy,
and energy has no mass: it has no counterpart. And, in place of a
discharger, we could have considered just simply a lamp with a reflector
concentrating its rays in a single direction.

It is true that, if the energy sent out from the discharger or from the
lamp meets a material object, this object receives a mechanical push as
if it had been hit by a real projectile, and this push will be equal to
the recoil of the discharger and of the lamp, if no energy has been lost
on the way and if the object absorbs the whole of the energy. Therefore
one is tempted to say that there still is compensation between the
action and the reaction. But this compensation, even should it be
complete, is always belated. It never happens if the light, after
leaving its source, wanders through interstellar spaces without ever
meeting a material body; it is incomplete, if the body it strikes is not
perfectly absorbent.

Are these mechanical actions too small to be measured, or are they
accessible to experiment? These actions are nothing other than those due
to the _Maxwell-Bartholi_ pressures; Maxwell had predicted these
pressures from calculations relative to electrostatics and magnetism;
Bartholi reached the same result by thermodynamic considerations.

This is how the _tails of comets_ are explained. Little particles detach
themselves from the nucleus of the comet; they are struck by the light
of the sun, which pushes them back as would a rain of projectiles coming
from the sun. The mass of these particles is so little that this
repulsion sweeps it away against the Newtonian attraction; so in moving
away from the sun they form the tails.

The direct experimental verification was not easy to obtain. The first
endeavor led to the construction of the _radiometer_. But this
instrument _turns backward_, in the sense opposite to the theoretic
sense, and the explanation of its rotation, since discovered, is wholly
different. At last success came, by making the vacuum more complete, on
the one hand, and on the other by not blackening one of the faces of the
paddles and directing a pencil of luminous rays upon one of the faces.
The radiometric effects and the other disturbing causes are eliminated
by a series of pains-taking precautions, and one obtains a deviation
which is very minute, but which is, it would seem, in conformity with
the theory.

The same effects of the Maxwell-Bartholi pressure are forecast likewise
by the theory of Hertz of which we have before spoken, and by that of
Lorentz. But there is a difference. Suppose that the energy, under the
form of light, for example, proceeds from a luminous source to any body
through a transparent medium. The Maxwell-Bartholi pressure will act,
not alone upon the source at the departure, and on the body lit up at
the arrival, but upon the matter of the transparent medium which it
traverses. At the moment when the luminous wave reaches a new region of
this medium, this pressure will push forward the matter there
distributed and will put it back when the wave leaves this region. So
that the recoil of the source has for counterpart the forward movement
of the transparent matter which is in contact with this source; a little
later, the recoil of this same matter has for counterpart the forward
movement of the transparent matter which lies a little further on, and
so on.

Only, is the compensation perfect? Is the action of the Maxwell-Bartholi
pressure upon the matter of the transparent medium equal to its reaction
upon the source, and that whatever be this matter? Or is this action by
so much the less as the medium is less refractive and more rarefied,
becoming null in the void?

If we admit the theory of Hertz, who regards matter as mechanically
bound to the ether, so that the ether may be entirely carried along by
matter, it would be necessary to answer yes to the first question and no
to the second.

There would then be perfect compensation, as required by the principle
of the equality of action and reaction, even in the least refractive
media, even in the air, even in the interplanetary void, where it would
suffice to suppose a residue of matter, however subtile. If on the
contrary we admit the theory of Lorentz, the compensation, always
imperfect, is insensible in the air and becomes null in the void.

But we have seen above that Fizeau's experiment does not permit of our
retaining the theory of Hertz; it is necessary therefore to adopt the
theory of Lorentz, and consequently _to renounce the principle of
reaction_.


IV

_Consequences of the Principle of Relativity_

We have seen above the reasons which impel us to regard the principle of
relativity as a general law of nature. Let us see to what consequences
this principle would lead, should it be regarded as finally
demonstrated.

First, it obliges us to generalize the hypothesis of Lorentz and
Fitzgerald on the contraction of all bodies in the sense of the
translation. In particular, we must extend this hypothesis to the
electrons themselves. Abraham considered these electrons as spherical
and indeformable; it will be necessary for us to admit that these
electrons, spherical when in repose, undergo the Lorentz contraction
when in motion and take then the form of flattened ellipsoids.

This deformation of the electrons will influence their mechanical
properties. In fact I have said that the displacement of these charged
electrons is a veritable current of convection and that their apparent
inertia is due to the self-induction of this current: exclusively as
concerns the negative electrons; exclusively or not, we do not yet know,
for the positive electrons. Well, the deformation of the electrons, a
deformation which depends upon their velocity, will modify the
distribution of the electricity upon their surface, consequently the
intensity of the convection current they produce, consequently the laws
according to which the self-induction of this current will vary as a
function of the velocity.

At this price, the compensation will be perfect and will conform to the
requirements of the principle of relativity, but only upon two
conditions:

1º That the positive electrons have no real mass, but only a fictitious
electromagnetic mass; or at least that their real mass, if it exists, is
not constant and varies with the velocity according to the same laws as
their fictitious mass;

2º That all forces are of electromagnetic origin, or at least that they
vary with the velocity according to the same laws as the forces of
electromagnetic origin.

It still is Lorentz who has made this remarkable synthesis; stop a
moment and see what follows therefrom. First, there is no more matter,
since the positive electrons no longer have real mass, or at least no
constant real mass. The present principles of our mechanics, founded
upon the constancy of mass, must therefore be modified. Again, an
electromagnetic explanation must be sought of all the known forces, in
particular of gravitation, or at least the law of gravitation must be so
modified that this force is altered by velocity in the same way as the
electromagnetic forces. We shall return to this point.

All that appears, at first sight, a little artificial. In particular,
this deformation of electrons seems quite hypothetical. But the thing
may be presented otherwise, so as to avoid putting this hypothesis of
deformation at the foundation of the reasoning. Consider the electrons
as material points and ask how their mass should vary as function of the
velocity not to contravene the principle of relativity. Or, still
better, ask what should be their acceleration under the influence of an
electric or magnetic field, that this principle be not violated and that
we come back to the ordinary laws when we suppose the velocity very
slight. We shall find that the variations of this mass, or of these
accelerations, must be _as if_ the electron underwent the Lorentz
deformation.


V

_Kaufmann's Experiment_

We have before us, then, two theories: one where the electrons are
indeformable, this is that of Abraham; the other where they undergo the
Lorentz deformation. In both cases, their mass increases with the
velocity, becoming infinite when this velocity becomes equal to that of
light; but the law of the variation is not the same. The method employed
by Kaufmann to bring to light the law of variation of the mass seems
therefore to give us an experimental means of deciding between the two
theories.

Unhappily, his first experiments were not sufficiently precise for that;
so he decided to repeat them with more precautions, and measuring with
great care the intensity of the fields. Under their new form _they are
in favor of the theory of Abraham_. Then the principle of relativity
would not have the rigorous value we were tempted to attribute to it;
there would no longer be reason for believing the positive electrons
denuded of real mass like the negative electrons. However, before
definitely adopting this conclusion, a little reflection is necessary.
The question is of such importance that it is to be wished Kaufmann's
experiment were repeated by another experimenter.[17] Unhappily, this
experiment is very delicate and could be carried out successfully only
by a physicist of the same ability as Kaufmann. All precautions have
been properly taken and we hardly see what objection could be made.

  [17] At the moment of going to press we learn that M. Bucherer has
       repeated the experiment, taking new precautions, and that he
       has obtained, contrary to Kaufmann, results confirming the
       views of Lorentz.

There is one point however to which I wish to draw attention: that is to
the measurement of the electrostatic field, a measurement upon which all
depends. This field was produced between the two armatures of a
condenser; and, between these armatures, there was to be made an
extremely perfect vacuum, in order to obtain a complete isolation. Then
the difference of potential of the two armatures was measured, and the
field obtained by dividing this difference by the distance apart of the
armatures. That supposes the field uniform; is this certain? Might there
not be an abrupt fall of potential in the neighborhood of one of the
armatures, of the negative armature, for example? There may be a
difference of potential at the meeting of the metal and the vacuum, and
it may be that this difference is not the same on the positive side and
on the negative side; what would lead me to think so is the electric
valve effects between mercury and vacuum. However slight the probability
that it is so, it seems that it should be considered.


VI

_The Principle of Inertia_

In the new dynamics, the principle of inertia is still true, that is to
say that an _isolated_ electron will have a straight and uniform motion.
At least this is generally assumed; however, Lindemann has made
objections to this view; I do not wish to take part in this discussion,
which I can not here expound because of its too difficult character. In
any case, slight modifications to the theory would suffice to shelter it
from Lindemann's objections.

We know that a body submerged in a fluid experiences, when in motion,
considerable resistance, but this is because our fluids are viscous; in
an ideal fluid, perfectly free from viscosity, the body would stir up
behind it a liquid hill, a sort of wake; upon departure, a great effort
would be necessary to put it in motion, since it would be necessary to
move not only the body itself, but the liquid of its wake. But, the
motion once acquired, it would perpetuate itself without resistance,
since the body, in advancing, would simply carry with it the
perturbation of the liquid, without the total vis viva of the liquid
augmenting. Everything would happen therefore as if its inertia was
augmented. An electron advancing in the ether would behave in the same
way: around it, the ether would be stirred up, but this perturbation
would accompany the body in its motion; so that, for an observer carried
along with the electron, the electric and magnetic fields accompanying
this electron would appear invariable, and would change only if the
velocity of the electron varied. An effort would therefore be necessary
to put the electron in motion, since it would be necessary to create the
energy of these fields; on the contrary, once the movement acquired, no
effort would be necessary to maintain it, since the created energy would
only have to go along behind the electron as a wake. This energy,
therefore, could only augment the inertia of the electron, as the
agitation of the liquid augments that of the body submerged in a perfect
fluid. And anyhow, the negative electrons at least have no other inertia
except that.

In the hypothesis of Lorentz, the vis viva, which is only the energy of
the ether, is not proportional to _v_^{2}. Doubtless if _v_ is very
slight, the vis viva is sensibly proportional to _v_^{2}, the quantity
of motion sensibly proportional to _v_, the two masses sensibly constant
and equal to each other. But _when the velocity tends toward the
velocity of light, the vis viva, the quantity of motion and the two
masses increase beyond all limit_.

In the hypothesis of Abraham, the expressions are a little more
complicated; but what we have just said remains true in essentials.

So the mass, the quantity of motion, the vis viva become infinite when
the velocity is equal to that of light.

Thence results that _no body can attain in any way a velocity beyond
that of light_. And in fact, in proportion as its velocity increases,
its mass increases, so that its inertia opposes to any new increase of
velocity a greater and greater obstacle.

A question then suggests itself: let us admit the principle of
relativity; an observer in motion would not have any means of perceiving
his own motion. If therefore no body in its absolute motion can exceed
the velocity of light, but may approach it as nearly as you choose, it
should be the same concerning its relative motion with reference to our
observer. And then we might be tempted to reason as follows: The
observer may attain a velocity of 200,000 kilometers; the body in its
relative motion with reference to the observer may attain the same
velocity; its absolute velocity will then be 400,000 kilometers, which
is impossible, since this is beyond the velocity of light. This is only
a seeming, which vanishes when account is taken of how Lorentz evaluates
local time.


VII

_The Wave of Acceleration_

When an electron is in motion, it produces a perturbation in the ether
surrounding it; if its motion is straight and uniform, this perturbation
reduces to the wake of which we have spoken in the preceding section.
But it is no longer the same, if the motion be curvilinear or varied.
The perturbation may then be regarded as the superposition of two
others, to which Langevin has given the names _wave of velocity_ and
_wave of acceleration_. The wave of velocity is only the wave which
happens in uniform motion.

As to the wave of acceleration, this is a perturbation altogether
analogous to light waves, which starts from the electron at the instant
when it undergoes an acceleration, and which is then propagated by
successive spherical waves with the velocity of light. Whence follows:
in a straight and uniform motion, the energy is wholly conserved; but,
when there is an acceleration, there is loss of energy, which is
dissipated under the form of luminous waves and goes out to infinity
across the ether.

However, the effects of this wave of acceleration, in particular the
corresponding loss of energy, are in most cases negligible, that is to
say not only in ordinary mechanics and in the motions of the heavenly
bodies, but even in the radium rays, where the velocity is very great
without the acceleration being so. We may then confine ourselves to
applying the laws of mechanics, putting the force equal to the product
of acceleration by mass, this mass, however, varying with the velocity
according to the laws explained above. We then say the motion is
_quasi-stationary_.

It would not be the same in all cases where the acceleration is great,
of which the chief are the following:

1º In incandescent gases certain electrons take an oscillatory motion of
very high frequency; the displacements are very small, the velocities
are finite, and the accelerations very great; energy is then
communicated to the ether, and this is why these gases radiate light of
the same period as the oscillations of the electron;

2º Inversely, when a gas receives light, these same electrons are put in
swing with strong accelerations and they absorb light;

3º In the Hertz discharger, the electrons which circulate in the
metallic mass undergo, at the instant of the discharge, an abrupt
acceleration and take then an oscillatory motion of high frequency.
Thence results that a part of the energy radiates under the form of
Hertzian waves;

4º In an incandescent metal, the electrons enclosed in this metal are
impelled with great velocity; upon reaching the surface of the metal,
which they can not get through, they are reflected and thus undergo a
considerable acceleration. This is why the metal emits light. The
details of the laws of the emission of light by dark bodies are
perfectly explained by this hypothesis;

5º Finally when the cathode rays strike the anticathode, the negative
electrons, constituting these rays, which are impelled with very great
velocity, are abruptly arrested. Because of the acceleration they thus
undergo, they produce undulations in the ether. This, according to
certain physicists, is the origin of the Röntgen rays, which would only
be light rays of very short wave-length.



CHAPTER III

THE NEW MECHANICS AND ASTRONOMY


I

_Gravitation_

Mass may be defined in two ways:

1º By the quotient of the force by the acceleration; this is the true
definition of the mass, which measures the inertia of the body.

2° By the attraction the body exercises upon an exterior body, in virtue
of Newton's law. We should therefore distinguish the mass coefficient of
inertia and the mass coefficient of attraction. According to Newton's
law, there is rigorous proportionality between these two coefficients.
But that is demonstrated only for velocities to which the general
principles of dynamics are applicable. Now, we have seen that the mass
coefficient of inertia increases with the velocity; should we conclude
that the mass coefficient of attraction increases likewise with the
velocity and remains proportional to the coefficient of inertia, or, on
the contrary, that this coefficient of attraction remains constant? This
is a question we have no means of deciding.

On the other hand, if the coefficient of attraction depends upon the
velocity, since the velocities of two bodies which mutually attract are
not in general the same, how will this coefficient depend upon these two
velocities?

Upon this subject we can only make hypotheses, but we are naturally led
to investigate which of these hypotheses would be compatible with the
principle of relativity. There are a great number of them; the only one
of which I shall here speak is that of Lorentz, which I shall briefly
expound.

Consider first electrons at rest. Two electrons of the same sign repel
each other and two electrons of contrary sign attract each other; in the
ordinary theory, their mutual actions are proportional to their electric
charges; if therefore we have four electrons, two positive _A_ and
_A'_, and two negative _B_ and _B'_, the charges of these four being the
same in absolute value, the repulsion of _A_ for _A'_ will be, at the
same distance, equal to the repulsion of _B_ for _B'_ and equal also to
the attraction of _A_ for _B'_, or of _A'_ for _B_. If therefore _A_ and
_B_ are very near each other, as also _A'_ and _B'_, and we examine the
action of the system _A_ + _B_ upon the system _A'_ + _B'_, we shall
have two repulsions and two attractions which will exactly compensate
each other and the resulting action will be null.

Now, material molecules should just be regarded as species of solar
systems where circulate the electrons, some positive, some negative, and
_in such a way that the algebraic sum of all the charges is null_. A
material molecule is therefore wholly analogous to the system _A_ + _B_
of which we have spoken, so that the total electric action of two
molecules one upon the other should be null.

But experiment shows us that these molecules attract each other in
consequence of Newtonian gravitation; and then we may make two
hypotheses: we may suppose gravitation has no relation to the
electrostatic attractions, that it is due to a cause entirely different,
and is simply something additional; or else we may suppose the
attractions are not proportional to the charges and that the attraction
exercised by a charge +1 upon a charge -1 is greater than the mutual
repulsion of two +1 charges, or two -1 charges.

In other words, the electric field produced by the positive electrons
and that which the negative electrons produce might be superposed and
yet remain distinct. The positive electrons would be more sensitive to
the field produced by the negative electrons than to the field produced
by the positive electrons; the contrary would be the case for the
negative electrons. It is clear that this hypothesis somewhat
complicates electrostatics, but that it brings back into it gravitation.
This was, in sum, Franklin's hypothesis.

What happens now if the electrons are in motion? The positive electrons
will cause a perturbation in the ether and produce there an electric and
magnetic field. The same will be the case for the negative electrons.
The electrons, positive as well as negative, undergo then a mechanical
impulsion by the action of these different fields. In the ordinary
theory, the electromagnetic field, due to the motion of the positive
electrons, exercises, upon two electrons of contrary sign and of the
same absolute charge, equal actions with contrary sign. We may then
without inconvenience not distinguish the field due to the motion of the
positive electrons and the field due to the motion of the negative
electrons and consider only the algebraic sum of these two fields, that
is to say the resulting field.

In the new theory, on the contrary, the action upon the positive
electrons of the electromagnetic field due to the positive electrons
follows the ordinary laws; it is the same with the action upon the
negative electrons of the field due to the negative electrons. Let us
now consider the action of the field due to the positive electrons upon
the negative electrons (or inversely); it will still follow the same
laws, but _with a different coefficient_. Each electron is more
sensitive to the field created by the electrons of contrary name than to
the field created by the electrons of the same name.

Such is the hypothesis of Lorentz, which reduces to Franklin's
hypothesis for slight velocities; it will therefore explain, for these
small velocities, Newton's law. Moreover, as gravitation goes back to
forces of electrodynamic origin, the general theory of Lorentz will
apply, and consequently the principle of relativity will not be
violated.

We see that Newton's law is no longer applicable to great velocities and
that it must be modified, for bodies in motion, precisely in the same
way as the laws of electrostatics for electricity in motion.

We know that electromagnetic perturbations spread with the velocity of
light. We may therefore be tempted to reject the preceding theory upon
remembering that gravitation spreads, according to the calculations of
Laplace, at least ten million times more quickly than light, and that
consequently it can not be of electromagnetic origin. The result of
Laplace is well known, but one is generally ignorant of its
signification. Laplace supposed that, if the propagation of gravitation
is not instantaneous, its velocity of spread combines with that of the
body attracted, as happens for light in the phenomenon of astronomic
aberration, so that the effective force is not directed along the
straight joining the two bodies, but makes with this straight a small
angle. This is a very special hypothesis, not well justified, and, in
any case, entirely different from that of Lorentz. Laplace's result
proves nothing against the theory of Lorentz.


II

_Comparison with Astronomic Observations_

Can the preceding theories be reconciled with astronomic observations?

First of all, if we adopt them, the energy of the planetary motions will
be constantly dissipated by the effect of the _wave of acceleration_.
From this would result that the mean motions of the stars would
constantly accelerate, as if these stars were moving in a resistant
medium. But this effect is exceedingly slight, far too much so to be
discerned by the most precise observations. The acceleration of the
heavenly bodies is relatively slight, so that the effects of the wave of
acceleration are negligible and the motion may be regarded as _quasi
stationary_. It is true that the effects of the wave of acceleration
constantly accumulate, but this accumulation itself is so slow that
thousands of years of observation would be necessary for it to become
sensible. Let us therefore make the calculation considering the motion
as quasi-stationary, and that under the three following hypotheses:

A. Admit the hypothesis of Abraham (electrons indeformable) and retain
Newton's law in its usual form;

B. Admit the hypothesis of Lorentz about the deformation of electrons
and retain the usual Newton's law;

C. Admit the hypothesis of Lorentz about electrons and modify Newton's
law as we have done in the preceding paragraph, so as to render it
compatible with the principle of relativity.

It is in the motion of Mercury that the effect will be most sensible,
since this planet has the greatest velocity. Tisserand formerly made an
analogous calculation, admitting Weber's law; I recall that Weber had
sought to explain at the same time the electrostatic and electrodynamic
phenomena in supposing that electrons (whose name was not yet invented)
exercise, one upon another, attractions and repulsions directed along
the straight joining them, and depending not only upon their distances,
but upon the first and second derivatives of these distances,
consequently upon their velocities and their accelerations. This law of
Weber, different enough from those which to-day tend to prevail, none
the less presents a certain analogy with them.

Tisserand found that, if the Newtonian attraction conformed to Weber's
law there resulted, for Mercury's perihelion, secular variation of 14",
_of the same sense as that which has been observed and could not be
explained_, but smaller, since this is 38".

Let us recur to the hypotheses A, B and C, and study first the motion of
a planet attracted by a fixed center. The hypotheses B and C are no
longer distinguished, since, if the attracting point is fixed, the field
it produces is a purely electrostatic field, where the attraction varies
inversely as the square of the distance, in conformity with Coulomb's
electrostatic law, identical with that of Newton.

The vis viva equation holds good, taking for vis viva the new
definition; in the same way, the equation of areas is replaced by
another equivalent to it; the moment of the quantity of motion is a
constant, but the quantity of motion must be defined as in the new
dynamics.

The only sensible effect will be a secular motion of the perihelion.
With the theory of Lorentz, we shall find, for this motion, half of what
Weber's law would give; with the theory of Abraham, two fifths.

If now we suppose two moving bodies gravitating around their common
center of gravity, the effects are very little different, though the
calculations may be a little more complicated. The motion of Mercury's
perihelion would therefore be 7" in the theory of Lorentz and 5".6 in
that of Abraham.

The effect moreover is proportional to (_n_^{3})(_a_^{2}), where _n_ is
the star's mean motion and a the radius of its orbit. For the planets,
in virtue of Kepler's law, the effect varies then inversely as
sqrt(_a_^{5}); it is therefore insensible, save for Mercury.

It is likewise insensible for the moon though _n_ is great, because _a_
is extremely small; in sum, it is five times less for Venus, and six
hundred times less for the moon than for Mercury. We may add that as to
Venus and the earth, the motion of the perihelion (for the same angular
velocity of this motion) would be much more difficult to discern by
astronomic observations, because the excentricity of their orbits is
much less than for Mercury.

To sum up, _the only sensible effect upon astronomic observations would
be a motion of Mercury's perihelion, in the same sense as that which has
been observed without being explained, but notably slighter_.

That can not be regarded as an argument in favor of the new dynamics,
since it will always be necessary to seek another explanation for the
greater part of Mercury's anomaly; but still less can it be regarded as
an argument against it.


III

_The Theory of Lesage_

It is interesting to compare these considerations with a theory long
since proposed to explain universal gravitation.

Suppose that, in the interplanetary spaces, circulate in every
direction, with high velocities, very tenuous corpuscles. A body
isolated in space will not be affected, apparently, by the impacts of
these corpuscles, since these impacts are equally distributed in all
directions. But if two bodies _A_ and _B_ are present, the body _B_ will
play the rôle of screen and will intercept part of the corpuscles which,
without it, would have struck _A_. Then, the impacts received by _A_ in
the direction opposite that from _B_ will no longer have a counterpart,
or will now be only partially compensated, and this will push _A_ toward
_B_.

Such is the theory of Lesage; and we shall discuss it, taking first the
view-point of ordinary mechanics.

First, how should the impacts postulated by this theory take place; is
it according to the laws of perfectly elastic bodies, or according to
those of bodies devoid of elasticity, or according to an intermediate
law? The corpuscles of Lesage can not act as perfectly elastic bodies;
otherwise the effect would be null, since the corpuscles intercepted by
the body _B_ would be replaced by others which would have rebounded from
_B_, and calculation proves that the compensation would be perfect. It
is necessary then that the impact make the corpuscles lose energy, and
this energy should appear under the form of heat. But how much heat
would thus be produced? Note that attraction passes through bodies; it
is necessary therefore to represent to ourselves the earth, for example,
not as a solid screen, but as formed of a very great number of very
small spherical molecules, which play individually the rôle of little
screens, but between which the corpuscles of Lesage may freely
circulate. So, not only the earth is not a solid screen, but it is not
even a cullender, since the voids occupy much more space than the
plenums. To realize this, recall that Laplace has demonstrated that
attraction, in traversing the earth, is weakened at most by one
ten-millionth part, and his proof is perfectly satisfactory: in fact, if
attraction were absorbed by the body it traverses, it would no longer be
proportional to the masses; it would be _relatively_ weaker for great
bodies than for small, since it would have a greater thickness to
traverse. The attraction of the sun for the earth would therefore be
_relatively_ weaker than that of the sun for the moon, and thence would
result, in the motion of the moon, a very sensible inequality. We should
therefore conclude, if we adopt the theory of Lesage, that the total
surface of the spherical molecules which compose the earth is at most
the ten-millionth part of the total surface of the earth.

Darwin has proved that the theory of Lesage only leads exactly to
Newton's law when we postulate particles entirely devoid of elasticity.
The attraction exerted by the earth on a mass 1 at a distance 1 will
then be proportional, at the same time, to the total surface _S_ of the
spherical molecules composing it, to the velocity _v_ of the corpuscles,
to the square root of the density [rho] of the medium formed by the
corpuscles. The heat produced will be proportional to _S_, to the
density [rho], and to the cube of the velocity _v_.

But it is necessary to take account of the resistance experienced by a
body moving in such a medium; it can not move, in fact, without going
against certain impacts, in fleeing, on the contrary, before those
coming in the opposite direction, so that the compensation realized in
the state of rest can no longer subsist. The calculated resistance is
proportional to _S_, to [rho] and to _v_; now, we know that the heavenly
bodies move as if they experienced no resistance, and the precision of
observations permits us to fix a limit to the resistance of the medium.

This resistance varying as _S_[rho]_v_, while the attraction varies as
_S_{sqrt([rho]_v_)}, we see that the ratio of the resistance to the
square of the attraction is inversely as the product _Sv_.

We have therefore a lower limit of the product _Sv_. We have already an
upper limit of _S_ (by the absorption of attraction by the body it
traverses); we have therefore a lower limit of the velocity _v_, which
must be at least 24·10^{17} times that of light.

From this we are able to deduce [rho] and the quantity of heat produced;
this quantity would suffice to raise the temperature 10^{26} degrees a
second; the earth would receive in a given time 10^{20} times more heat
than the sun emits in the same time; I am not speaking of the heat the
sun sends to the earth, but of that it radiates in all directions.

It is evident the earth could not long stand such a régime.

We should not be led to results less fantastic if, contrary to Darwin's
views, we endowed the corpuscles of Lesage with an elasticity imperfect
without being null. In truth, the vis viva of these corpuscles would not
be entirely converted into heat, but the attraction produced would
likewise be less, so that it would be only the part of this vis viva
converted into heat, which would contribute to produce the attraction
and that would come to the same thing; a judicious employment of the
theorem of the viriel would enable us to account for this.

The theory of Lesage may be transformed; suppress the corpuscles and
imagine the ether overrun in all senses by luminous waves coming from
all points of space. When a material object receives a luminous wave,
this wave exercises upon it a mechanical action due to the
Maxwell-Bartholi pressure, just as if it had received the impact of a
material projectile. The waves in question could therefore play the rôle
of the corpuscles of Lesage. This is what is supposed, for example, by
M. Tommasina.

The difficulties are not removed for all that; the velocity of
propagation can be only that of light, and we are thus led, for the
resistance of the medium, to an inadmissible figure. Besides, if the
light is all reflected, the effect is null, just as in the hypothesis of
the perfectly elastic corpuscles.

That there should be attraction, it is necessary that the light be
partially absorbed; but then there is production of heat. The
calculations do not differ essentially from those made in the ordinary
theory of Lesage, and the result retains the same fantastic character.

On the other hand, attraction is not absorbed by the body it traverses,
or hardly at all; it is not so with the light we know. Light which would
produce the Newtonian attraction would have to be considerably different
from ordinary light and be, for example, of very short wave length. This
does not count that, if our eyes were sensible of this light, the whole
heavens should appear to us much more brilliant than the sun, so that
the sun would seem to us to stand out in black, otherwise the sun would
repel us instead of attracting us. For all these reasons, light which
would permit of the explanation of attraction would be much more like
Röntgen rays than like ordinary light.

And besides, the X-rays would not suffice; however penetrating they may
seem to us, they could not pass through the whole earth; it would be
necessary therefore to imagine X'-rays much more penetrating than the
ordinary X-rays. Moreover a part of the energy of these X'-rays would
have to be destroyed, otherwise there would be no attraction. If you do
not wish it transformed into heat, which would lead to an enormous heat
production, you must suppose it radiated in every direction under the
form of secondary rays, which might be called X'' and which would have
to be much more penetrating still than the X'-rays, otherwise they would
in their turn derange the phenomena of attraction.

Such are the complicated hypotheses to which we are led when we try to
give life to the theory of Lesage.

But all we have said presupposes the ordinary laws of mechanics.

Will things go better if we admit the new dynamics? And first, can we
conserve the principles of relativity? Let us give at first to the
theory of Lesage its primitive form, and suppose space ploughed by
material corpuscles; if these corpuscles were perfectly elastic, the
laws of their impact would conform to this principle of relativity, but
we know that then their effect would be null. We must therefore suppose
these corpuscles are not elastic, and then it is difficult to imagine a
law of impact compatible with the principle of relativity. Besides, we
should still find a production of considerable heat, and yet a very
sensible resistance of the medium.

If we suppress these corpuscles and revert to the hypothesis of the
Maxwell-Bartholi pressure, the difficulties will not be less. This is
what Lorentz himself has attempted in his Memoir to the Amsterdam
Academy of Sciences of April 25, 1900.

Consider a system of electrons immersed in an ether permeated in every
sense by luminous waves; one of these electrons, struck by one of these
waves, begins to vibrate; its vibration will be synchronous with that of
light; but it may have a difference of phase, if the electron absorbs a
part of the incident energy. In fact, if it absorbs energy, this is
because the vibration of the ether _impels_ the electron; the electron
must therefore be slower than the ether. An electron in motion is
analogous to a convection current; therefore every magnetic field, in
particular that due to the luminous perturbation itself, must exert a
mechanical action upon this electron. This action is very slight;
moreover, it changes sign in the current of the period; nevertheless,
the mean action is not null if there is a difference of phase between
the vibrations of the electron and those of the ether. The mean action
is proportional to this difference, consequently to the energy absorbed
by the electron. I can not here enter into the detail of the
calculations; suffice it to say only that the final result is an
attraction of any two electrons, varying inversely as the square of the
distance and proportional to the energy absorbed by the two electrons.

Therefore there can not be attraction without absorption of light and,
consequently, without production of heat, and this it is which
determined Lorentz to abandon this theory, which, at bottom, does not
differ from that of Lesage-Maxwell-Bartholi. He would have been much
more dismayed still if he had pushed the calculation to the end. He
would have found that the temperature of the earth would have to
increase 10^{12} degrees a second.


IV

_Conclusions_

I have striven to give in few words an idea as complete as possible of
these new doctrines; I have sought to explain how they took birth;
otherwise the reader would have had ground to be frightened by their
boldness. The new theories are not yet demonstrated; far from it; only
they rest upon an aggregate of probabilities sufficiently weighty for us
not to have the right to treat them with disregard.

New experiments will doubtless teach us what we should finally think of
them. The knotty point of the question lies in Kaufmann's experiment and
those that may be undertaken to verify it.

In conclusion, permit me a word of warning. Suppose that, after some
years, these theories undergo new tests and triumph; then our secondary
education will incur a great danger; certain professors will doubtless
wish to make a place for the new theories.

Novelties are so attractive, and it is so hard not to seem highly
advanced! At least there will be the wish to open vistas to the pupils
and, before teaching them the ordinary mechanics, to let them know it
has had its day and was at best good enough for that old dolt Laplace.
And then they will not form the habit of the ordinary mechanics.

Is it well to let them know this is only approximative? Yes; but later,
when it has penetrated to their very marrow, when they shall have taken
the bent of thinking only through it, when there shall no longer be risk
of their unlearning it, then one may, without inconvenience, show them
its limits.

It is with the ordinary mechanics that they must live; this alone will
they ever have to apply. Whatever be the progress of automobilism, our
vehicles will never attain speeds where it is not true. The other is
only a luxury, and we should think of the luxury only when there is no
longer any risk of harming the necessary.



BOOK IV


ASTRONOMIC SCIENCE



CHAPTER I

THE MILKY WAY AND THE THEORY OF GASES


The considerations to be here developed have scarcely as yet drawn the
attention of astronomers; there is hardly anything to cite except an
ingenious idea of Lord Kelvin's, which has opened a new field of
research, but still waits to be followed out. Nor have I original
results to impart, and all I can do is to give an idea of the problems
presented, but which no one hitherto has undertaken to solve. Every one
knows how a large number of modern physicists represent the constitution
of gases; gases are formed of an innumerable multitude of molecules
which, at high speeds, cross and crisscross in every direction. These
molecules probably act at a distance one upon another, but this action
decreases very rapidly with distance, so that their trajectories remain
sensibly straight; they cease to be so only when two molecules happen to
pass very near to each other; in this case, their mutual attraction or
repulsion makes them deviate to right or left. This is what is sometimes
called an impact; but the word _impact_ is not to be understood in its
usual sense; it is not necessary that the two molecules come into
contact, it suffices that they approach sufficiently near each other for
their mutual attractions to become sensible. The laws of the deviation
they undergo are the same as for a veritable impact.

It seems at first that the disorderly impacts of this innumerable dust
can engender only an inextricable chaos before which analysis must
recoil. But the law of great numbers, that supreme law of chance, comes
to our aid; in presence of a semi-disorder, we must despair, but in
extreme disorder, this statistical law reestablishes a sort of mean
order where the mind can recover. It is the study of this mean order
which constitutes the kinetic theory of gases; it shows us that the
velocities of the molecules are equally distributed among all the
directions, that the rapidity of these velocities varies from one
molecule to another, but that even this variation is subject to a law
called Maxwell's law. This law tells us how many of the molecules move
with such and such a velocity. As soon as the gas departs from this law,
the mutual impacts of the molecules, in modifying the rapidity and
direction of their velocities, tend to bring it promptly back.
Physicists have striven, not without success, to explain in this way the
experimental properties of gases; for example Mariotte's law.

Consider now the milky way; there also we see an innumerable dust; only
the grains of this dust are not atoms, they are stars; these grains move
also with high velocities; they act at a distance one upon another, but
this action is so slight at great distance that their trajectories are
straight; and yet, from time to time, two of them may approach near
enough to be deviated from their path, like a comet which has passed too
near Jupiter. In a word, to the eyes of a giant for whom our suns would
be as for us our atoms, the milky way would seem only a bubble of gas.

Such was Lord Kelvin's leading idea. What may be drawn from this
comparison? In how far is it exact? This is what we are to investigate
together; but before reaching a definite conclusion, and without wishing
to prejudge it, we foresee that the kinetic theory of gases will be for
the astronomer a model he should not follow blindly, but from which he
may advantageously draw inspiration. Up to the present, celestial
mechanics has attacked only the solar system or certain systems of
double stars. Before the assemblage presented by the milky way, or the
agglomeration of stars, or the resolvable nebulae it recoils, because it
sees therein only chaos. But the milky way is not more complicated than
a gas; the statistical methods founded upon the calculus of
probabilities applicable to a gas are also applicable to it. Before all,
it is important to grasp the resemblance of the two cases, and their
difference.

Lord Kelvin has striven to determine in this manner the dimensions of
the milky way; for that we are reduced to counting the stars visible in
our telescopes; but we are not sure that behind the stars we see, there
are not others we do not see; so that what we should measure in this way
would not be the size of the milky way, it would be the range of our
instruments.

The new theory comes to offer us other resources. In fact, we know the
motions of the stars nearest us, and we can form an idea of the rapidity
and direction of their velocities. If the ideas above set forth are
exact, these velocities should follow Maxwell's law, and their mean
value will tell us, so to speak, that which corresponds to the
temperature of our fictitious gas. But this temperature depends itself
upon the dimensions of our gas bubble. In fact, how will a gaseous mass
let loose in the void act, if its elements attract one another according
to Newton's law? It will take a spherical form; moreover, because of
gravitation, the density will be greater at the center, the pressure
also will increase from the surface to the center because of the weight
of the outer parts drawn toward the center; finally, the temperature
will increase toward the center: the temperature and the pressure being
connected by the law called adiabatic, as happens in the successive
layers of our atmosphere. At the surface itself, the pressure will be
null, and it will be the same with the absolute temperature, that is to
say with the velocity of the molecules.

A question comes here: I have spoken of the adiabatic law, but this law
is not the same for all gases, since it depends upon the ratio of their
two specific heats; for the air and like gases, this ratio is 1.42; but
is it to air that it is proper to liken the milky way? Evidently not, it
should be regarded as a mono-atomic gas, like mercury vapor, like argon,
like helium, that is to say that the ratio of the specific heats should
be taken equal to 1.66. And, in fact, one of our molecules would be for
example the solar system; but the planets are very small personages, the
sun alone counts, so that our molecule is indeed mono-atomic. And even
if we take a double star, it is probable that the action of a strange
star which might approach it would become sufficiently sensible to
deviate the motion of general translation of the system much before
being able to trouble the relative orbits of the two components; the
double star, in a word, would act like an indivisible atom.

However that may be, the pressure, and consequently the temperature, at
the center of the gaseous sphere would be by so much the greater as the
sphere was larger since the pressure increases by the weight of all the
superposed layers. We may suppose that we are nearly at the center of
the milky way, and by observing the mean proper velocity of the stars,
we shall know that which corresponds to the central temperature of our
gaseous sphere and we shall determine its radius.

We may get an idea of the result by the following considerations: make a
simpler hypothesis: the milky way is spherical, and in it the masses are
distributed in a homogeneous manner; thence results that the stars in it
describe ellipses having the same center. If we suppose the velocity
becomes nothing at the surface, we may calculate this velocity at the
center by the equation of vis viva. Thus we find that this velocity is
proportional to the radius of the sphere and to the square root of its
density. If the mass of this sphere was that of the sun and its radius
that of the terrestrial orbit, this velocity would be (it is easy to
see) that of the earth in its orbit. But in the case we have supposed,
the mass of the sun should be distributed in a sphere of radius
1,000,000 times greater, this radius being the distance of the nearest
stars; the density is therefore 10^{18} times less; now, the velocities
are of the same order, therefore it is necessary that the radius be
10^{9} times greater, be 1,000 times the distance of the nearest stars,
which would give about a thousand millions of stars in the milky way.

But you will say these hypothesis differ greatly from the reality;
first, the milky way is not spherical and we shall soon return to this
point, and again the kinetic theory of gases is not compatible with the
hypothesis of a homogeneous sphere. But in making the exact calculation
according to this theory, we should find a different result, doubtless,
but of the same order of magnitude; now in such a problem the data are
so uncertain that the order of magnitude is the sole end to be aimed at.

And here a first remark presents itself; Lord Kelvin's result, which I
have obtained again by an approximative calculation, agrees sensibly
with the evaluations the observers have made with their telescopes; so
that we must conclude we are very near to piercing through the milky
way. But that enables us to answer another question. There are the stars
we see because they shine; but may there not be dark stars circulating
in the interstellar spaces whose existence might long remain unknown?
But then, what Lord Kelvin's method would give us would be the total
number of stars, including the dark stars; as his figure is comparable
to that the telescope gives, this means there is no dark matter, or at
least not so much as of shining matter.

Before going further, we must look at the problem from another angle. Is
the milky way thus constituted truly the image of a gas properly so
called? You know Crookes has introduced the notion of a fourth state of
matter, where gases having become too rarefied are no longer true gases
and become what he calls radiant matter. Considering the slight density
of the milky way, is it the image of gaseous matter or of radiant
matter? The consideration of what is called the _free path_ will furnish
us the answer.

The trajectory of a gaseous molecule may be regarded as formed of
straight segments united by very small arcs corresponding to the
successive impacts. The length of each of these segments is what is
called the free path; of course this length is not the same for all the
segments and for all the molecules; but we may take a mean; this is what
is called the _mean path_. This is the greater the less the density of
the gas. The matter will be radiant if the mean path is greater than the
dimensions of the receptacle wherein the gas is enclosed, so that a
molecule has a chance to go across the whole receptacle without
undergoing an impact; if the contrary be the case, it is gaseous. From
this it follows that the same fluid may be radiant in a little
receptacle and gaseous in a big one; this perhaps is why, in a Crookes
tube, it is necessary to make the vacuum by so much the more complete as
the tube is larger.

How is it then for the milky way? This is a mass of gas of which the
density is very slight, but whose dimensions are very great; has a star
chances of traversing it without undergoing an impact, that is to say
without passing sufficiently near another star to be sensibly deviated
from its route! What do we mean by _sufficiently near_? That is perforce
a little arbitrary; take it as the distance from the sun to Neptune,
which would represent a deviation of a dozen degrees; suppose therefore
each of our stars surrounded by a protective sphere of this radius;
could a straight pass between these spheres? At the mean distance of the
stars of the milky way, the radius of these spheres will be seen under
an angle of about a tenth of a second; and we have a thousand millions
of stars. Put upon the celestial sphere a thousand million little
circles of a tenth of a second radius. Are the chances that these
circles will cover a great number of times the celestial sphere? Far
from it; they will cover only its sixteen thousandth part. So the milky
way is not the image of gaseous matter, but of Crookes' radiant matter.
Nevertheless, as our foregoing conclusions are happily not at all
precise, we need not sensibly modify them.

But there is another difficulty: the milky way is not spherical, and we
have reasoned hitherto as if it were, since this is the form of
equilibrium a gas isolated in space would take. To make amends,
agglomerations of stars exist whose form is globular and to which would
better apply what we have hitherto said. Herschel has already endeavored
to explain their remarkable appearances. He supposed the stars of the
aggregates uniformly distributed, so that an assemblage is a homogeneous
sphere; each star would then describe an ellipse and all these orbits
would be passed over in the same time, so that at the end of a period
the aggregate would take again its primitive configuration and this
configuration would be stable. Unluckily, the aggregates do not appear
to be homogeneous; we see a condensation at the center, we should
observe it even were the sphere homogeneous, since it is thicker at the
center; but it would not be so accentuated. We may therefore rather
compare an aggregate to a gas in adiabatic equilibrium, which takes the
spherical form because this is the figure of equilibrium of a gaseous
mass.

But, you will say, these aggregates are much smaller than the milky way,
of which they even in probability make part, and even though they be
more dense, they will rather present something analogous to radiant
matter; now, gases attain their adiabatic equilibrium only through
innumerable impacts of the molecules. That might perhaps be adjusted.
Suppose the stars of the aggregate have just enough energy for their
velocity to become null when they reach the surface; then they may
traverse the aggregate without impact, but arrived at the surface they
will go back and will traverse it anew; after a great number of
crossings, they will at last be deviated by an impact; under these
conditions, we should still have a matter which might be regarded as
gaseous; if perchance there had been in the aggregate stars whose
velocity was greater, they have long gone away out of it, they have left
it never to return. For all these reasons, it would be interesting to
examine the known aggregates, to seek to account for the law of the
densities, and to see if it is the adiabatic law of gases.

But to return to the milky way; it is not spherical and would rather be
represented as a flattened disc. It is clear then that a mass starting
without velocity from the surface will reach the center with different
velocities, according as it starts from the surface in the neighborhood
of the middle of the disc or just on the border of the disc; the
velocity would be notably greater in the latter case. Now, up to the
present, we have supposed that the proper velocities of the stars, those
we observe, must be comparable to those which like masses would attain;
this involves a certain difficulty. We have given above a value for the
dimensions of the milky way, and we have deduced it from the observed
proper velocities which are of the same order of magnitude as that of
the earth in its orbit; but which is the dimension we have thus
measured? Is it the thickness? Is it the radius of the disc? It is
doubtless something intermediate; but what can we say then of the
thickness itself, or of the radius of the disc? Data are lacking to make
the calculation; I shall confine myself to giving a glimpse of the
possibility of basing an evaluation at least approximate upon a deeper
discussion of the proper motions.

And then we find ourselves facing two hypotheses: either the stars of
the milky way are impelled by velocities for the most part parallel to
the galactic plane, but otherwise distributed uniformly in all
directions parallel to this plane. If this be so, observation of the
proper motions should show a preponderance of components parallel to the
milky way; this is to be determined, because I do not know whether a
systematic discussion has ever been made from this view-point. On the
other hand, such an equilibrium could only be provisory, since because
of impacts the molecules, I mean the stars, would in the long run
acquire notable velocities in the sense perpendicular to the milky way
and would end by swerving from its plane, so that the system would tend
toward the spherical form, the only figure of equilibrium of an isolated
gaseous mass.

Or else the whole system is impelled by a common rotation, and for that
reason is flattened like the earth, like Jupiter, like all bodies that
twirl. Only, as the flattening is considerable, the rotation must be
rapid; rapid doubtless, but it must be understood in what sense this
word is used. The density of the milky way is 10^{23} times less than
that of the sun; a velocity of rotation sqrt(10^{25}) times less than
that of the sun, for it would, therefore, be the equivalent so far as
concerns flattening; a velocity 10^{12} times slower than that of the
earth, say a thirtieth of a second of arc in a century, would be a very
rapid rotation, almost too rapid for stable equilibrium to be possible.

In this hypothesis, the observable proper motions would appear to us
uniformly distributed, and there would no longer be a preponderance of
components parallel to the galactic plane.

They will tell us nothing about the rotation itself, since we belong to
the turning system. If the spiral nebulæ are other milky ways, foreign
to ours, they are not borne along in this rotation, and we might study
their proper motions. It is true they are very far away; if a nebula has
the dimensions of the milky way and if its apparent radius is for
example 20", its distance is 10,000 times the radius of the milky way.

But that makes no difference, since it is not about the translation of
our system that we ask information from them, but about its rotation.
The fixed stars, by their apparent motion, reveal to us the diurnal
rotation of the earth, though their distance is immense. Unluckily, the
possible rotation of the milky way, however rapid it may be relatively,
is very slow viewed absolutely, and besides the pointings on nebulæ can
not be very precise; therefore thousands of years of observations would
be necessary to learn anything.

However that may be, in this second hypothesis, the figure of the milky
way would be a figure of final equilibrium.

I shall not further discuss the relative value of these two hypotheses
since there is a third which is perhaps more probable. We know that
among the irresolvable nebulæ, several kinds may be distinguished: the
irregular nebulæ like that of Orion, the planetary and annular nebulæ,
the spiral nebulæ. The spectra of the first two families have been
determined, they are discontinuous; these nebulæ are therefore not
formed of stars; besides, their distribution on the heavens seems to
depend upon the milky way; whether they have a tendency to go away from
it, or on the contrary to approach it, they make therefore a part of the
system. On the other hand, the spiral nebulæ are generally considered as
independent of the milky way; it is supposed that they, like it, are
formed of a multitude of stars, that they are, in a word, other milky
ways very far away from ours. The recent investigations of Stratonoff
tend to make us regard the milky way itself as a spiral nebula, and this
is the third hypothesis of which I wish to speak.

How can we explain the very singular appearances presented by the spiral
nebulæ, which are too regular and too constant to be due to chance?
First of all, to take a look at one of these representations is enough
to see that the mass is in rotation; we may even see what the sense of
the rotation is; all the spiral radii are curved in the same sense; it
is evident that the _moving wing_ lags behind the pivot and that fixes
the sense of the rotation. But this is not all; it is evident that these
nebulæ can not be likened to a gas at rest, nor even to a gas in
relative equilibrium under the sway of a uniform rotation; they are to
be compared to a gas in permanent motion in which internal currents
prevail.

Suppose, for example, that the rotation of the central nucleus is rapid
(you know what I mean by this word), too rapid for stable equilibrium;
then at the equator the centrifugal force will drive it away over the
attraction, and the stars will tend to break away at the equator and
will form divergent currents; but in going away, as their moment of
rotation remains constant, while the radius vector augments, their
angular velocity will diminish, and this is why the moving wing seems to
lag back.

From this point of view, there would not be a real permanent motion, the
central nucleus would constantly lose matter which would go out of it
never to return, and would drain away progressively. But we may modify
the hypothesis. In proportion as it goes away, the star loses its
velocity and ends by stopping; at this moment attraction regains
possession of it and leads it back toward the nucleus; so there will be
centripetal currents. We must suppose the centripetal currents are the
first rank and the centrifugal currents the second rank, if we adopt the
comparison with a troop in battle executing a change of front; and, in
fact, it is necessary that the composite centrifugal force be
compensated by the attraction exercised by the central layers of the
swarm upon the extreme layers.

Besides, at the end of a certain time a permanent régime establishes
itself; the swarm being curved, the attraction exercised upon the pivot
by the moving wing tends to slow up the pivot and that of the pivot upon
the moving wing tends to accelerate the advance of this wing which no
longer augments its lag, so that finally all the radii end by turning
with a uniform velocity. We may still suppose that the rotation of the
nucleus is quicker than that of the radii.

A question remains; why do these centripetal and centrifugal swarms tend
to concentrate themselves in radii instead of disseminating themselves a
little everywhere? Why do these rays distribute themselves regularly? If
the swarms concentrate themselves, it is because of the attraction
exercised by the already existing swarms upon the stars which go out
from the nucleus in their neighborhood. After an inequality is produced,
it tends to accentuate itself in this way.

Why do the rays distribute themselves regularly? That is less obvious.
Suppose there is no rotation, that all the stars are in two planes at
right angles, in such a way that their distribution is symmetric with
regard to these two planes.

By symmetry, there would be no reason for their going out of these
planes, nor for the symmetry changing. This configuration would give us
therefore equilibrium, but _this would be an unstable equilibrium_.

If on the contrary, there is rotation, we shall find an analogous
configuration of equilibrium with four curved rays, equal to each other
and intersecting at 90°, and if the rotation is sufficiently rapid, this
equilibrium is stable.

I am not in position to make this more precise: enough if you see that
these spiral forms may perhaps some day be explained by only the law of
gravitation and statistical consideration recalling those of the theory
of gases.

What has been said of internal currents shows it is of interest to
discuss systematically the aggregate of proper motions; this may be done
in a hundred years, when the second edition is issued of the chart of
the heavens and compared with the first, that we now are making.

But, in conclusion, I wish to call your attention to a question, that of
the age of the milky way or the nebulæ. If what we think we see is
confirmed, we can get an idea of it. That sort of statistical
equilibrium of which gases give us the model is established only in
consequence of a great number of impacts. If these impacts are rare, it
can come about only after a very long time; if really the milky way (or
at least the agglomerations which are contained in it), if the nebulæ
have attained this equilibrium, this means they are very old, and we
shall have an inferior limit of their age. Likewise we should have of it
a superior limit; this equilibrium is not final and can not last always.
Our spiral nebulæ would be comparable to gases impelled by permanent
motions; but gases in motion are viscous and their velocities end by
wearing out. What here corresponds to the viscosity (and which depends
upon the chances of impact of the molecules) is excessively slight, so
that the present régime may persist during an extremely long time, yet
not forever, so that our milky ways can not live eternally nor become
infinitely old.

And this is not all. Consider our atmosphere: at the surface must reign
a temperature infinitely small and the velocity of the molecules there
is near zero. But this is a question only of the mean velocity; as a
consequence of impacts, one of these molecules may acquire (rarely, it
is true) an enormous velocity, and then it will rush out of the
atmosphere, and once out, it will never return; therefore our atmosphere
drains off thus with extreme slowness. The milky way also from time to
time loses a star by the same mechanism, and that likewise limits its
duration.

Well, it is certain that if we compute in this manner the age of the
milky way, we shall get enormous figures. But here a difficulty presents
itself. Certain physicists, relying upon other considerations, reckon
that suns can have only an ephemeral existence, about fifty million
years; our minimum would be much greater than that. Must we believe that
the evolution of the milky way began when the matter was still dark? But
how have the stars composing it reached all at the same time adult age,
an age so briefly to endure? Or must they reach there all successively,
and are those we see only a feeble minority compared with those
extinguished or which shall one day light up? But how reconcile that
with what we have said above on the absence of a noteworthy proportion
of dark matter? Should we abandon one of the two hypotheses, and which?
I confine myself to pointing out the difficulty without pretending to
solve it; I shall end therefore with a big interrogation point.

However, it is interesting to set problems, even when their solution
seems very far away.



CHAPTER II

FRENCH GEODESY


Every one understands our interest in knowing the form and dimensions of
our earth; but some persons will perhaps be surprised at the exactitude
sought after. Is this a useless luxury? What good are the efforts so
expended by the geodesist?

Should this question be put to a congressman, I suppose he would say:
"I am led to believe that geodesy is one of the most useful of the
sciences; because it is one of those costing us most dear." I shall try
to give you an answer a little more precise.

The great works of art, those of peace as well as those of war, are not
to be undertaken without long studies which save much groping,
miscalculation and useless expense. These studies can only be based upon
a good map. But a map will be only a valueless phantasy if constructed
without basing it upon a solid framework. As well make stand a human
body minus the skeleton.

Now, this framework is given us by geodesic measurements; so, without
geodesy, no good map; without a good map, no great public works.

These reasons will doubtless suffice to justify much expense; but these
are arguments for practical men. It is not upon these that it is proper
to insist here; there are others higher and, everything considered, more
important.

So we shall put the question otherwise; can geodesy aid us the better to
know nature? Does it make us understand its unity and harmony? In
reality an isolated fact is of slight value, and the conquests of
science are precious only if they prepare for new conquests.

If therefore a little hump were discovered on the terrestrial ellipsoid,
this discovery would be by itself of no great interest. On the other
hand, it would become precious if, in seeking the cause of this hump, we
hoped to penetrate new secrets.

Well, when, in the eighteenth century, Maupertuis and La Condamine
braved such opposite climates, it was not solely to learn the shape of
our planet, it was a question of the whole world-system.

If the earth was flattened, Newton triumphed and with him the doctrine
of gravitation and the whole modern celestial mechanics.

And to-day, a century and a half after the victory of the Newtonians,
think you geodesy has nothing more to teach us?

We know not what is within our globe. The shafts of mines and borings
have let us know a layer of 1 or 2 kilometers thickness, that is to say,
the millionth part of the total mass; but what is beneath?

Of all the extraordinary journeys dreamed by Jules Verne, perhaps that
to the center of the earth took us to regions least explored.

But these deep-lying rocks we can not reach, exercise from afar their
attraction which operates upon the pendulum and deforms the terrestrial
spheroid. Geodesy can therefore weigh them from afar, so to speak, and
tell us of their distribution. Thus will it make us really see those
mysterious regions which Jules Verne only showed us in imagination.

This is not an empty illusion. M. Faye, comparing all the measurements,
has reached a result well calculated to surprise us. Under the oceans,
in the depths, are rocks of very great density; under the continents, on
the contrary, are empty spaces.

New observations will modify perhaps the details of these conclusions.

In any case, our venerated dean has shown us where to search and what
the geodesist may teach the geologist, desirous of knowing the interior
constitution of the earth, and even the thinker wishing to speculate
upon the past and the origin of this planet.

And now, why have I entitled this chapter _French Geodesy_? It is
because, in each country, this science has taken, more than all others,
perhaps, a national character. It is easy to see why.

There must be rivalry. The scientific rivalries are always courteous, or
at least almost always; in any case, they are necessary, because they
are always fruitful. Well, in those enterprises which require such long
efforts and so many collaborators, the individual is effaced, in spite
of himself, of course; no one has the right to say: this is my work.
Therefore it is not between men, but between nations that rivalries go
on.

So we are led to seek what has been the part of France. Her part I
believe we are right to be proud of.

At the beginning of the eighteenth century, long discussions arose
between the Newtonians who believed the earth flattened, as the theory
of gravitation requires, and Cassini, who, deceived by inexact
measurements, believed our globe elongated. Only direct observation
could settle the question. It was our Academy of Sciences that undertook
this task, gigantic for the epoch.

While Maupertuis and Clairaut measured a degree of meridian under the
polar circle, Bouguer and La Condamine went toward the Andes Mountains,
in regions then under Spain which to-day are the Republic of Ecuador.

Our envoys were exposed to great hardships. Traveling was not as easy as
at present.

Truly, the country where Maupertuis operated was not a desert and he
even enjoyed, it is said, among the Laplanders those sweet satisfactions
of the heart that real arctic voyagers never know. It was almost the
region where, in our days, comfortable steamers carry, each summer,
hosts of tourists and young English people. But in those days Cook's
agency did not exist and Maupertuis really believed he had made a polar
expedition.

Perhaps he was not altogether wrong. The Russians and the Swedes carry
out to-day analogous measurements at Spitzbergen, in a country where
there is real ice-cap. But they have quite other resources, and the
difference of time makes up for that of latitude.

The name of Maupertuis has reached us much scratched by the claws of
Doctor Akakia; the scientist had the misfortune to displease Voltaire,
who was then the king of mind. He was first praised beyond measure; but
the flatteries of kings are as much to be dreaded as their displeasure,
because the days after are terrible. Voltaire himself knew something of
this.

Voltaire called Maupertuis, my amiable master in thinking, marquis of
the polar circle, dear flattener out of the world and Cassini, and even,
flattery supreme, Sir Isaac Maupertuis; he wrote him: "Only the king of
Prussia do I put on a level with you; he only lacks being a geometer."
But soon the scene changes, he no longer speaks of deifying him, as in
days of yore the Argonauts, or of calling down from Olympus the council
of the gods to contemplate his works, but of chaining him up in a
madhouse. He speaks no longer of his sublime mind, but of his despotic
pride, plated with very little science and much absurdity.

I care not to relate these comico-heroic combats; but permit me some
reflections on two of Voltaire's verses. In his 'Discourse on
Moderation' (no question of moderation in praise and criticism), the
poet has written:

  You have confirmed in regions drear
  What Newton discerned without going abroad.

These two verses (which replace the hyperbolic praises of the first
period) are very unjust, and doubtless Voltaire was too enlightened not
to know it.

Then, only those discoveries were esteemed which could be made without
leaving one's house.

To-day, it would rather be theory that one would make light of.

This is to misunderstand the aim of science.

Is nature governed by caprice, or does harmony rule there? That is the
question. It is when it discloses to us this harmony that science is
beautiful and so worthy to be cultivated. But whence can come to us this
revelation, if not from the accord of a theory with experiment? To seek
whether this accord exists or if it fails, this therefore is our aim.
Consequently these two terms, which we must compare, are as
indispensable the one as the other. To neglect one for the other would
be nonsense. Isolated, theory would be empty, experiment would be blind;
each would be useless and without interest.

Maupertuis therefore deserves his share of glory. Truly, it will not
equal that of Newton, who had received the spark divine; nor even that
of his collaborator Clairaut. Yet it is not to be despised, because his
work was necessary, and if France, outstripped by England in the
seventeenth century, has so well taken her revenge in the century
following, it is not alone to the genius of Clairauts, d'Alemberts,
Laplaces that she owes it; it is also to the long patience of the
Maupertuis and the La Condamines.

We reach what may be called the second heroic period of geodesy. France
is torn within. All Europe is armed against her; it would seem that
these gigantic combats might absorb all her forces. Far from it; she
still has them for the service of science. The men of that time recoiled
before no enterprise, they were men of faith.

Delambre and Méchain were commissioned to measure an arc going from
Dunkerque to Barcelona. This time there was no going to Lapland or to
Peru; the hostile squadrons had closed to us the ways thither. But,
though the expeditions are less distant, the epoch is so troubled that
the obstacles, the perils even, are just as great.

In France, Delambre had to fight against the ill-will of suspicious
municipalities. One knows that the steeples, which are visible from so
far, and can be aimed at with precision, often serve as signal points to
geodesists. But in the region Delambre traversed there were no longer
any steeples. A certain proconsul had passed there, and boasted of
knocking down all the steeples rising proudly above the humble abode of
the sans-culottes. Pyramids then were built of planks and covered with
white cloth to make them more visible. That was quite another thing:
with white cloth! What was this rash person who, upon our heights so
recently set free, dared to raise the hateful standard of the
counter-revolution? It was necessary to border the white cloth with blue
and red bands.

Méchain operated in Spain; the difficulties were other; but they were
not less. The Spanish peasants were hostile. There steeples were not
lacking: but to install oneself in them with mysterious and perhaps
diabolic instruments, was it not sacrilege? The revolutionists were
allies of Spain, but allies smelling a little of the stake.

"Without cease," writes Méchain, "they threaten to butcher us."
Fortunately, thanks to the exhortations of the priests, to the pastoral
letters of the bishops, these ferocious Spaniards contented themselves
with threatening.

Some years after Méchain made a second expedition into Spain: he
proposed to prolong the meridian from Barcelona to the Balearics. This
was the first time it had been attempted to make the triangulations
overpass a large arm of the sea by observing signals installed upon some
high mountain of a far-away isle. The enterprise was well conceived and
well prepared; it failed however.

The French scientist encountered all sorts of difficulties of which he
complains bitterly in his correspondence. "Hell," he writes, perhaps
with some exaggeration--"hell and all the scourges it vomits upon the
earth, tempests, war, the plague and black intrigues are therefore
unchained against me!"

The fact is that he encountered among his collaborators more of proud
obstinacy than of good will and that a thousand accidents retarded his
work. The plague was nothing, the fear of the plague was much more
redoubtable; all these isles were on their guard against the neighboring
isles and feared lest they should receive the scourge from them. Méchain
obtained permission to disembark only after long weeks upon the
condition of covering all his papers with vinegar; this was the
antisepsis of that time.

Disgusted and sick, he had just asked to be recalled, when he died.

Arago and Biot it was who had the honor of taking up the unfinished work
and carrying it on to completion.

Thanks to the support of the Spanish government, to the protection of
several bishops and, above all, to that of a famous brigand chief, the
operations went rapidly forward. They were successfully completed, and
Biot had returned to France when the storm burst.

It was the moment when all Spain took up arms to defend her independence
against France. Why did this stranger climb the mountains to make
signals? It was evidently to call the French army. Arago was able to
escape the populace only by becoming a prisoner. In his prison, his only
distraction was reading in the Spanish papers the account of his own
execution. The papers of that time sometimes gave out news prematurely.
He had at least the consolation of learning that he died with courage
and like a Christian.

Even the prison was no longer safe; he had to escape and reach Algiers.
There, he embarked for Marseilles on an Algerian vessel. This ship was
captured by a Spanish corsair, and behold Arago carried back to Spain
and dragged from dungeon to dungeon, in the midst of vermin and in the
most shocking wretchedness.

If it had only been a question of his subjects and his guests, the dey
would have said nothing. But there were on board two lions, a present
from the African sovereign to Napoleon. The dey threatened war.

The vessel and the prisoners were released. The port should have been
properly reached, since they had on board an astronomer; but the
astronomer was seasick, and the Algerian seamen, who wished to make
Marseilles, came out at Bougie. Thence Arago went to Algiers, traversing
Kabylia on foot in the midst of a thousand perils. He was long detained
in Africa and threatened with the convict prison. Finally he was able to
get back to France; his observations, which he had preserved and
safeguarded under his shirt, and, what is still more remarkable, his
instruments had traversed unhurt these terrible adventures. Up to this
point, not only did France hold the foremost place, but she occupied the
stage almost alone.

In the years which follow, she has not been inactive and our
staff-office map is a model. However, the new methods of observation and
calculation have come to us above all from Germany and England. It is
only in the last forty years that France has regained her rank. She owes
it to a scientific officer, General Perrier, who has successfully
executed an enterprise truly audacious, the junction of Spain and
Africa. Stations were installed on four peaks upon the two sides of the
Mediterranean. For long months they awaited a calm and limpid
atmosphere. At last was seen the little thread of light which had
traversed 300 kilometers over the sea. The undertaking had succeeded.

To-day have been conceived projects still more bold. From a mountain
near Nice will be sent signals to Corsica, not now for geodesic
determinations, but to measure the velocity of light. The distance is
only 200 kilometers; but the ray of light is to make the journey there
and return, after reflection by a mirror installed in Corsica. And it
should not wander on the way, for it must return exactly to the point of
departure.

Ever since, the activity of French geodesy has never slackened. We have
no more such astonishing adventures to tell; but the scientific work
accomplished is immense. The territory of France beyond the sea, like
that of the mother country, is covered by triangles measured with
precision.

We have become more and more exacting and what our fathers admired does
not satisfy us to-day. But in proportion as we seek more exactitude, the
difficulties greatly increase; we are surrounded by snares and must be
on our guard against a thousand unsuspected causes of error. It is
needful, therefore, to create instruments more and more faultless.

Here again France has not let herself be distanced. Our appliances for
the measurement of bases and angles leave nothing to desire, and, I may
also mention the pendulum of Colonel Defforges, which enables us to
determine gravity with a precision hitherto unknown.

The future of French geodesy is at present in the hands of the
Geographic Service of the army, successively directed by General Bassot
and General Berthaut. We can not sufficiently congratulate ourselves
upon it. For success in geodesy, scientific aptitudes are not enough; it
is necessary to be capable of standing long fatigues in all sorts of
climates; the chief must be able to win obedience from his collaborators
and to make obedient his native auxiliaries. These are military
qualities. Besides, one knows that, in our army, science has always
marched shoulder to shoulder with courage.

I add that a military organization assures the indispensable unity of
action. It would be more difficult to reconcile the rival pretensions of
scientists jealous of their independence, solicitous of what they call
their fame, and who yet must work in concert, though separated by great
distances. Among the geodesists of former times there were often
discussions, of which some aroused long echoes. The Academy long
resounded with the quarrel of Bouguer and La Condamine. I do not mean to
say that soldiers are exempt from passion, but discipline imposes
silence upon a too sensitive self-esteem.

Several foreign governments have called upon our officers to organize
their geodesic service: this is proof that the scientific influence of
France abroad has not declined.

Our hydrographic engineers contribute also to the common achievement a
glorious contingent. The survey of our coasts, of our colonies, the
study of the tides, offer them a vast domain of research. Finally I may
mention the general leveling of France which is carried out by the
ingenious and precise methods of M. Lallemand.

With such men we are sure of the future. Moreover, work for them will
not be lacking; our colonial empire opens for them immense expanses illy
explored. That is not all: the International Geodetic Association has
recognized the necessity of a new measurement of the arc of Quito,
determined in days of yore by La Condamine. It is France that has been
charged with this operation; she had every right to it, since our
ancestors had made, so to speak, the scientific conquest of the
Cordilleras. Besides, these rights have not been contested and our
government has undertaken to exercise them.

Captains Maurain and Lacombe completed a first reconnaissance, and the
rapidity with which they accomplished their mission, crossing the
roughest regions and climbing the most precipitous summits, is worthy of
all praise. It won the admiration of General Alfaro, President of the
Republic of Ecuador, who called them 'los hombres de hierro,' the men of
iron.

The final commission then set out under the command of
Lieutenant-Colonel (then Major) Bourgeois. The results obtained have
justified the hopes entertained. But our officers have encountered
unforeseen difficulties due to the climate. More than once, one of them
has been forced to remain several months at an altitude of 4,000 meters,
in the clouds and the snow, without seeing anything of the signals he
had to aim at and which refused to unmask themselves. But thanks to
their perseverance and courage, there resulted from this only a delay
and an increase of expense, without the exactitude of the measurements
suffering therefrom.



GENERAL CONCLUSIONS


What I have sought to explain in the preceding pages is how the
scientist should guide himself in choosing among the innumerable facts
offered to his curiosity, since indeed the natural limitations of his
mind compel him to make a choice, even though a choice be always a
sacrifice. I have expounded it first by general considerations,
recalling on the one hand the nature of the problem to be solved and on
the other hand seeking to better comprehend that of the human mind,
which is the principal instrument of the solution. I then have explained
it by examples; I have not multiplied them indefinitely; I also have had
to make a choice, and I have chosen naturally the questions I had
studied most. Others would doubtless have made a different choice; but
what difference, because I believe they would have reached the same
conclusions.

There is a hierarchy of facts; some have no reach; they teach us nothing
but themselves. The scientist who has ascertained them has learned
nothing but a fact, and has not become more capable of foreseeing new
facts. Such facts, it seems, come once, but are not destined to
reappear.

There are, on the other hand, facts of great yield; each of them teaches
us a new law. And since a choice must be made, it is to these that the
scientist should devote himself.

Doubtless this classification is relative and depends upon the weakness
of our mind. The facts of slight outcome are the complex facts, upon
which various circumstances may exercise a sensible influence,
circumstances too numerous and too diverse for us to discern them all.
But I should rather say that these are the facts we think complex, since
the intricacy of these circumstances surpasses the range of our mind.
Doubtless a mind vaster and finer than ours would think differently of
them. But what matter; we can not use that superior mind, but only our
own.

The facts of great outcome are those we think simple; may be they really
are so, because they are influenced only by a small number of
well-defined circumstances, may be they take on an appearance of
simplicity because the various circumstances upon which they depend obey
the laws of chance and so come to mutually compensate. And this is what
happens most often. And so we have been obliged to examine somewhat more
closely what chance is.

Facts where the laws of chance apply become easy of access to the
scientist who would be discouraged before the extraordinary complication
of the problems where these laws are not applicable. We have seen that
these considerations apply not only to the physical sciences, but to the
mathematical sciences. The method of demonstration is not the same for
the physicist and the mathematician. But the methods of invention are
very much alike. In both cases they consist in passing up from the fact
to the law, and in finding the facts capable of leading to a law.

To bring out this point, I have shown the mind of the mathematician at
work, and under three forms: the mind of the mathematical inventor and
creator; that of the unconscious geometer who among our far distant
ancestors, or in the misty years of our infancy, has constructed for us
our instinctive notion of space; that of the adolescent to whom the
teachers of secondary education unveil the first principles of the
science, seeking to give understanding of the fundamental definitions.
Everywhere we have seen the rôle of intuition and of the spirit of
generalization without which these three stages of mathematicians, if I
may so express myself, would be reduced to an equal impotence.

And in the demonstration itself, the logic is not all; the true
mathematical reasoning is a veritable induction, different in many
regards from the induction of physics, but proceeding like it from the
particular to the general. All the efforts that have been made to
reverse this order and to carry back mathematical induction to the rules
of logic have eventuated only in failures, illy concealed by the
employment of a language inaccessible to the uninitiated. The examples I
have taken from the physical sciences have shown us very different cases
of facts of great outcome. An experiment of Kaufmann on radium rays
revolutionizes at the same time mechanics, optics and astronomy. Why?
Because in proportion as these sciences have developed, we have the
better recognized the bonds uniting them, and then we have perceived a
species of general design of the chart of universal science. There are
facts common to several sciences, which seem the common source of
streams diverging in all directions and which are comparable to that
knoll of Saint Gothard whence spring waters which fertilize four
different valleys.

And then we can make choice of facts with more discernment than our
predecessors who regarded these valleys as distinct and separated by
impassable barriers.

It is always simple facts which must be chosen, but among these simple
facts we must prefer those which are situated upon these sorts of knolls
of Saint Gothard of which I have just spoken.

And when sciences have no direct bond, they still mutually throw light
upon one another by analogy. When we studied the laws obeyed by gases we
knew we had attacked a fact of great outcome; and yet this outcome was
still estimated beneath its value, since gases are, from a certain point
of view, the image of the milky way, and those facts which seemed of
interest only for the physicist, ere long opened new vistas to astronomy
quite unexpected.

And finally when the geodesist sees it is necessary to move his
telescope some seconds to see a signal he has set up with great pains,
this is a very small fact; but this is a fact of great outcome, not only
because this reveals to him the existence of a small protuberance upon
the terrestrial globe, that little hump would be by itself of no great
interest, but because this protuberance gives him information about the
distribution of matter in the interior of the globe, and through that
about the past of our planet, about its future, about the laws of its
development.


       *       *       *       *       *



INDEX


  aberration of light, 315, 496

  Abraham, 311, 490-1, 505-7, 509, 515-6

  absolute motion, 107
    orientation, 83
    space, 85, 93, 246, 257, 353

  acceleration, 94, 98, 486, 509

  accidental constant, 112
    errors, 171, 402

  accommodation of the eyes, 67-8

  action at a distance, 137

  addition, 34

  aim of mathematics, 280

  alchemists, 11

  Alfaro, 543

  algebra, 379

  analogy, 220

  analysis, 218-9, 279

  analysis situs, 53, 239, 381

  analyst, 210, 221

  ancestral experience, 91

  Andrade, 93, 104, 228

  Andrews, 153

  angle sum of triangle, 58

  Anglo-Saxons, 3

  antinomies, 449, 457, 477

  Arago, 540-1

  Aristotle, 205, 292, 460

  arithmetic, 34, 379, 441, 463

  associativity, 35

  assumptions, 451, 453

  astronomy, 81, 289, 315, 512

  Atwood, 446

  axiom, 60, 63, 65, 215


  Bacon, 128

  Bartholi, 503

  Bassot, 542

  beauty, 349, 368

  Becquerel, 312

  Beltrami, 56, 58

  Bergson, 321

  Berkeley, 4

  Berthaut, 542

  Bertrand, 156, 190, 211, 395

  Betti, 239

  Biot, 540

  bodies, solid, 72

  Boltzmann, 304

  Bolyai, 56, 201, 203

  Borel, 482

  Bouguer, 537, 542

  Bourgeois, 543

  Boutroux, 390, 464

  Bradley, 496

  Briot, 298

  Brownian movement, 152, 410

  Bucherer, 507

  Burali-Forti, 457-9, 477, 481-2


  Caen, 387-8

  Calinon, 228

  canal rays, 491-2

  canals, semicircular, 276

  Cantor, 11, 448-9, 457, 459, 477

  Cantorism, 381, 382, 480, 484

  capillarity, 298

  Carlyle, 128

  Carnot's principle, 143, 151, 300, 303-5, 399

  Cassini, 537

  cathode rays, 487-92

  cells, 217

  center of gravity, 103

  central forces, 297

  Chaldeans, 290

  chance, 395, 408

  change of position, 70
    state, 70

  chemistry of the stars, 295

  circle-squarers, 11

  Clairaut, 537-8

  Clausius, 119, 123, 143

  color sensation, 252

  Columbus, 228

  commutativity, 35-6

  compensation, 72

  complete induction, 40

  Comte, 294

  Condorcet, 411

  contingence, 340

  continuity, 173

  continuum, 43
    amorphous, 238
    mathematical, 46
    physical, 46, 240
    tridimensional, 240

  convention, 50, 93, 106, 125, 173, 208, 317, 440, 451

  convergence, 67-8

  coordinates, 244

  Copernicus, 109, 291, 354

  Coulomb, 143, 516

  Couturat, 450, 453, 456, 460, 462-3, 467, 472-6

  creation, mathematical, 383

  creed, 1

  Crémieu, 168-9, 490

  crisis, 303

  Crookes, 195, 488, 527-8

  crude fact, 326, 330

  Curie, 312-3, 318

  current, 186

  curvature, 58-9

  curve, 213, 346

  curves without tangents, 51

  cut, 52, 256

  cyclones, 353


  d'Alembert, 538

  Darwin, 518-9

  De Cyon, 276, 427

  Dedekind, 44-5

  Defforges, 542

  definitions, 430, 453

  deformation, 73, 415

  Delage, 277

  Delambre, 539

  Delbeuf, 414

  Descartes, 127

  determinism, 123, 340

  dictionary, 59

  didymium, 333

  dilatation, 76

  dimensions, 53, 68, 78, 241, 256, 426

  direction, 69

  Dirichlet, 213

  dispersion, 141

  displacement, 73, 77, 247, 256

  distance, 59, 292

  distributivity, 36

  Du Bois-Reymond, 50


  earth, rotation of, 326, 353

  eclipse, 326

  electricity, 174

  electrified bodies, 117

  electrodynamic attraction, 308
    induction, 188
    mass, 311

  electrodynamics, 184, 282

  electromagnetic theory of light, 301

  electrons, 316, 492-4, 505-8, 510, 512-4

  elephant, 217, 436

  ellipse, 215

  Emerson, 203

  empiricism, 86, 271

  Epimenides, 478-9

  equation of Laplace, 283

  Erdély, 203

  errors, accidental, 171, 402
    law of, 119
    systematic, 171, 402
    theory of, 402, 406

  ether, 145, 351

  ethics, 205

  Euclid, 62, 86, 202-3, 213

  Euclidean geometry, 65, 235-6, 337

  Euclid's postulate, 83, 91, 124, 353, 443, 453, 468, 470-1

  experience, 90-1

  experiment, 127, 317, 336, 446


  fact, crude, 326, 330
    in the rough, 327
    scientific, 326

  facts, 362, 371

  Fahrenheit, 238

  Faraday, 150, 192

  Faye, 536

  Fechner, 46, 52

  Fehr, 383

  finite, 57

  Fitzgerald, 415-6, 500-1, 505

  Fizeau, 146, 149, 309, 498, 504

  Flammarion, 400, 406-7

  flattening of the earth, 353

  force, 72, 98, 444
    direction of, 445
    -flow, 284

  forces, central, 297
    equivalence of, 445
    magnitude of, 445

  Foucault's pendulum, 85, 109, 353

  four dimensions, 78

  Fourier, 298-9

  Fourier's problem, 317
    series, 286

  Franklin, 513-4

  Fresnel, 132, 140, 153, 174, 176, 181, 351, 498

  Fuchsian, 387-8

  function, 213
    continuous, 218, 288


  Galileo, 97, 331, 353-4

  gaseous pressure, 141

  gases, theory of, 400, 405, 523

  Gauss, 384-5, 406

  Gay-Lussac, 157

  generalize, 342

  geodesy, 535

  geometer, 83, 210, 438

  geometric space, 66

  geometry, 72, 81, 125, 207, 380, 428, 442, 467
    Euclidean, 65, 93
    fourth, 62
    non-Euclidean, 55
    projective, 201
    qualitative, 238
    rational, 5, 467
    Riemann's, 57
    spheric, 59

  Gibbs, 304

  Goldstein, 492

  Gouy, 152, 305, 410

  gravitation, 512

  Greeks, 93, 368


  Hadamard, 459

  Halsted, 3, 203, 464, 467

  Hamilton, 115

  helium, 294

  Helmholtz, 56, 115, 118, 141, 190, 196

  Hercules, 449

  Hermite, 211, 220, 222, 285

  Herschel, 528

  Hertz, 102, 145, 194-5, 427, 488, 498, 502, 504, 510

  Hertzian oscillator, 309, 317

  Hilbert, 5, 11, 203, 433, 450-1, 464-8, 471, 475-7, 484

  Himstedt, 195

  Hipparchus, 291

  homogeneity, 74, 423

  homogeneous, 67

  hydrodynamics, 284

  hyperbola, 215

  hypotheses, 6, 15, 127, 133

  hysteresis, 151


  identity of spaces, 268
    of two points, 259

  illusions, optical, 202

  incommensurable numbers, 44

  induction, complete, 40, 452-3, 467-8
    electromagnetic, 188
    mathematical, 40, 220
    principle of, 481

  inertia, 93, 486, 489, 507

  infinite, 448

  infinitesimals, 50

  inquisitor, 331

  integration, 139

  interpolation, 131

  intuition, 210, 213, 215

  invariant, 333

  Ionians, 127

  ions, 152

  irrational number, 44

  irreversible phenomena, 151

  isotropic, 67


  Japanese mice, 277, 427

  Jevons, 451

  John Lackland, 128

  Jules Verne, 111, 536

  Jupiter, 131, 157, 231, 289


  Kant, 16, 64, 202-3, 450-1, 471

  Kauffman, 311, 490-1, 495, 506-7, 522, 545

  Kazan, 203

  Kelvin, 145, 523-4, 526-7

  Kepler, 120, 133, 153, 282, 291-2

  Kepler's laws, 136, 516

  kinematics, 337

  kinetic energy, 116
    theory of gases, 141

  Kirchhoff, 98-9, 103-5

  Klein, 60, 211, 287

  knowledge, 201

  König, 144, 477

  Kovalevski, 212, 286

  Kronecker, 44


  Lacombe, 543

  La Condamine, 535, 537-8, 542-3

  Lagrange, 98, 151, 179

  Laisant, 383

  Lallamand, 543

  Langevin, 509

  Laplace, 298, 398, 514-5, 518, 522, 538

  Laplace's equation, 283, 287

  Larmor, 145, 150

  Lavoisier's principle, 301, 310, 312

  law, 207, 291, 395

  Leibnitz, 32, 450, 471

  Le Roy, 28, 321-6, 332, 335, 337, 347-8, 354, 468

  Lesage, 517-21

  Liard, 440

  Lie, 62-3, 212

  light sensations, 252
    theory of, 351
    velocity of, 232, 312

  Lindemann, 508

  line, 203, 243

  linkages, 144

  Lippmann, 196

  Lobachevski, 29, 56, 60, 62, 83, 86, 203

  Lobachevski's space, 239

  local time, 306-7, 499

  logic, 214, 435, 448, 460-2, 464

  logistic, 457, 472-4

  logisticians, 472

  Lorentz, 147, 149, 196-7, 306, 308, 311, 315, 415-6, 492, 498-502,
            504-9, 512, 514-6, 521

  Lotze, 264

  luck, 399

  Lumen, 407-8


  MacCullagh, 150

  Mach, 375

  Mach-Delage, 276

  magnetism, 149

  magnitude, 49

  Mariotte's law, 120, 132, 157, 342, 524

  Maros, 203

  mass, 98, 312, 446, 486, 489, 494, 515

  mathematical analysis, 218
    continuum, 46
    creation, 383
    induction, 40, 220
    physics, 136, 297, 319

  mathematics, 369, 448

  matter, 492

  Maupertuis, 535, 537-8

  Maurain, 543

  Maxwell, 140, 152, 175, 177, 181, 193, 282-3, 298, 301, 304-5, 351,
            503, 524-5

  Maxwell-Bartholi, 309, 503-4, 519, 521

  Mayer, 119, 123, 300, 312, 318

  measurement, 49

  Méchain, 539-40

  mechanical explanation, 177
    mass, 312

  mechanics, 92, 444, 486, 496, 512
    anthropomorphic, 103
    celestial, 279
    statistical, 304

  Méray, 211

  metaphysician, 221

  meteorology, 398

  mice, 277

  Michelson, 306, 309, 311, 316, 498, 500-1

  milky way, 523-30

  Mill, Stuart, 60-1, 453-4

  Monist, 4, 89, 464

  moons of Jupiter, 233

  Morley, 309

  motion of liquids, 283
    of moon, 28
    of planets, 341
    relative, 107, 487
    without deformation, 236

  multiplication, 36

  muscular sensations, 69


  Nagaoka, 317

  nature, 127

  navigation, 289

  neodymium, 333

  neomonics, 283

  Neumann, 181

  Newton, 85, 96, 98, 109, 153, 291, 370, 486, 516, 536, 538

  Newton's argument, 108, 334, 343
    law, 111, 118, 132, 136, 149, 157, 233, 282, 292, 512, 514-5,
            518, 525
    principle, 146, 300, 308-9, 312

  no-class theory, 478

  nominalism, 28, 125, 321, 333, 335

  non-Euclidean geometry, 55, 59, 388
    language, 127
    space, 55, 235, 237
    straight, 236, 470
    world, 75

  number, 31
    big, 88
    imaginary, 283
    incommensurable, 44
    transfinite, 448-9
    whole, 44, 469


  objectivity, 209, 347, 349, 408

  optical illusions, 202

  optics, 174, 496

  orbit of Saturn, 341

  order, 385

  orientation, 83

  osmotic, 141


  Padoa, 463

  Panthéon, 414

  parallax, 470

  parallels, 56, 443

  Paris time, 233

  parry, 419-22, 427

  partition, 45

  pasigraphy, 456-7

  Pasteur, 128

  Peano, 450, 456-9, 463, 472

  Pender, 490

  pendulum, 224

  Perrier, 541

  Perrin, 195

  phosphorus, 333, 468, 470-1

  physical continuum, 46

  physics, 127, 140, 144, 279, 297

  physics of central forces, 297
    of the principles, 299

  Pieri, 11, 203

  Plato, 292

  Poincaré, 473

  point, 89, 244

  Poncelet, 215

  postulates, 382

  potential energy, 116

  praseodymium, 333

  principle, 125, 299
    Carnot's, 143, 151, 300, 303-5, 399
    Clausius', 119, 123, 143
    Hamilton's, 115
    Lavoisier's, 300, 310
    Mayer's, 119, 121, 123, 300, 312, 318
    Newton's, 146, 300, 308-9, 312
    of action and reaction, 300, 487, 502
    of conservation of energy, 300
    of degradation of energy, 300
    of inertia, 93, 486, 507
    of least action, 118, 300
    of relativity, 300, 305, 498, 505

  Prony, 445

  psychologist, 383

  Ptolemy, 110, 291, 353-4

  Pythagoras, 292


  quadrature of the circle, 161

  qualitative geometry, 238
    space, 207
    time, 224

  quaternions, 282


  radiometer, 503

  radium, 312, 318, 486-7

  Rados, 201

  Ramsay, 313

  rational geometry, 5, 467

  reaction, 502

  reality, 217, 340, 349

  Réaumur, 238

  recurrence, 37

  Regnault, 170

  relativity, 83, 305, 417, 423, 498, 505

  Richard, 477-8, 480-1

  Riemann, 56, 62, 145, 212, 239, 243, 381, 432
    surface, 211, 287

  Roemer, 233

  Röntgen, 511, 520

  rotation of earth, 225, 331, 353

  roulette, 403

  Rowland, 194-7, 305, 489

  Royce, 202

  Russell, 201, 450, 460-2, 464-7, 471-4, 477-82, 484-5


  St. Louis exposition, 208, 320

  Sarcey, 442

  Saturn, 231, 317

  Schiller, 202

  Schliemann, 19

  science, 205, 321, 323, 340, 354

  Science and Hypothesis, 205-7, 220, 240, 246-7, 319, 353, 452

  semicircular canals, 276

  series, development in, 287
    Fourier's, 286

  Sirius, 226, 229

  solid bodies, 72

  space, 55, 66, 89, 235, 256
    absolute, 85, 93
    amorphous, 417
    Bolyai, 56
    Euclidean, 65
    geometric, 66
    Lobachevski's, 239
    motor, 69
    non-Euclidean, 55, 235, 237
    of four dimensions, 78
    perceptual, 66, 69
    tactile, 68, 264
    visual, 67, 252

  spectra, 316

  spectroscope, 294

  Spencer, 9

  sponge, 219

  Stallo, 10

  stars, 292

  statistical mechanics, 304

  straight, 62, 82, 236, 433, 450, 470

  Stratonoff, 531

  surfaces, 58

  systematic errors, 171


  tactile space, 68, 264

  Tait, 98

  tangent, 51

  Tannery, 43

  teaching, 430, 437

  thermodynamics, 115, 119

  Thomson, 98, 488

  thread, 104

  time, 223
    equality, 225
    local, 306, 307
    measure of, 223-4

  Tisserand, 515-6

  Tolstoi, 354, 362, 368

  Tommasina, 519

  Transylvania, 203

  triangle, 58
    angle sum of, 58

  truth, 205

  Tycho Brahe, 133, 153, 228


  unity of nature, 130

  universal invariant, 333

  Uriel, 203


  van der Waals, 153

  Vauban, 210

  Veblen, 203

  velocity of light, 232, 312

  Venus of Milo, 201

  verification, 33

  Virchow, 21

  visual impressions, 252
    space, 67, 252

  Volga, 203

  Voltaire, 537-8


  Weber, 117, 515-6

  Weierstrass, 11, 212, 432

  Whitehead, 472, 481-2

  whole numbers, 44

  Wiechert, 145, 488


  x-rays, 152, 511, 520


  Zeeman effect, 152, 196, 317, 494

  Zeno, 382

  Zermelo, 477, 482-3

  zigzag theory, 478

  zodiac, 398, 404


       *       *       *       *       *


Transcriber's Note: The Greek alphabets are represented within square
brackets. For example, [alpha] stands for first Greek alphabet alpha.
Square root of a number is represented using the symbol (sqrt). That
is to say, sqrt(25) stands for square root of 25. The superscript is
shown with carat (^) symbol, example, 10^{5} stands for 5th power of
10. Similarly, subscript is represented by underscore (_) symbol. For
instance, n_{3} stands for letter n with subscript 3.





*** End of this LibraryBlog Digital Book "The Foundations of Science: Science and Hypothesis, The Value of Science, Science and Method" ***

Copyright 2023 LibraryBlog. All rights reserved.



Home