Home
  By Author [ A  B  C  D  E  F  G  H  I  J  K  L  M  N  O  P  Q  R  S  T  U  V  W  X  Y  Z |  Other Symbols ]
  By Title [ A  B  C  D  E  F  G  H  I  J  K  L  M  N  O  P  Q  R  S  T  U  V  W  X  Y  Z |  Other Symbols ]
  By Language
all Classics books content using ISYS

Download this book: [ ASCII ]

Look for this book on Amazon


We have new books nearly every day.
If you would like a news letter once a week or once a month
fill out this form and we will give you a summary of the books for that week or month by email.

Title: The Copernicus of Antiquity - Aristarchus of Samos
Author: Heath, Thomas Little, Sir
Language: English
As this book started as an ASCII text book there are no pictures available.


*** Start of this LibraryBlog Digital Book "The Copernicus of Antiquity - Aristarchus of Samos" ***


  PIONEERS OF PROGRESS

  MEN OF SCIENCE
  EDITED BY S. CHAPMAN, M.A., D.Sc., F.R.S.


  THE
  COPERNICUS OF ANTIQUITY
  (ARISTARCHUS OF SAMOS)


  BY
  SIR THOMAS HEATH
  K.C.B., K.C.V.O., F.R.S.; SC.D., CAMB.; HON. D.SC., OXFORD


  LONDON:
  SOCIETY FOR PROMOTING
  CHRISTIAN KNOWLEDGE
  NEW YORK: THE MACMILLAN COMPANY
  1920



CONTENTS


  PART I
  GREEK ASTRONOMY TO ARISTARCHUS
                                                          PAGE
  THALES                                                     6

  ANAXIMANDER                                               10

  ANAXIMENES                                                13

  PYTHAGORAS                                                14

  PARMENIDES                                                16

  ANAXAGORAS                                                18

  EMPEDOCLES                                                21

  THE PYTHAGOREANS                                          22

  ŒNOPIDES OF CHIOS                                         24

  PLATO                                                     25

  EUDOXUS, CALLIPPUS, ARISTOTLE                             28

  HERACLIDES OF PONTUS                                      33


  PART II
  ARISTARCHUS OF SAMOS

  THE HELIOCENTRIC HYPOTHESIS                               39

  ON THE APPARENT DIAMETER OF THE SUN                       42

  ON THE SIZES AND DISTANCES OF THE SUN AND MOON            43

  ON THE YEAR AND “GREAT YEAR”                              53

  LATER IMPROVEMENTS ON ARISTARCHUS’S FIGURES               54


  BIBLIOGRAPHY                                              57

  CHRONOLOGY                                                59


[Illustration: COPERNICUS’S DIAGRAM OF HIS SYSTEM (ANTICIPATED BY
ARISTARCHUS).]



PART I.

GREEK ASTRONOMY TO ARISTARCHUS.


The title-page of this book necessarily bears the name of one man;
but the reader will find in its pages the story, or part of the
story, of many other Pioneers of Progress. The crowning achievement
of anticipating the hypothesis of Copernicus belongs to Aristarchus
of Samos alone; but to see it in its proper setting it is necessary
to have followed in the footsteps of the earlier pioneers who, by one
bold speculation after another, brought the solution of the problem
nearer, though no one before Aristarchus actually hit upon the truth.
This is why the writer has thought it useful to prefix to his account
of Aristarchus a short sketch of the history of the development of
astronomy in Greece down to Aristarchus’s time, which is indeed the
most fascinating portion of the story of Greek astronomy.

The extraordinary advance in astronomy made by the Greeks in a period
of little more than three centuries is a worthy parallel to the rapid
development, in their hands, of pure geometry, which, created by
them as a theoretical science about the same time, had by the time
of Aristarchus covered the ground of the Elements (including solid
geometry and the geometry of the sphere), had established the main
properties of the three conic sections, had solved problems which were
beyond the geometry of the straight line and circle, and finally,
before the end of the third century B.C., had been carried to its
highest perfection by the genius of Archimedes, who measured the
areas of curves and the surfaces and volumes of curved surfaces by
geometrical methods practically anticipating the integral calculus.

To understand how all this was possible we have to remember that the
Greeks, pre-eminently among all the nations of the world, possessed
just those gifts which are essential to the initiation and development
of philosophy and science. They had in the first place a remarkable
power of accurate observation; and to this were added clearness of
intellect to see things as they are, a passionate love of knowledge
for its own sake, and a genius for speculation which stands unrivalled
to this day. Nothing that is perceptible to the senses seems to
have escaped them; and when the apparent facts had been accurately
ascertained, they wanted to know the _why_ and the _wherefore_, never
resting satisfied until they had given a rational explanation, or what
seemed to them to be such, of the phenomena observed. Observation or
experiment and theory went hand in hand. So it was that they developed
such subjects as medicine and astronomy. In astronomy their guiding
principle was, in their own expressive words, to “save the phenomena”.
This meant that, as more and more facts became known, their theories
were continually revised to fit them.

It would be easy to multiply instances; it must suffice in this place
to mention one, which illustrates not only the certainty with which the
Greeks detected the occurrence of even the rarest phenomena, but also
the persistence with which they sought for the true explanation.

Cleomedes (second century A.D.) mentions that there were stories of
extraordinary eclipses which “the more ancient of the mathematicians”
had vainly tried to explain; the supposed “paradoxical” case was that
in which, while the sun seems to be still above the western horizon,
the _eclipsed_ moon is seen to rise in the east. The phenomenon
appeared to be inconsistent with the explanation of lunar eclipses by
the entry of the moon into the earth’s shadow; how could this be if
both bodies were above the horizon at the same time? The “more ancient”
mathematicians essayed a geometrical explanation; they tried to argue
that it was possible that a spectator standing on an _eminence_ of
the spherical earth might see along the generators of a _cone_ i.e. a
little downwards on all sides instead of merely in the plane of the
horizon, and so might see both the sun and the moon even when the
latter was in the earth’s shadow. Cleomedes denies this and prefers to
regard the whole story of such cases as a fiction designed merely for
the purpose of plaguing astronomers and philosophers; no Chaldæan, he
says, no Egyptian, and no mathematician or philosopher has recorded
such a case. But the phenomenon is possible, and it is certain that
it had been observed in Greece and that the Greek astronomers did not
rest until they had found out the solution of the puzzle; for Cleomedes
himself gives the explanation, namely that the phenomenon is due to
atmospheric refraction. Observing that such cases of atmospheric
refraction were especially noticeable in the neighbourhood of the Black
Sea, Cleomedes goes on to say that it is possible that the visual rays
going out from our eyes are refracted through falling on wet and damp
air, and so reach the sun although it is already below the horizon;
and he compares the well-known experiment of the ring at the bottom
of a jug, where the ring, just out of sight when the jug is empty, is
brought into view when water is poured in.

The genius of the race being what it was, the Greeks must from the
earliest times have been in the habit of scanning the heavens, and, as
might be expected, we find the beginnings of astronomical knowledge in
the earliest Greek literature.

In the Homeric poems and in Hesiod the earth is a flat circular disc;
round this disc runs the river Oceanus, encircling the earth and
flowing back into itself. The flat earth has above it the vault of
heaven, like a sort of hemispherical dome exactly covering it; this
vault remains for ever in one position; the sun, moon and stars move
round under it, rising from Oceanus in the east and plunging into it
again in the west.

Homer mentions, in addition to the sun and moon, the Morning Star, the
Evening Star, the Pleiades, the Hyades, Orion, the Great Bear (“which
is also called by the name of the Wain”), Sirius, the late-setting
Boötes (the ploughman driving the Wain), i.e. Arcturus, as it was first
called by Hesiod. Of the Great Bear Homer says that it turns round on
the same spot and watches Orion; it alone is without lot in Oceanus’s
bath (i.e. it never sets). With regard to the last statement it is to
be noted that some of the principal stars of the Great Bear do now set
in the Mediterranean, e.g. in places further south than Rhodes (lat.
36°), γ, the hind foot, and η, the tip of the tail, and at Alexandria
all the seven stars except α, the head. It might be supposed that here
was a case of Homer “nodding”. But no; the old poet was perfectly
right; the difference between the facts as observed by him and as seen
by us respectively is due to the Precession of the Equinoxes, the
gradual movement of the fixed stars themselves about the pole of the
ecliptic, which was discovered by Hipparchus (second century B.C.).
We know from the original writings of the Greek astronomers that in
Eudoxus’s time (say 380 B.C.) the whole of the Great Bear remained
always well above the horizon, while in the time of Proclus (say A.D.
460) the Great Bear “grazed” the horizon.

In Homer astronomical phenomena are only vaguely used for such purposes
as fixing localities or marking times of day or night. Sometimes
constellations are used in giving sailing directions, as when Calypso
directs Odysseus to sail in such a way as always to keep the Great Bear
on his left.

Hesiod mentions practically the same stars as Homer, but makes more use
of celestial phenomena for determining times and seasons. For example,
he marked the time for sowing at the beginning of winter by the setting
of the Pleiades in the early twilight, or again by the early setting
of the Hyades or Orion, which means the 3rd, 7th, or 15th November in
the Julian calendar according to the particular stars taken; the time
for harvest he fixed by the early rising of the Pleiades (19th May),
threshing time by the early rising of Orion (9th July), vintage time by
the early rising of Arcturus (18th September), and so on. Hesiod makes
spring begin sixty days after the winter solstice, and the early summer
fifty days after the summer solstice. Thus he knew about the solstices,
though he says nothing of the equinoxes. He had an approximate notion
of the moon’s period, which he put at thirty days.

But this use of astronomical facts for the purpose of determining times
and seasons or deducing weather indications is a very different thing
from the science of astronomy, which seeks to explain the heavenly
phenomena and their causes. The history of this science, as of Greek
philosophy in general, begins with Thales.

The Ionian Greeks were in the most favourable position for initiating
philosophy. Foremost among the Greeks in the love of adventure and the
instinct of new discovery (as is shown by their leaving their homes to
found settlements in distant lands), and fired, like all Greeks, with
a passion for knowledge, they needed little impulse to set them on the
road of independent thought and speculation. This impulse was furnished
by their contact with two ancient civilisations, the Egyptian and the
Babylonian. Acquiring from them certain elementary facts and rules
in mathematics and astronomy which had been handed down through the
priesthood from remote antiquity, they built upon them the foundation
of the science, as distinct from the mere routine, of the subjects in
question.


THALES.

Thales of Miletus (about 624–547 B.C.) was a man of extraordinary
versatility; philosopher, mathematician, astronomer, statesman,
engineer, and man of business, he was declared one of the Seven Wise
Men in 582–581 B.C. His propensity to star-gazing is attested by the
story of his having fallen into a well while watching the stars,
insomuch that (as Plato has it) he was rallied by a clever and pretty
maidservant from Thrace for being so “eager to know what goes on in the
heavens when he could not see what was in front of him, nay at his very
feet”.

Thales’s claim to a place in the history of scientific astronomy rests
on one achievement attributed to him, that of predicting an eclipse
of the sun. The evidence for this is fairly conclusive, though the
accounts of it differ slightly. Eudemus, the pupil of Aristotle, who
wrote histories of Greek geometry and astronomy, is quoted by three
different Greek writers as the authority for the story. But there is
testimony much earlier than this. Herodotus, speaking of a war between
the Lydians and the Medes, says that, “when in the sixth year they
encountered one another, it fell out that, after they had joined
battle, the day suddenly turned into night. Now that this change of
day into night would occur was foretold to the Ionians by Thales of
Miletus, who fixed as the limit of time this very year in which the
change took place.” Moreover Xenophanes, who was born some twenty-three
years before Thales’s death, is said to have lauded Thales’s
achievement; this would amount to almost contemporary evidence.

Could Thales have known the cause of solar eclipses? Aëtius (A.D.
100), the author of an epitome of an older collection of the opinions
of philosophers, says that Thales was the first to declare that the
sun is eclipsed when the moon comes in a direct line below it, the
image of the moon then appearing on the sun’s disc as on a mirror;
he also associates Thales with Anaxagoras, Plato, Aristotle, and the
Stoics as holding that the moon is eclipsed by reason of its falling
into the shadow made by the earth when the earth is between the sun
and the moon. But, as regards the eclipse of the moon, Thales could
not have given this explanation, because he held that the earth (which
he presumably regarded as a flat disc) floated on the water like a
log. And if he had given the true explanation of a solar eclipse, it
is impossible that all the succeeding Ionian philosophers should have
exhausted their imaginations in other fanciful explanations such as we
find recorded.

The key to the puzzle may be afforded by the passage of Herodotus
according to which the prediction was a rough one, only specifying
that the eclipse would occur within a certain year. The prediction was
probably one of the same kind as had long been made by the Chaldæans.
The Chaldæans, no doubt as the result of observations continued
through many centuries, had discovered the period of 223 lunations
after which lunar eclipses recur. (This method would very often fail
for solar eclipses because no account was taken of parallax; and
Assyrian cuneiform inscriptions record failures as well as successful
predictions.) Thales, then, probably learnt about the period of 223
lunations either in Egypt or more directly through Lydia, which was an
outpost of Assyrio-Babylonian culture. If there happened to be a number
of _possible_ solar eclipses in the year which (according to Herodotus)
Thales fixed for the eclipse, he was, in using the Chaldæan rule, not
taking an undue risk; but it was great luck that the eclipse should
have been total. It seems practically certain that the eclipse in
question was that of the (Julian) 28th May, 585.

Thales, as we have seen, made the earth a circular or cylindrical
disc floating on the water like a log or a cork and, so far as we can
judge of his general conception of the universe, he would appear to
have regarded it as a mass of water (that on which the earth floats)
with the heavens encircling it in the form of a hemisphere and also
bounded by the primeval water. This view of the world has been compared
with that found in ancient Egyptian papyri. In the beginning existed
the _Nū_, a primordial liquid mass in the limitless depths of which
floated the germs of things. When the sun began to shine, the earth was
flattened out and the water separated into two masses. The one gave
rise to the rivers and the ocean, the other, suspended above, formed
the vault of heaven, the waters above, on which the stars and the gods,
borne by an eternal current, began to float. The sun, standing upright
in his sacred barque which had endured for millions of years, glides
slowly, conducted by an army of secondary gods, the planets and the
fixed stars. The assumption of an upper and lower ocean is also old
Babylonian (cf. the division in Genesis 1. 7 of the waters which were
under the firmament from the waters which were above the firmament).

It would follow from Thales’s general view of the universe that the
sun, moon and stars did not, between their setting and rising again,
continue their circular path below the earth but (as with Anaximenes
later) moved laterally round the earth.

Thales’s further contributions to observational astronomy may be
shortly stated. He wrote two works _On the solstice_ and _On the
equinox_, and he is said by Eudemus to have discovered that “the
period of the sun with respect to the solstices is not always the
same,” which probably means that he discovered the inequality of the
four astronomical seasons. His division of the year into 365 days he
probably learnt from the Egyptians. He said of the Hyades that there
are two, one north and the other south. He observed the Little Bear and
used it as a means of finding the pole; he advised the Greeks to follow
the Phœnician plan of sailing by the Little Bear in preference to their
own habit of steering by the Great Bear.

Limited as the certain contributions of Thales to astronomy are,
it became the habit of the Greek _Doxographi_, or retailers of the
opinions of philosophers, to attribute to Thales, in common with other
astronomers in each case, a number of discoveries which were not made
till later. The following is a list, with (in brackets) the names
of the astronomers to whom the respective discoveries may with most
certainty be assigned: (1) the fact that the moon takes its light from
the sun (Anaxagoras), (2) the sphericity of the earth (Pythagoras), (3)
the division of the heavenly sphere into five zones (Pythagoras and
Parmenides), (4) the obliquity of the ecliptic (Œnopides of Chios),
and (5) the estimate of the sun’s apparent diameter as 1/720th of the
sun’s circle (Aristarchus of Samos).


ANAXIMANDER.

Anaximander (about 611–547 B.C.), a contemporary and fellow-citizen
of Thales, was a remarkably original thinker. He was the first Greek
philosopher who ventured to put forward his views in a formal written
treatise. This was a work _About Nature_ and was not given to the world
till he was about sixty-four years old. His originality is illustrated
by his theory of evolution. According to him animals first arose from
slime evaporated by the sun; they lived in the sea and had prickly
coverings; men at first resembled fishes.

But his astronomical views were not less remarkable. Anaximander boldly
maintained that the earth is in the centre of the universe, suspended
freely and without support, whereas Thales regarded it as resting on
the water and Anaximenes as supported by the air. It remains in its
position, said Anaximander, because it is at an equal distance from
all the rest of the heavenly bodies. The earth was, according to him,
cylinder-shaped, round “like a stone pillar”; one of its two plane
faces is that on which we stand; its depth is one-third of its breadth.

Anaximander postulated as his first principle, not water (like Thales)
or any of the elements, but the Infinite; this was a substance, not
further defined, from which all the heavens and the worlds in them
were produced; according to him the worlds themselves were infinite in
number, and there were always some worlds coming into being and others
passing away _ad infinitum_. The origin of the stars, and their nature,
he explained as follows. “That which is capable of begetting the hot
and the cold out of the eternal was separated off during the coming
into being of our world, and from the flame thus produced a sort of
sphere was made which grew round the air about the earth as the bark
round the tree; then this sphere was torn off and became enclosed in
certain circles or rings, and thus were formed the sun, the moon and
the stars.” “The stars are produced as a circle of fire, separated
off from the fire in the universe and enclosed by air. They have as
vents certain pipe-shaped passages at which the stars are seen.” “The
stars are compressed portions of air, in the shape of wheels filled
with fire, and they emit flames at some point from small openings.”
“The stars are borne round by the circles in which they are enclosed.”
“The sun is a circle twenty-eight times (_v. l._ 27 times) the size of
the earth; it is like a wheel of a chariot the rim of which is hollow
and full of fire and lets the fire shine out at a certain point in it
through an opening like the tube of a blow-pipe; such is the sun.” “The
sun is equal to the earth.” “The eclipses of the sun occur through
the opening by which the fire finds vent being shut up.” “The moon
is a circle nineteen times the size of the earth; it is similar to a
chariot-wheel the rim of which is hollow and full of fire like the
circle of the sun, and it is placed obliquely like the other; it has
one vent like the tube of a blow-pipe; the eclipses of the moon depend
on the turnings of the wheel.” “The moon is eclipsed when the opening
in the rim of the wheel is stopped up.” “The moon appears sometimes as
waxing, sometimes as waning, to an extent corresponding to the closing
or opening of the passages.” “The sun is placed highest of all, after
it the moon, and under them the fixed stars and the planets.”

It has been pointed out that the idea of the formation of tubes of
compressed air within which the fire of each star is shut up except
for the one opening through which the flame shows (like a gas-jet,
as it were) is not unlike Laplace’s hypothesis with reference to the
origin of Saturn’s rings. In any case it is a sufficiently original
conception.

When Anaximander says that the hoops carrying the sun and moon “lie
obliquely,” this is no doubt an attempt to explain, in addition to the
daily rotation, the annual movement of the sun and the monthly movement
of the moon.

We have here too the first speculation about the sizes and distances of
the heavenly bodies. The sun is as large as the earth. The ambiguity
between the estimates of the size of the sun’s circle as twenty-seven
or twenty-eight times the size of the earth suggests that it is a
question between taking the inner and outer circumferences of the sun’s
ring respectively, and a similar ambiguity may account for the circle
of the moon being stated to be nineteen times, not eighteen times, the
size of the earth. No estimate is given of the distance of the planets
from the earth, but as, according to Anaximander, they are nearer to
the earth than the sun and moon are, it is possible that, if a figure
had been stated, it would have been nine times the size of the earth,
in which case we should have had the numbers 9, 18, 27, three terms in
arithmetical progression and all of them multiples of 9, the square
of 3. It seems probable that these figures were not arrived at by any
calculation based on geometrical considerations, but that we have here
merely an illustration of the ancient cult of the sacred numbers 3
and 9. Three is the sacred number in Homer, 9 in Theognis. The cult
of 3 and its multiples 9 and 27 is found among the Aryans, then among
the Finns and Tartars and then again among the Etruscans. Therefore
Anaximander’s figures probably say little more than what the Indians
tell us, namely, that three Vishnu-steps reach from earth to heaven.

Anaximander is said to have been the first to discover the _gnomon_
(or sun-dial with a vertical needle). This is, however, incorrect,
for Herodotus says that the Greeks learnt the use of the _gnomon_ and
the _polos_ from the Babylonians. Anaximander may have been the first
to introduce the gnomon into Greece. He is said to have set it up in
Sparta and to have shown on it “the solstices, the times, the seasons,
and the equinox”.

But Anaximander has another title to fame. He was the first who
ventured to draw a map of the inhabited earth. The Egyptians indeed had
drawn maps before, but only of special districts. Anaximander boldly
planned out the whole world with “the circumference of the earth and of
the sea”. Hecataeus, a much-travelled man, is said to have corrected
Anaximander’s map so that it became the object of general admiration.


ANAXIMENES.

With Anaximenes of Miletus (about 585–528/4 B.C.) the earth is still
flat like a table, but, instead of being suspended freely without
support as with Anaximander, it is supported by the air, riding on it
as it were. The sun, moon and stars are all made of fire and (like the
earth) they ride on the air because of their breadth. The sun is flat
like a leaf. Anaximenes also held that the stars are fastened on a
crystal sphere like nails or studs. It seems clear therefore that by
the stars which “ride on the air because of their breadth” he meant
the planets only. A like apparent inconsistency applies to the motion
of the stars. If the stars are fixed in the crystal sphere like nails,
they must be carried round complete circles by the revolution of the
sphere about a diameter. Yet Anaximenes also said that the stars do
not move or revolve _under_ the earth as some suppose, but _round_
the earth, just as a cap can be turned round on the head. The sun is
hidden from sight, not because it is under the earth, but because it
is covered by the higher parts of the earth and because its distance
from us is greater. Aristotle adds the detail that the sun is carried
round the northern portion of the earth and produces night because the
earth is lofty towards the north. We must again conclude that the stars
which, like the sun and moon, move laterally round the earth between
their setting and rising again are the planets, as distinct from the
fixed stars. It would therefore seem that Anaximenes was the first
to distinguish the planets from the fixed stars in respect of their
irregular movements. He improved on Anaximander in that he relegated
the fixed stars to the region most distant from the earth.

Anaximenes was also original in holding that, in the region occupied
by the stars, bodies of an earthy nature are carried round along with
them. The object of these invisible bodies of an earthy nature carried
round along with the stars is clearly to explain the eclipses and
phases of the moon. It was doubtless this conception which, in the
hands of Anaxagoras and others, ultimately led to the true explanation
of eclipses.

The one feature of Anaximenes’s system which was destined to an
enduring triumph was the conception of the stars being fixed on
a crystal sphere as in a rigid frame. This really remained the
fundamental principle in all astronomy down to Copernicus.


PYTHAGORAS.

With Pythagoras and the Pythagoreans we come to a different order of
things. Pythagoras, born at Samos about 572 B.C., is undoubtedly one
of the greatest names in the history of science. He was a mathematician
of brilliant achievements; he was also the inventor of the science of
acoustics, an astronomer of great originality, a theologian and moral
reformer, and the founder of a brotherhood which admits comparison
with the orders of mediæval chivalry. Perhaps his most epoch-making
discovery was that of the dependence of musical tones on numerical
proportions, the octave representing the proportion of 2 : 1 in length
of string at the same tension, the fifth 3 : 2, and the fourth 4 : 3.
Mathematicians know him as the reputed discoverer of the famous theorem
about the square on the hypotenuse of a right-angled triangle (= Euclid
I. 47); but he was also the first to make geometry a part of a liberal
education and to explore its first principles (definitions, etc.).

Pythagoras is said to have been the first to maintain that the earth
is spherical in shape; on what ground, is uncertain. One suggestion
is that he may have argued from the roundness of the shadow cast by
the earth in the eclipses of the moon; but Anaxagoras was the first
to give the true explanation of such eclipses. Probably Pythagoras
attributed spherical shape to the earth for the mathematical or
mathematico-æsthetical reason that the sphere is the most beautiful of
all solid figures. It is probable too, and for the same reason, that
Pythagoras gave the same spherical shape to the sun and moon, and even
to the stars, in which case the way lay open for the discovery of the
true cause of eclipses and of the phases of the moon. Pythagoras is
also said to have distinguished five zones in the earth. It is true
that the first declaration that the earth is spherical and that it has
five zones is alternatively attributed to Parmenides (born perhaps
about 516 or 514 B.C.), on the good authority of Theophrastus. It is
possible that, although Pythagoras was the real author of these views,
Parmenides was the first to state them in public.

Pythagoras regarded the universe as living, intelligent, spherical,
enclosing the earth at the centre, and rotating about an axis passing
through the centre of the earth, the earth remaining at rest.

He is said to have been the first to observe that the planets have an
independent motion of their own in a direction opposite to that of the
fixed stars, i.e. the daily rotation. Alternatively with Parmenides he
is said to have been the first to recognise that the Morning and the
Evening Stars are one and the same. Pythagoras is hardly likely to have
known this as the result of observations of his own; he may have learnt
it from Egypt or Chaldæa along with other facts about the planets.


PARMENIDES.

We have seen that certain views are alternatively ascribed to
Pythagoras and Parmenides. The system of Parmenides was in fact a kind
of blend of the theories of Pythagoras and Anaximander. In giving
the earth spherical form with five zones he agreed with Pythagoras.
Pythagoras, however, made the spherical universe rotate about an axis
through the centre of the earth; this implied that the universe is
itself limited, but that something exists round it, and in fact that
beyond the finite rotating sphere there is limitless void or empty
space. Parmenides, on the other hand, denied the existence of the
infinite void and was therefore obliged to make his finite sphere
motionless and to hold that its apparent rotation is only an illusion.

In other portions of his system Parmenides followed the lead of
Anaximander. Like Anaximander (and Democritus later) he argued that
the earth remains in the centre because, being equidistant from all
points on the sphere of the universe, it is in equilibrium and there
is no more reason why it should tend to move in one direction than in
another. Parmenides also had a system of wreaths or bands round the
sphere of the universe which contained the sun, the moon and the stars;
the wreaths remind us of the hoops of Anaximander, but their nature is
different. The wreaths, according to the most probable interpretation
of the texts, are, starting from the outside, (1) a solid envelope like
a wall; (2) a band of fire (the æther-fire); (3) mixed bands, made up
of light and darkness in combination, which exhibit the phenomenon of
“fire shining out here and there,” these mixed bands including the
Milky Way as well as the sun, moon and planets; (4) a band of fire, the
inner side of which is our atmosphere, touching the earth. Except that
Parmenides placed the Morning Star first in the æther and therefore
above the sun, he did not apparently differ from Anaximander’s view of
the relative distances of the heavenly bodies, according to which both
the planets and the other stars are all placed below the sun and moon.

Two lines from Parmenides’s poem have been quoted to show that he
declared that the moon is illuminated by the sun. The first line
speaks of the moon as “a night-shining foreign light wandering round
the earth”; but, even if the line is genuine, “foreign” need not mean
“borrowed”. The other line speaks of the moon as “always fixing its
gaze on the sun”; but, though this states an observed fact, it is
far from explaining the cause. We have, moreover, positive evidence
against the attribution of the discovery of the opacity of the moon to
Parmenides. It is part of the connected prose description of his system
that the moon is a mixture of air and fire, and in other passages we
are told that he held the moon to be of fire. Lastly, Plato speaks of
“the fact which Anaxagoras _lately asserted_, that the moon has its
light from the sun”. It seems impossible that Plato would speak in such
terms if the fact in question had been stated for the first time either
by Parmenides or by the Pythagoreans.


ANAXAGORAS.

Anaxagoras, a man of science if ever there was one, was born at
Clazomenae in the neighbourhood of Smyrna about 500 B.C. He neglected
his possessions, which were considerable, in order to devote himself
to science. Someone once asked him what was the object of being born,
and he replied, “The investigation of sun, moon and heaven”. He took
up his abode at Athens, where he enjoyed the friendship of Pericles.
When Pericles became unpopular shortly before the outbreak of the
Peloponnesian war, he was attacked through his friends, and Anaxagoras
was accused of impiety for declaring that the sun was a red-hot stone
and the moon made of earth. One account says that he was fined and
banished; another that he was imprisoned, and that it was intended to
put him to death, but that Pericles obtained his release; he retired to
Lampsacus, where he died at the age of seventy-two.

One epoch-making discovery belongs to him, namely, that the moon does
not shine by its own light but receives its light from the sun: Plato,
as we have seen, is one authority for this statement. Plutarch also
in his _De facie in orbe lunae_ says, “Now when our comrade in his
discourse had expounded that proposition of Anaxagoras that ‘the sun
places the brightness in the moon,’ he was greatly applauded”.

This discovery enabled Anaxagoras to say that “the obscurations of
the moon month by month were due to its following the course of the
sun by which it is illuminated, and the eclipses of the moon were
caused by its falling within the shadow of the earth which then comes
between the sun and the moon, while the eclipses of the sun were due
to the interposition of the moon”. Anaxagoras was therefore the first
to give the true explanation of eclipses. As regards the phases of the
moon, his explanation could only have been complete if he had known
that the moon is spherical; in fact, however, he considered the earth
(and doubtless the other heavenly bodies also) to be flat. To his true
theory of eclipses Anaxagoras added the unnecessary assumption that
the moon was sometimes eclipsed by other earthy bodies below the moon
but invisible to us. In this latter assumption he followed the lead
of Anaximenes. The other bodies in question were probably invented to
explain why the eclipses of the moon are seen oftener than those of the
sun.

Anaxagoras’s cosmogony contained some fruitful ideas. According to him,
the formation of the world began with a vortex set up, in a portion
of the mixed mass in which “all things were together,” by Mind. This
rotatory movement began at one point and then gradually spread, taking
in wider and wider circles. The first effect was to separate two
great masses, one consisting of the rare, hot, light, dry, called the
æther, and the other of the opposite categories and called air. The
æther took the outer place, the air the inner. Out of the air were
separated successively clouds, water, earth, and stones. The dense,
the moist, the dark and cold, and all the heaviest things, collect in
the centre as the result of the circular motion, and it is from these
elements when consolidated that the earth is formed. But after this,
“in consequence of the violence of the whirling motion, the surrounding
fiery æther tore stones away from the earth and kindled them into
stars”. Anaxagoras conceived therefore the idea of a _centrifugal_
force, as distinct from that of concentration brought about by the
motion of the vortex, and he assumed a series of projections or
“hurlings-off” of precisely the same kind as the theory of Kant and
Laplace assumed for the formation of the solar system.

In other matters than the above Anaxagoras did not make much advance
on the crude Ionian theories. “The sun is a red-hot mass or a stone on
fire.” “It is larger (or ‘many times larger’) than the Peloponnese.” He
considered that “the stars were originally carried round (laterally)
like a dome, the pole which is always visible being thus vertically
above the earth, and it was only afterwards that their course became
inclined”.

But he put forward a remarkable and original hypothesis to explain
the Milky Way. He thought the sun to be smaller than the earth.
Consequently, when the sun in its revolution passes below the earth,
the shadow cast by the earth extends without limit. The trace of this
shadow on the heavens is the Milky Way. The stars within this shadow
are not interfered with by the light of the sun, and we therefore see
them shining; those stars, on the other hand, which are outside the
shadow are overpowered by the light of the sun which shines on them
even during the night, so that we cannot see them. Aristotle easily
disposes of this theory by observing that, the sun being much larger
than the earth, and the distance of the stars from the earth being many
times greater than the distance of the sun, the sun’s shadow would form
a cone with its vertex not very far from the earth, so that the shadow
of the earth, which we call night, would not reach the stars at all.


EMPEDOCLES.

Empedocles of Agrigentum (about 494–434 B.C.) would hardly deserve
mention for his astronomy alone, so crude were his views where they
differed from those of his predecessors. The earth, according to
Empedocles, is kept in its place by the swiftness of the revolution
of the heaven, just as we may swing a cup with water in it round and
round so that in some positions the top of the cup may even be turned
downwards without the water escaping. Day and night he explained
as follows. Within the crystal sphere to which the fixed stars are
attached (as Anaximenes held), and filling it, is a sphere consisting
of two hemispheres, one of which is wholly of fire and therefore light,
while the other is a mixture of air with a little fire, which mixture
is darkness or night. The revolution of these two hemispheres round the
earth produces at each point on its surface the succession of day and
night. Empedocles held the sun to be, not fire, but a reflection of
fire similar to that which takes place from the surface of water, the
fire of a whole hemisphere of the world being bent back from the earth,
which is circular, and concentrated into the crystalline sun which is
carried round by the motion of the fiery hemisphere.

Empedocles’s one important scientific achievement was his theory
that light travels and takes time to pass from one point to another.
The theory is alluded to by Aristotle, who says that, according to
Empedocles, the light from the sun reaches the intervening space before
it reaches the eye or the earth; there was therefore a time when the
ray was not yet seen, but was being transmitted through the medium.


THE PYTHAGOREANS.

We have seen that Pythagoras was the first to give spherical form to
the earth and probably to the heavenly bodies generally, and to assign
to the planets a revolution of their own in a sense opposite to that of
the daily rotation of the fixed stars about the earth as centre.

But a much more remarkable development was to follow in the Pythagorean
school. This was nothing less than the abandonment of the geocentric
hypothesis and the reduction of the earth to the status of a planet
like the others. The resulting system, known as the Pythagorean, is
attributed (on the authority probably of Theophrastus) to Philolaus;
but Diogenes Laertius and Aëtius refer to one Hicetas of Syracuse in
this connection; Aristotle attributes the system to “the Pythagoreans”.
It is a partial anticipation of the theory of Copernicus but differs
from it in that the earth and the planets do not revolve round the sun
but about an assumed “central fire,” and the sun itself as well as the
moon does the same. There were thus eight heavenly bodies, in addition
to the sphere of the fixed stars, all revolving about the central
fire. The number of revolutions being thus increased to nine, the
Pythagoreans postulated yet another, making ten. The tenth body they
called the counter-earth, and its character and object will appear from
the following general description of the system.

The universe is spherical in shape and finite in size. Outside it is
infinite void, which enables the universe to breathe, as it were. At
the centre is the central fire, the Hearth of the Universe, called by
various names such as the Tower or Watch-tower of Zeus, the Throne
of Zeus, the Mother of the Gods. In this central fire is located the
governing principle, the force which directs the movement and activity
of the universe. The outside boundary of the sphere is an envelope
of fire; this is called Olympus, and in this region the elements are
found in all their purity; below this is the universe. In the universe
there revolve in circles round the central fire the following bodies:
nearest to the central fire the counter-earth which always accompanies
the earth, then the earth, then the moon, then the sun, next to the sun
the five planets, and last of all, outside the orbits of the planets,
the sphere of the fixed stars. The counter-earth, which accompanies
the earth but revolves in a smaller orbit, is not seen by us because
the hemisphere on which we live is turned away from the counter-earth.
It follows that our hemisphere is always turned away from the central
fire, that is, it faces outwards from the orbit towards Olympus (the
analogy of the moon which always turns one side towards us may have
suggested this); this involves a rotation of the earth about its
axis completed in the same time as it takes the earth to complete a
revolution about the central fire.

Although there was a theory that the counter-earth was introduced in
order to bring the number of the moving bodies up to ten, the perfect
number according to the Pythagoreans, it is clear from a passage of
Aristotle that this was not the real reason. Aristotle says, namely,
that the eclipses of the moon were considered to be due sometimes to
the interposition of the earth, sometimes to the interposition of the
counter-earth. Evidently therefore the purpose of the counter-earth was
to explain the frequency with which eclipses of the moon occur.

The Pythagoreans held that the earth, revolving, like one of the stars,
about the central fire, makes night and day according to its position
relatively to the sun; it is therefore day in that region which is lit
up by the sun and night in the cone formed by the earth’s shadow. As
the same hemisphere is always turned outwards, it follows that the
earth completes one revolution about the central fire in a day and
a night or in about twenty-four hours. This would account for the
apparent diurnal rotation of the heavens from east to west; but for
parallax (of which, if we may believe Aristotle, the Pythagoreans made
light), it would be equivalent to the rotation of the earth on its own
axis once in twenty-four hours. This would make the revolution of the
sphere of the fixed stars unnecessary. Yet the Pythagoreans certainly
gave some motion to the latter sphere. What it was remains a puzzle. It
cannot have been the precession of the equinoxes, for that was first
discovered by Hipparchus (second century B.C.). Perhaps there was a
real incompatibility between the two revolutions which was unnoticed by
the authors of the system.


ŒNOPIDES OF CHIOS.

Œnopides of Chios (a little younger than Anaxagoras) is credited with
two discoveries. The first, which was important, was that of the
obliquity of the zodiac circle or the ecliptic; the second was that of
a Great Year, which Œnopides put at fifty-nine years. He also (so we
are told) found the length of the year to be 365-22/59 days. He seems
to have obtained this figure by a sort of circular argument. Starting
first with 365 days as the length of a year and 29½ days as the length
of the lunar month, approximate figures known before his time, he had
to find the least integral number of complete years containing an exact
number of lunar months; this is clearly fifty-nine years, which contain
twice 365 or 730 lunar months. Œnopides seems by his knowledge of the
calendar to have determined the number of days in 730 lunar months to
be 21,557, and this number divided by fifty-nine, the number of years,
gives 365-22/59 as the number of days in the year.


PLATO.

We come now to Plato (427–347 B.C.). In the astronomy of Plato, as we
find it in the Dialogues, there is so large an admixture of myth and
poetry that it is impossible to be sure what his real views were on
certain points of detail. In the _Phædo_ we have certain statements
about the earth to the effect that it is of very large dimensions, the
apparent hollow (according to Plato) in which we live being a very
small portion of the whole, and that it is in the middle of the heaven,
in equilibrium, without any support, by virtue of the uniformity in
the substance of the heaven. In the _Republic_ we have a glimpse of a
more complete astronomical system. The outermost revolution is that of
the sphere of the fixed stars, which carries round with it the whole
universe including the sun, moon and planets; the latter seven bodies,
while they are so carried round by the general rotation, have slower
revolutions of their own in addition, one inside the other, these
revolutions being at different speeds but all in the opposite sense to
the general rotation of the universe. The quickest rotation is that
of the fixed stars and the universe, which takes place once in about
twenty-four hours. The slower speeds of the sun, moon and planets are
not absolute but relative to the sphere of the fixed stars regarded
as stationary. The earth in the centre is unmoved; the successive
revolutions about it and within the sphere of the fixed stars are
(reckoning from the earth outwards) those of the moon, the sun, Venus,
Mercury, Mars, Jupiter, Saturn; the speed of the moon is the quickest,
that of the sun the next quickest, while Venus and Mercury travel with
the sun and have the same speed, taking about a year to describe their
orbits; after these in speed comes Mars, then Jupiter and, last and
slowest of all, Saturn. There is nothing said in the _Republic_ about
the seven bodies revolving in a circle different from and inclined to
the equator of the sphere of the fixed stars; that is, the obliquity of
the ecliptic does not appear; hence the standpoint of the whole system
is that of Pythagoras as distinct from that of the Pythagoreans.

Plato’s astronomical system is, however, most fully developed in the
_Timæus_. While other details remain substantially the same, the zodiac
circle in which the sun, moon and planets revolve is distinguished from
the equator of the sphere of the fixed stars. The latter is called
the circle of the Same, the former that of the Other, and we are told
(quite correctly) that, since the revolution of the universe in the
circle of the Same carries all the other revolutions with it, the
effect on each of the seven bodies is to turn their actual motions in
space into spirals. There is a difficulty in interpreting a phrase in
Plato’s description which says that Venus and Mercury, though moving in
a circle having equal speed with the sun, “have the contrary tendency
to it”. Literally this would seem to mean that Venus and Mercury
describe their circles the opposite way to the sun, but this is so
contradicted by observation that Plato could hardly have maintained
it; hence the words have been thought to convey a vague reference to
the apparent irregularities in the motion of Venus and Mercury, their
standings-still and retrogradations.

But the most disputed point in the system is the part assigned in it
to the earth. An expression is used with regard to its relation to
the axis of the heavenly sphere which might mean either (1) that it
is wrapped or globed about that axis but without motion, or (2) that
it revolves round the axis. If the word means _revolving_ about the
axis of the sphere, the revolution would be either (_a_) rotation
about its own axis supposed to be identical with that of the sphere,
or (_b_) revolution about the axis of the heavenly sphere in the same
way that the sun, moon and planets revolve about an axis obliquely
inclined to that axis. But (_a_) if the earth rotated about its own
axis, this would make unnecessary the rotation of the sphere of the
fixed stars once in twenty-four hours, which, however, is expressly
included as part of the system. The hypothesis (_b_) would make the
system similar to the Pythagorean except that the earth would revolve
about the axis of the heavenly sphere instead of round the central
fire. The supporters of this hypothesis cite two passages of Plutarch
to the effect that Plato was said in his old age to have repented of
having given the earth the middle place in the universe instead of
placing it elsewhere and giving the middle and chiefest place to some
worthier occupant. It is a sufficient answer to this argument that,
if Plato really meant in the passage of the _Timæus_ to say that the
earth revolves about the axis of the heavenly sphere, he had nothing
to repent of. We must therefore, for our part, conclude that in his
written Dialogues Plato regarded the earth as _at rest_ in the centre
of the universe.

We have it on good authority that Plato set it as a problem to all
earnest students “to find what are the uniform and ordered movements
by the assumption of which the apparent movements of the planets can
be accounted for”. The same authority adds that Eudoxus was the first
to formulate a theory with this object; and Heraclides of Pontus
followed with an entirely new hypothesis. Both were pupils of Plato
and, in so far as the statement of his problem was a stimulus to these
speculations, he rendered an important service to the science of
astronomy.


EUDOXUS, CALLIPPUS, ARISTOTLE.

Eudoxus of Cnidos (about 408–355 B.C.) was one of the very greatest
of the Greek mathematicians. He was the discoverer and elaborator of
the great theory of proportion applicable to all magnitudes whether
commensurable or incommensurable which is given in Euclid’s Book V. He
was also the originator of the powerful _method of exhaustion_ used
by all later Greek geometers for the purpose of finding the areas of
curves and the volumes of pyramids, cones, spheres and other curved
surfaces. It is not therefore surprising that he should have invented
a remarkable geometrical hypothesis for explaining the irregular
movements of the planets. The problem was to find the necessary number
of circular motions which by their combination would produce the
motions of the planets as actually observed, and in particular the
variations in their apparent speeds, their stations and retrogradations
and their movements in latitude. This Eudoxus endeavoured to do by
combining the motions of several concentric spheres, one inside the
other, and revolving about different axes, each sphere revolving on
its own account but also being carried round bodily by the revolution
of the next sphere encircling it. We are dependent on passages from
Aristotle and Simplicius for our knowledge of Eudoxus’s system, which
he had set out in a work _On Speeds_, now lost. Eudoxus assumed three
revolving spheres for producing the apparent motions of the sun and
moon respectively, and four for that of each of the planets. In his
hypothesis for the sun he seems deliberately to have ignored the
discovery made by Meton and Euctemon some sixty or seventy years before
that the sun does not take the same time to describe the four quadrants
of its orbit between the equinoctial and solstitial points.

It should be observed that the whole hypothesis of the concentric
spheres is pure geometry, and there is no mechanics in it. We will
shortly describe the arrangement of the four spheres which by their
revolution produced the motion of a planet. The first and outermost
sphere produced the daily rotation in twenty-four hours; the second
sphere revolved about an axis perpendicular to the plane of the zodiac
or ecliptic, thereby producing the motion along the zodiac “in the
respective periods in which the planets appear to describe the zodiac
circle,” i.e. in the case of the superior planets, the sidereal periods
of revolution, and in the case of Mercury and Venus (on a geocentric
system) one year. The third sphere had its poles at two opposite points
on the zodiac circle, the poles being carried round in the motion of
the second sphere; the revolution of the third sphere about the axis
connecting the two poles was again uniform and took place in a period
equal to the synodic period of the planet, or the time elapsing between
two successive oppositions or conjunctions with the sun.

The poles of the third sphere were different for all the planets,
except that for Mercury and Venus they were the same. On the surface
of the third sphere the poles of the fourth sphere were fixed, and
its axis of revolution was inclined to that of the former at an angle
constant for each planet but different for the different planets.
The planet was fixed at a point on the equator of the fourth sphere.
The third and fourth spheres together cause the planet’s movement
in latitude. Simplicius explains clearly the effect of these two
rotations. If, he says, the planet had been on the third sphere (by
itself), it would actually have arrived at the poles of the zodiac
circle; but, as things are, the fourth sphere, which turns about the
poles of the inclined circle carrying the planet and rotates in the
opposite sense to the third, i.e. from east to west, but in the
same period, will prevent any considerable divergence on the part
of the planet from the zodiac circle, and will cause the planet to
describe about this same zodiac circle the curve called by Eudoxus
the _hippopede_ (horse-fetter), so that the breadth of this curve
will be the maximum amount of the apparent deviation of the planet in
latitude. The curve in question is an elongated figure-of-eight lying
along and bisected by the zodiac circle. The motion then round this
figure-of-eight combined with the motion in the zodiac circle produces
the acceleration and retardation of the motion of the planet, causing
the stations and retrogradations. Mathematicians will appreciate the
wonderful ingenuity and beauty of the construction.

Eudoxus spent sixteen months in Egypt about 381–380 B.C., and, while
there, he assimilated the astronomical knowledge of the priests of
Heliopolis and himself made observations. The Observatory between
Heliopolis and Cercesura used by him was still pointed out in
Augustus’s time; he also had one built at Cnidos. He wrote two books
entitled respectively the _Mirror_ and the _Phænomena_; the poem of
Aratus was, so far as verses 19–732 are concerned, drawn from the
_Phænomena_ of Eudoxus. He is also credited with the invention of the
_arachne_ (spider’s web) which, however, is alternatively attributed to
Apollonius, and which seems to have been a sun-clock of some kind.

Eudoxus’s system of concentric spheres was improved upon by Callippus
(about 370–300 B.C.), who added two more spheres for the sun and the
moon, and one more in the case of each of the three nearer planets,
Mercury, Venus and Mars. The two additional spheres in the case of
the sun were introduced in order to account for the unequal motion
of the sun in longitude; and the purpose in the case of the moon
was presumably similar. Callippus made the length of the seasons,
beginning with the vernal equinox, ninety-four, ninety-two, eighty-nine
and ninety days respectively, figures much more accurate than those
given by Euctemon a hundred years earlier, which were ninety-three,
ninety, ninety and ninety-two days respectively.

With Callippus as well as Eudoxus the system of concentric spheres
was purely geometrical. Aristotle (384–322 B.C.) thought it necessary
to alter it in a mechanical sense; he made the spheres into spherical
shells actually in contact with one another, and this made it almost
necessary, instead of having independent sets of spheres, one set for
each planet, to make all the sets part of one continuous system of
spheres. For this purpose he assumed sets of _reacting_ spheres between
successive sets of the original spheres. E.g. Saturn being carried by
a set of four spheres, he had three reacting spheres to neutralise
the last three, in order to restore the outermost sphere to act as
the first of the four spheres producing the motion of the next lower
planet, Jupiter, and so on. The change was hardly an improvement.

Aristotle’s other ideas in astronomy do not require detailed notice,
except his views about the earth. Although he held firmly to the old
belief that the earth is in the centre and remains motionless, he was
clear that its shape (like that of the stars and the universe) is
spherical, and he had arrived at views about its size sounder than
those of Plato. In support of the spherical shape of the earth he used
some good arguments based on observation. (1) In partial eclipses of
the moon the line separating the dark and bright portions is always
circular--unlike the line of demarcation in the phases of the moon
which may be straight. (2) Certain stars seen above the horizon in
Egypt and in Cyprus are not visible further north, and, on the other
hand, certain stars set there which in more northern latitudes remain
always above the horizon. As there is so perceptible a change of
horizon between places so near to each other, it follows not only that
the earth is spherical but also that it is not a very large sphere.
Aristotle adds that people are not improbably right when they say that
the region about the Pillars of Heracles is joined on to India, one sea
connecting them. He quotes a result arrived at by the mathematicians of
his time, that the circumference of the earth is 400,000 stades. He is
clear that the earth is much smaller than some of the stars, but that
the moon is smaller than the earth.

The systems of concentric spheres were not destined to hold their
ground for long. In these systems the sun, moon and planets were of
necessity always at the same distances from the earth respectively. But
it was soon recognised that they did not “save the phenomena,” since
it was seen that the planets appeared to be at one time nearer and at
another time further off. Autolycus of Pitane (who flourished about
310 B.C.) knew this and is said to have tried to explain it; indeed
it can hardly have been unknown even to the authors of the concentric
theory themselves, for Polemarchus of Cyzicus, almost contemporary
with Eudoxus, is said to have been aware of it but to have minimised
the difficulty because he preferred the hypothesis of the concentric
spheres to others.

Development along the lines of Eudoxus’s theory being thus blocked,
the alternative was open of seeing whether any modification of the
Pythagorean system would give better results. We actually have evidence
of revisions of the Pythagorean theory. The first step was to get rid
of the counter-earth, and some Pythagoreans did this by identifying
the counter-earth with the moon. We hear too of a Pythagorean system
in which the central fire was not outside the earth but in the centre
of the earth itself. The descriptions of this system rather indicate
that in it the earth was supposed to be at rest, without any rotation,
in the centre of the universe. This was practically a return to
the standpoint of Pythagoras himself. But it is clear that, if the
system of Philolaus (or Hicetas) be taken and the central fire be
transferred to the centre of the earth (the counter-earth being also
eliminated), and if the movements of the earth, sun, moon and planets
round the centre be retained without any modification save that which
is mathematically involved by the transfer of the central fire to
the centre of the earth, the daily revolution of the earth about the
central fire is necessarily transformed into a rotation of the earth
about its own axis in about twenty-four hours.


HERACLIDES OF PONTUS.

All authorities agree that the theory of the daily rotation of the
earth about its own axis was put forward by Heraclides of Pontus
(about 388–315 B.C.), a pupil of Plato; with him in some accounts
is associated the name of one Ecphantus, a Pythagorean. We are told
that Ecphantus asserted “that the earth, being in the centre of the
universe, moves about its own centre in an eastward direction,” and
that “Heraclides of Pontus and Ecphantus the Pythagorean make the earth
move, not in the sense of translation, but by way of turning as on an
axle, like a wheel, from west to east, about its own centre”.

Heraclides was born at Heraclea in Pontus. He went to Athens not later
than 364 B.C., and there met Speusippus, who introduced him into the
school of Plato. On the death of Speusippus (then at the head of the
school) in 338, Xenocrates was elected to succeed him; at this election
Heraclides was also a candidate and was only defeated by a few votes.
He was the author of dialogues, brilliant and original, on all sorts
of subjects, which were much read and imitated at Rome, e.g. by Varro
and Cicero. Two of them “On Nature” and “On the Heavens” may have dealt
with astronomy.

In his view that the earth rotates about its own axis Heraclides is
associated with Aristarchus of Samos; thus Simplicius says: “There
have been some, like Heraclides of Pontus and Aristarchus, who
supposed that the phenomena can be saved if the heaven and the stars
are at rest while the earth moves about the poles of the equinoctial
circle from the west to the east, completing one revolution each day,
approximately; the ‘approximately’ is added because of the daily motion
of the sun to the extent of one degree”.

Heraclides made another important advance towards the Copernican
hypothesis. He discovered the fact that Venus and Mercury revolve
about the sun as centre. So much is certain; but a further question
naturally arises. Having made Venus and Mercury revolve round the sun
like satellites, did Heraclides proceed to draw the same inference
with regard to the other, the superior, planets? The question is
interesting because, had it been laid down that all the five planets
alike revolve round the sun, the combination of this hypothesis with
Heraclides’s assumption that the earth rotates about its own axis
in twenty-four hours would have amounted to an anticipation of the
system of Tycho Brahe, but with the improvement of the substitution
of the daily rotation of the earth for the daily revolution of the
whole system about the earth supposed at rest. Schiaparelli dealt with
the question in two papers entitled _I precursori di Copernico nell’
antichità_ (1873), and _Origine del sistema planetario eliocentrico
presso i Greci_ (1898). Schiaparelli tried to show that Heraclides
did arrive at the conclusion that the superior planets as well as
Mercury and Venus revolve round the sun; but most persons will probably
agree that his argument is not convincing. The difficulties seem too
great. The circles described by Mercury and Venus about the sun are
relatively small circles and are entirely on one side of the earth.
But when the possibility of, say, Mars revolving about the sun came to
be considered, it would be at once obvious that the precise hypothesis
adopted for Mercury and Venus would not apply. It would be seen that
Mars is brightest when it occupies a position in the zodiac _opposite_
to the sun; it must therefore be nearest to the earth at that time.
Consequently the circle described by Mars, instead of being on one side
of the earth, must comprehend the earth which is inside it. Whereas
therefore the circles described by Mercury and Venus were what the
Greeks called _epicycles_ about a material centre, the sun (itself
moving in a circle round the earth), what was wanted in the case of
Mars (if the circle described by Mars was to have the sun for centre)
was what the Greeks called an _eccentric_ circle, with a centre which
itself moves in a circle about the earth, and with a radius greater
than that of the sun’s orbit. Though the same motion could have been
produced by an _epicycle_, the epicycle would have had to have a
mathematical point (not the material sun) as centre. But the idea of
using non-material points as centres for epicycles was probably first
thought of, at a later stage, by some of the great mathematicians such
as Apollonius of Perga (about 265–190 B.C.).

Not only does Schiaparelli maintain that the complete (but improved)
Tychonic hypothesis was put forward by Heraclides or at least in
Heraclides’s time; he goes further and makes a still greater claim on
behalf of Heraclides, namely, that it was he, and not Aristarchus of
Samos, who first stated as a possibility the Copernican hypothesis.
Now it was much to discover, as Heraclides did, that the earth rotates
about its own axis and that Mercury and Venus revolve round the sun
like satellites; and it seems _a priori_ incredible that one man should
not only have reached, and improved upon, the hypothesis of Tycho
Brahe but should _also_ have suggested the Copernican hypothesis.
It is therefore necessary to examine briefly the evidence on which
Schiaparelli relied. His argument rests entirely upon one passage, a
sentence forming part of a quotation from a summary by Geminus of the
_Meteorologica_ of Posidonius, which Simplicius copied from Alexander
Aphrodisiensis and embodied in his commentary on the _Physics_ of
Aristotle. The sentence in question, according to the reading of
the MSS., is as follows: “Hence we actually find a certain person,
Heraclides of Pontus, coming forward and saying that, even on the
assumption that the earth moves in a certain way, while the sun is in
a certain way at rest, the apparent irregularity with reference to the
sun can be saved”. (The preceding sentence is about possible answers to
the question, why do the sun, the moon and the planets appear to move
irregularly? and says, “we may answer that, if we assume that their
orbits are eccentric circles or that the stars describe an epicycle,
their apparent irregularity will be saved, and it will be necessary to
go further and examine in how many different ways it is possible for
these phenomena to be brought about”.)

Now it is impossible that Geminus himself can have spoken of an
astronomer of the distinction of Heraclides as “_a certain_ Heraclides
of Pontus”. Consequently there have been different attempts made to
emend the reading of the MSS. All the emendations proposed are open
to serious objections, and we are thrown back on the reading of the
MSS. Now it “leaps to the eyes” that, if the name of Heraclides of
Pontus is left out, everything is in order. “This is why one astronomer
has actually suggested that, by assuming the earth to move in a
certain way, and the sun to be in a certain way at rest, the apparent
irregularity with reference to the sun will be saved.” This seems to
be the solution of the puzzle suggested by the ordinary principles of
textual criticism, and is so simple and natural that it will surely
carry conviction to the minds of unbiassed persons. Geminus, in fact,
mentioned no name but meant Aristarchus of Samos, and some scholiast,
remembering that Heraclides had given a certain motion to the earth
(namely, rotation about its axis), immediately thought of Heraclides
and inserted his name in the margin, from which it afterwards crept
into the text.

It is only necessary to add that Archimedes is not likely to have
been wrong when he attributed the first suggestion of the Copernican
hypothesis to Aristarchus of Samos in express terms; and this is
confirmed by another positive statement by Aëtius, already quoted,
that “Heraclides of Pontus and Ecphantus the Pythagorean made the
earth move, _not_ in the sense of translation, but with a movement of
rotation”.



PART II.

ARISTARCHUS OF SAMOS.


We are told that Aristarchus of Samos was a pupil of Strato of
Lampsacus, a natural philosopher of originality, who succeeded
Theophrastus as head of the Peripatetic school in 288 or 287 B.C., and
held that position for eighteen years. Two other facts enable us to fix
Aristarchus’s date approximately. In 281–280 he made an observation
of the summer solstice; and the book in which he formulated his
heliocentric hypothesis was published before the date of Archimedes’s
_Psammites_ or _Sandreckoner_, a work written before 216 B.C.
Aristarchus therefore probably lived _circa_ 310–230 B.C., that is, he
came about seventy-five years later than Heraclides and was older than
Archimedes by about twenty-five years.

Aristarchus was called “the mathematician,” no doubt in order to
distinguish him from the many other persons of the same name; Vitruvius
includes him among the few great men who possessed an equally profound
knowledge of all branches of science, geometry, astronomy, music, etc.
“Men of this type are rare, men such as were in times past Aristarchus
of Samos, Philolaus and Archytas of Tarentum, Apollonius of Perga,
Eratosthenes of Cyrene, Archimedes and Scopinas of Syracuse, who
left to posterity many mechanical and gnomonic appliances which they
invented and explained on mathematical and natural principles.” That
Aristarchus was a very capable geometer is proved by his extant book,
_On the sizes and distances of the sun and moon_, presently to be
described. In the mechanical line he is credited with the invention of
an improved sun-dial, the so-called _scaphe_, which had not a plane but
a concave hemispherical surface, with a pointer erected vertically in
the middle, throwing shadows and so enabling the direction and height
of the sun to be read off by means of lines marked on the surface of
the hemisphere. He also wrote on vision, light, and colours. His views
on the latter subjects were no doubt largely influenced by the teaching
of Strato. Strato held that colours were emanations from bodies,
material molecules as it were, which imparted to the intervening air
the same colour as that possessed by the body. Aristarchus said that
colours are “shapes or forms stamping the air with impressions like
themselves as it were,” that “colours in darkness have no colouring,”
and that “light is the colour impinging on a substratum”.


THE HELIOCENTRIC HYPOTHESIS.

There is no doubt whatever that Aristarchus put forward the
heliocentric hypothesis. Ancient testimony is unanimous on the point,
and the first witness is Archimedes who was a younger contemporary of
Aristarchus, so that there is no possibility of a mistake. Copernicus
himself admitted that the theory was attributed to Aristarchus, though
this does not seem to be generally known. Copernicus refers in two
passages of his work, _De revolutionibus caelestibus_, to the opinions
of the ancients about the motion of the earth. In the dedicatory letter
to Pope Paul III he mentions that he first learnt from Cicero that one
Nicetas (i.e. Hicetas) had attributed motion to the earth, and that he
afterwards read in Plutarch that certain others held that opinion; he
then quotes the _Placita philosophorum_ according to which “Philolaus
the Pythagorean asserted that the earth moved round the fire in an
oblique circle in the same way as the sun and moon”. In Book I. c. 5 of
his work Copernicus alludes to the views of Heraclides, Ecphantus, and
Hicetas, who made the earth rotate about its own axis, and then goes on
to say that it would not be very surprising if any one should attribute
to the earth another motion besides rotation, namely, revolution in
an orbit in space: “atque etiam (terram) pluribus motibus vagantem et
unam ex astris Philolaus Pythagoricus sensisse fertur, Mathematicus non
vulgaris”. Here, however, there is no question of the earth revolving
round the sun, and there is no mention of Aristarchus. But Copernicus
did mention the theory of Aristarchus in a passage which he afterwards
suppressed: “Credibile est hisce similibusque causis Philolaum
mobilitatem terrae sensisse, quod etiam nonnulli Aristarchum Samium
ferunt in eadem fuisse sententia”.

It is desirable to quote the whole passage of Archimedes in which the
allusion to Aristarchus’s heliocentric hypothesis occurs, in order to
show the whole context.

“You are aware [‘you’ being King Gelon] that ‘universe’ is the name
given by most astronomers to the sphere the centre of which is the
centre of the earth, while its radius is equal to the straight line
between the centre of the sun and the centre of the earth. This is the
common account as you have heard from astronomers. But Aristarchus
brought out _a book consisting of certain hypotheses_, wherein it
appears, as a consequence of the assumptions made, that the universe is
many times greater than the ‘universe’ just mentioned. His hypotheses
are that _the fixed stars and the sun remain unmoved, that the earth
revolves about the sun in the circumference of a circle, the sun lying
in the middle of the orbit_, and that the sphere of the fixed stars,
situated about the same centre as the sun, is so great that the circle
in which he supposes the earth to revolve bears such a proportion to
the distance of the fixed stars as the centre of the sphere bears to
its surface.”

The heliocentric hypothesis is here stated in language which leaves
no room for doubt about its meaning. The sun, like the fixed stars,
remains unmoved and forms the centre of a circular orbit in which the
earth moves round it; the sphere of the fixed stars has its centre at
the centre of the sun.

We have further evidence in a passage of Plutarch’s tract, _On the
face in the moon’s orb_: “Only do not, my dear fellow, enter an action
for impiety against me in the style of Cleanthes, who thought it was
the duty of Greeks to indict Aristarchus on the charge of impiety for
putting in motion the Hearth of the Universe, this being the effect of
his attempt to save the phenomena by supposing the heaven to remain at
rest and the earth to revolve in an oblique circle, while it rotates,
at the same time, about its own axis”.

Here we have the additional detail that Aristarchus followed
Heraclides in attributing to the earth the daily rotation about its
axis; Archimedes does not state this in so many words, but it is
clearly involved by his remark that Aristarchus supposed the fixed
stars as well as the sun to remain unmoved in space. A tract “Against
Aristarchus” is mentioned by Diogenes Laertius among Cleanthes’s works;
and it was evidently published during Aristarchus’s lifetime (Cleanthes
died about 232 B.C.).

We learn from another passage of Plutarch that the hypothesis of
Aristarchus was adopted, about a century later, by Seleucus, of
Seleucia on the Tigris, a Chaldæan or Babylonian, who also wrote on
the subject of the tides about 150 B.C. The passage is interesting
because it also alludes to the doubt about Plato’s final views. “Did
Plato put the earth in motion as he did the sun, the moon and the five
planets which he called the ‘instruments of time’ on account of their
turnings, and was it necessary to conceive that the earth ‘which is
globed about the axis stretched from pole to pole through the whole
universe’ was not represented as being (merely) held together and
at rest but as turning and revolving, as Aristarchus and Seleucus
afterwards maintained that it did, the former of whom stated this as
only a hypothesis, the latter as a definite opinion?”

No one after Seleucus is mentioned by name as having accepted the
doctrine of Aristarchus and, if other Greek astronomers refer to it,
they do so only to denounce it. Hipparchus, himself a contemporary of
Seleucus, definitely reverted to the geocentric system, and it was
doubtless his authority which sealed the fate of the heliocentric
hypothesis for so many centuries.

The reasons which weighed with Hipparchus were presumably the facts
that the system in which the earth revolved in a circle of which
the sun was the exact _centre_ failed to “save the phenomena,” and
in particular to account for the variations of distance and the
irregularities of the motions, which became more and more patent as
methods of observation improved; that, on the other hand, the theory
of epicycles did suffice to represent the phenomena with considerable
accuracy; and that the latter theory could be reconciled with the
immobility of the earth.


ON THE APPARENT DIAMETER OF THE SUN.

Archimedes tells us in the same treatise that “Aristarchus discovered
that the sun’s apparent size is about 1/720th part of the zodiac
circle”; that is to say, he observed that the angle subtended at the
earth by the diameter of the sun is about half a degree.


ON THE SIZES AND DISTANCES OF THE SUN AND MOON.

Archimedes also says that, whereas the ratio of the diameter of the sun
to that of the moon had been estimated by Eudoxus at 9 : 1 and by his
own father Phidias at 12 : 1, Aristarchus made the ratio greater than
18 : 1 but less than 20 : 1. Fortunately we possess in Greek the short
treatise in which Aristarchus proved these conclusions; on the other
matter of the apparent diameter of the sun Archimedes’s statement is
our only evidence.

It is noteworthy that in Aristarchus’s extant treatise _On the sizes
and distances of the sun and moon_ there is no hint of the heliocentric
hypothesis, while the apparent diameter of the sun is there assumed to
be, not ½°, but the very inaccurate figure of 2°. Both circumstances
are explained if we assume that the treatise was an early work written
before the hypotheses described by Archimedes were put forward. In the
treatise Aristarchus finds the ratio of the diameter of the sun to the
diameter of the earth to lie between 19 : 3 and 43 : 6; this would
make the volume of the sun about 300 times that of the earth, and it
may be that the great size of the sun in comparison with the earth, as
thus brought out, was one of the considerations which led Aristarchus
to place the sun rather than the earth in the centre of the universe,
since it might even at that day seem absurd to make the body which was
so much larger revolve about the smaller.

There is no reason to doubt that in his heliocentric system Aristarchus
retained the moon as a satellite of the earth revolving round it as
centre; hence even in his system there was one _epicycle_.

The treatise _On sizes and distances_ being the only work of
Aristarchus which has survived, it will be fitting to give here a
description of its contents and special features.

The style of Aristarchus is thoroughly classical as befits an able
geometer intermediate in date between Euclid and Archimedes, and his
demonstrations are worked out with the same rigour as those of his
predecessor and successor. The propositions of Euclid’s _Elements_ are,
of course, taken for granted, but other things are tacitly assumed
which go beyond what we find in Euclid. Thus the transformations of
ratios defined in Euclid, Book V, and denoted by the terms _inversely_,
_alternately_, _componendo_, _convertendo_, etc., are regularly
used in dealing with _unequal_ ratios, whereas in Euclid they are
only used in proportions, i.e. cases of _equality_ of ratios. But
the propositions of Aristarchus are also of particular mathematical
interest because the ratios of the sizes and distances which have
to be calculated are really trigonometrical ratios, sines, cosines,
etc., although at the time of Aristarchus trigonometry had not been
invented, and no reasonably close approximation to the value of π,
the ratio of the circumference of any circle to its diameter, had
been made (it was Archimedes who first obtained the approximation
22/7). Exact calculation of the trigonometrical ratios being therefore
impossible for Aristarchus, he set himself to find upper and lower
limits for them, and he succeeded in locating those which emerge in
his propositions within tolerably narrow limits, though not always
the narrowest within which it would have been possible, even for him,
to confine them. In this species of approximation to trigonometry he
tacitly assumes propositions comparing the ratio between a greater
and a lesser _angle_ in a figure with the ratio between two _straight
lines_, propositions which are formally proved by Ptolemy at the
beginning of his _Syntaxis_. Here again we have proof that textbooks
containing such propositions existed before Aristarchus’s time, and
probably much earlier, although they have not survived.

Aristarchus necessarily begins by laying down, as the basis for his
treatise, certain assumptions. They are six in number, and he refers
to them as _hypotheses_. We cannot do better than quote them in full,
along with the sentences immediately following, in which he states the
main results to be established in the treatise:--

[HYPOTHESES.]

1. _That the moon receives its light from the sun._

2. _That the earth is in the relation of a point and centre to the
sphere in which the moon moves._

3. _That, when the moon appears to us halved, the great circle which
divides the dark and the bright portions of the moon is in the
direction of our eye._

4. _That, when the moon appears to us halved, its distance from the sun
is then less than a quadrant by one-thirtieth of a quadrant._

5. _That the breadth of the (earth’s) shadow is (that) of two moons._

6. _That the moon subtends one-fifteenth part of a sign of the zodiac._

We are now in a position to prove the following propositions:--

1. _The distance of the sun from the earth is greater than eighteen
times, but less than twenty times, the distance of the moon (from the
earth)_; this follows from the hypothesis about the halved moon.

2. _The diameter of the sun has the same ratio (as aforesaid) to the
diameter of the moon._

3. _The diameter of the sun has to the diameter of the earth a ratio
greater than that which 19 has to 3, but less than that which 43 has to
6_; this follows from the ratio thus discovered between the distances,
the hypothesis about the shadow, and the hypothesis that the moon
subtends one-fifteenth part of a sign of the zodiac.

The first assumption is Anaxagoras’s discovery. The second assumption
is no doubt an exaggeration; but it is made in order to avoid having
to allow for the fact that the phenomena as seen by an observer on the
surface of the earth are slightly different from what would be seen
if the observer’s eye were at the centre of the earth. Aristarchus,
that is, takes the earth to be like a point in order to avoid the
complication of parallax.

The meaning of the third hypothesis is that the plane of the great
circle in question passes through the point where the eye of the
observer is situated; that is to say, we see the circle _end on_, as it
were, and it looks like a straight line.

Hypothesis 4. If S be the sun, M the moon and E the earth, the triangle
SME is, at the moment when the moon appears to us halved, right-angled
at M; and the hypothesis states that the angle at E in this triangle is
87°, or, in other words, the angle MSE, that is, the angle subtended
at the sun by the line joining M to E, is 3°. These estimates are
decidedly inaccurate, for the true value of the angle MES is 89° 50′,
and that of the angle MSE is therefore 10′. There is nothing to show
how Aristarchus came to estimate the angle MSE at 3°, and none of his
successors seem to have made any direct estimate of the size of the
angle.

The assumption in Hypothesis 5 was improved upon later. Hipparchus made
the ratio of the diameter of the circle of the earth’s shadow to the
diameter of the moon to be, not 2, but 2½ at the moon’s mean distance
at the conjunctions; Ptolemy made it, at the moon’s greatest distance,
to be inappreciably less than 2⅗.

The sixth hypothesis states that the diameter of the moon subtends at
our eye an angle which is 1/15th of 30°, i.e. 2°, whereas Archimedes,
as we have seen, tells us that Aristarchus found the angle subtended
by the diameter of the sun to be ½° (Archimedes in the same tract
describes a rough instrument by means of which he himself found that
the diameter of the sun subtended an angle less than 1/164th, but
greater than 1/200th of a right angle). Even the Babylonians had, many
centuries before, arrived at 1° as the apparent angular diameter of the
sun. It is not clear why Aristarchus took a value so inaccurate as 2°.
It has been suggested that he merely intended to give a specimen of the
calculations which would have to be made on the basis of more exact
experimental observations, and to show that, for the solution of the
problem, one of the data could be chosen almost arbitrarily, by which
proceeding he secured himself against certain objections which might
have been raised. Perhaps this is too ingenious, and it may be that, in
view of the difficulty of working out the geometry if the two angles in
question are very small, he took 3° and 2° as being the smallest with
which he could conveniently deal. Certain it is that the _method_ of
Aristarchus is perfectly correct and, if he could have substituted the
true values (as we know them to-day) for the inaccurate values which he
assumes, and could have carried far enough his geometrical substitute
for trigonometry, he would have obtained close limits for the true
sizes and distances.

The book contains eighteen propositions. Prop. 1 proves that we can
draw one cylinder to touch two equal spheres, and one cone to touch two
unequal spheres, the planes of the circles of contact being at right
angles to the axis of the cylinder or cone. Next (Prop. 2) it is shown
that, if a lesser sphere be illuminated by a greater, the illuminated
portion of the former will be greater than a hemisphere. Prop. 3
proves that the circle in the moon which divides the dark and the
bright portions (we will in future, for short, call this “the dividing
circle”) is least when the cone which touches the sun and the moon
has its vertex at our eye. In Prop. 4 it is shown that the dividing
circle is not perceptibly different from a great circle in the moon.
If CD is a diameter of the dividing circle, EF the parallel diameter
of the parallel great circle in the moon, O the centre of the moon,
A the observer’s eye, FDG the great circle in the moon the plane of
which passes through A, and G the point where OA meets the latter great
circle, Aristarchus takes an arc of the great circle GH on one side of
G, and another GK on the other side of G, such that GH = GK = ½ (the
arc FD), and proves that the angle subtended at A by the arc HK is less
than 1/44°; consequently, he says, the arc would be imperceptible at
A even in that position, and _a fortiori_ the arc FD (which is nearly
in a straight line with the tangent AD) is quite imperceptible to the
observer at A. Hence (Prop. 5), when the moon appears to us halved, we
can take the plane of the great circle in the moon which is parallel to
the dividing circle as passing through our eye. (It is tacitly assumed
in Props. 3, 4, and throughout, that the diameters of the sun and moon
respectively subtend the same angle at our eye.) The proof of Prop.
4 assumes as known the equivalent of the proposition in trigonometry
that, if each of the angles α, β is not greater than a right angle, and
α > β, then

  tan α / tan β > α/β > sin α / sin β.

Prop. 6 proves that the moon’s orbit is “lower” (i.e. smaller) than
that of the sun, and that, when the moon appears to us halved, it
is distant less than a quadrant from the sun. Prop. 7 is the main
proposition in the treatise. It proves that, on the assumptions made,
the distance of the sun from the earth is greater than eighteen times,
but less than twenty times, the distance of the moon from the earth.
The proof is simple and elegant and should delight any mathematician;
its two parts depend respectively on the geometrical equivalents of the
two inequalities stated in the formula quoted above, namely,

  tan α / tan β > α/β > sin α / sin β,

where α, β are angles not greater than a right angle and α > β.
Aristarchus also, in this proposition, cites 7/5 as an approximation by
defect to the value of √2, an approximation found by the Pythagoreans
and quoted by Plato. The trigonometrical equivalent of the result
obtained in Prop. 7 is

  1/18 > sin 3° > 1/20.

Prop. 8 states that, when the sun is totally eclipsed, the sun and moon
are comprehended by one and the same cone which has its vertex at our
eye. Aristarchus supports this by the arguments (1) that, if the sun
overlapped the moon, it would not be totally eclipsed, and (2) that,
if the sun fell short (i.e. was more than covered), it would remain
totally eclipsed for some time, which it does not (this, he says,
is manifest from observation). It is clear from this reasoning that
Aristarchus had not observed the phenomenon of an _annular_ eclipse of
the sun; and it is curious that the first mention of an annular eclipse
seems to be that quoted by Simplicius from Sosigenes (second century,
A.D.), the teacher of Alexander Aphrodisiensis.

It follows (Prop. 9) from Prop. 8 that the diameters of the sun
and moon are in the same ratio as their distances from the earth
respectively, that is to say (Prop. 7) in a ratio greater than 18 : 1
but less than 20 : 1. Hence (Prop. 10) the volume of the sun is more
than 5832 times and less than 8000 times that of the moon.

By the usual geometrical substitute for trigonometry Aristarchus proves
in Prop. 11 that the diameter of the moon has to the distance between
the centre of the moon and our eye a ratio which is less than 2/45ths
but greater than 1/30th. Since the angle subtended by the moon’s
diameter at the observer’s eye is assumed to be 2°, this proposition is
equivalent to the trigonometrical formula

  1/45 > sin 1° > 1/60.

Having proved in Prop. 4 that, so far as our perception goes, the
dividing circle in the moon is indistinguishable from a great circle,
Aristarchus goes behind perception and proves in Prop. 12 that the
diameter of the dividing circle is less than the diameter of the moon
but greater than 89/90ths of it. This is again because half the angle
subtended by the moon at the eye is assumed to be 1° or 1/90th of a
right angle. The proposition is equivalent to the trigonometrical
formula

  1 > cos 1° > 89/90.

We come now to propositions which depend on Hypothesis 5 that “the
breadth of the earth’s shadow is that of two moons”. Prop. 13 is about
the diameter of the circular section of the cone formed by the earth’s
shadow at the place where the moon passes through it in an eclipse,
and it is worth while to notice the extreme accuracy with which
Aristarchus describes the diameter in question. It is with him “the
straight line subtending the portion intercepted within the earth’s
shadow of the circumference of the circle in which the extremities of
the diameter of the circle dividing the dark and the bright portions in
the moon move.” Aristarchus proves that the length of the straight line
in question has to the diameter of the moon a ratio less than 2 but
greater than 88 : 45, and has to the diameter of the sun a ratio less
than 1 : 9 but greater than 22 : 225. The ratio of the straight line to
the diameter of the moon is, in point of fact, 2 cos² 1° or 2 sin² 89°,
and Aristarchus therefore proves the equivalent of

  2 > 2 cos² 1° > ½(89/45)² or 7921/4050.

He then observes (without explanation) that 7921/4050 > 88/45 (an
approximation easily obtained by developing 7921/4050 as a continued
fraction (= 1 + (1    1    1)/(1 + 21 + 2))); his result is therefore
equivalent to

  1 > cos² 1° > 44/45.

The next propositions are the equivalents of more complicated
trigonometrical formulæ. Prop. 14 is an auxiliary proposition to Prop.
15. The diameter of the shadow dealt with in Prop. 13 divides into two
parts the straight line joining the centre of the earth to the centre
of the moon, and Prop. 14 shows that the whole length of this line is
more than 675 times the part of it terminating in the centre of the
moon. With the aid of Props. 7, 13, and 14 Aristarchus is now able,
in Prop. 15, to prove another of his main results, namely, that the
diameter of the sun has to the diameter of the earth a ratio greater
than 19 : 3 but less than 43 : 6. In the second half of the proof he
has to handle quite large numbers. If A be the centre of the sun, B the
centre of the earth, and M the vertex of the cone formed by the earth’s
shadow, he proves that MA : AB is greater than (10125 × 7087) : (9146
× 6750) or 71755875 : 61735500, and then adds, without any word of
explanation, that the latter ratio is greater than 43 : 37. Here again
it is difficult not to see in 43 : 37 the continued fraction 1 +
11/(6+6); and although we cannot suppose that the Greeks could actually
develop 71755875/61735500 or 21261/18292 as a continued fraction (in
_form_), “we have here an important proof of the employment by the
ancients of a method of calculation, the theory of which unquestionably
belongs to the moderns, but the first applications of which are too
simple not to have originated in very remote times” (Paul Tannery).

The remaining propositions contain no more than arithmetical inferences
from the foregoing. Prop. 16 is to the effect that the volume of the
sun has to the volume of the earth a ratio greater than 6859 : 27 but
less than 79507 : 216 (the numbers are the cubes of those in Prop.
15); Prop. 17 proves that the diameter of the earth is to that of the
moon in a ratio greater than 108 : 43 but less than 60 : 19 (ratios
compounded of those in Props. 9 and 15), and Prop. 18 proves that the
volume of the earth is to that of the moon in a ratio greater than
1259712 : 79507 but less than 216000 : 6859.


ARISTARCHUS ON THE YEAR AND “GREAT YEAR”.

Aristarchus is said to have increased by 1/1623rd of a day Callippus’s
figure of 365¼ days as the length of the solar year, and to have given
2484 years as the length of the Great Year or the period after which
the sun, the moon and the five planets return to the same position
in the heavens. Tannery has shown reason for thinking that 2484 is a
wrong reading for 2434 years, and he gives an explanation which seems
convincing of the way in which Aristarchus arrived at 2434 years as
the length of the Great Year. The Chaldæan period of 223 lunations was
well known in Greece. Its length was calculated to be 6585⅓ days, and
in this period the sun was estimated to describe 10⅔° of its circle in
addition to 18 sidereal revolutions. The Greeks used the period called
by them _exeligmus_ which was three times the period of 223 lunations
and contained a whole number of days, namely, 19756, during which the
sun described 32° in addition to 54 sidereal revolutions. It followed
that the number of days in the sidereal year was--

  19756/(54 + 32/360) = 19756/(54 + 4/45) = (45 × 19756)/2434

      = 889020/2434 = 365¼ + 3/4868.

Now 4868/3 = 1623 - ⅓, and Aristarchus seems to have merely replaced
3/4868 by the close approximation 1/1623. The calculation was, however,
of no value because the estimate of 10⅔° over 18 sidereal revolutions
seems to have been an approximation based merely on the difference
between 6585⅓ days and 18 years of 365¼ days, i.e. 6574½ days; thus
the 10⅔° itself probably depended on a solar year of 365¼ days, and
Aristarchus’s evaluation of it as 365¼ 1/1623 was really a sort of
circular argument like the similar calculation of the length of the
year made by Œnopides of Chios.


LATER IMPROVEMENTS ON ARISTARCHUS’S FIGURES.

It may interest the reader to know how far Aristarchus’s estimates of
sizes and distances were improved upon by later Greek astronomers. We
are not informed how large he conceived the earth to be; but Archimedes
tells us that “some have tried to prove that the circumference of
the earth is about 300,000 stades and not greater,” and it may be
presumed that Aristarchus would, like Archimedes, be content with this
estimate. It is probable that it was Dicaearchus who (about 300 B.C.)
arrived at this value, and that it was obtained by taking 24° (1/15th
of the whole meridian circle) as the difference of latitude between
Syene and Lysimachia (on the same meridian) and 20,000 stades as the
actual distance between the two places. Eratosthenes, born a few years
after Archimedes, say 284 B.C., is famous for a better measurement of
the earth which was based on scientific principles. He found that at
noon at the summer solstice the sun threw no shadow at Syene, whereas
at the same hour at Alexandria (which he took to be on the same
meridian) a vertical stick cast a shadow corresponding to 1/50th of the
meridian circle. Assuming then that the sun’s rays at the two places
are parallel in direction, and knowing the distance between them to
be 5000 stades, he had only to take 50 times 5000 stades to get the
circumference of the earth. He seems, for some reason, to have altered
250,000 into 252,000 stades, and this, according to Pliny’s account
of the kind of stade used, works out to about 24,662 miles, giving
for the diameter of the earth a length of 7850 miles, a surprisingly
close approximation, however much it owes to happy accidents in the
calculation.

Eratosthenes’s estimates of the sizes and distances of the sun and moon
cannot be restored with certainty in view of the defective state of
the texts of our authorities. We are better informed of Hipparchus’s
results. In the first book of a treatise on sizes and distances
Hipparchus based himself on an observation of an eclipse of the sun,
probably that of 20th November in the year 129 B.C., which was exactly
total in the region about the Hellespont, whereas at Alexandria about
⅘ths only of the diameter was obscured. From these facts Hipparchus
deduced that, if the radius of the earth be the unit, the least
distance of the moon contains 71, and the greatest 83 of these units,
the mean thus containing 77. But he reverted to the question in the
second book and proved “from many considerations” that the mean
distance of the moon is 67⅓ times the radius of the earth, and also
that the distance of the sun is 2490 times the radius of the earth.
Hipparchus also made the size (meaning thereby the solid content) of
the sun to be 1880 times that of the earth, and the size of the earth
to be 27 times that of the moon. The cube root of 1880 being about 12⅓,
the diameters of the sun, earth and moon would be in the ratio of the
numbers 12⅓, 1, ⅓. Hipparchus seems to have accepted Eratosthenes’s
estimate of 252,000 stades for the circumference of the earth.

It is curious that Posidonius (135–51 B.C.), who was much less of an
astronomer, made a much better guess at the distance of the sun from
the earth. He made it 500,000,000 stades. As he also estimated the
circumference of the earth at 240,000 stades, we may take the diameter
of the earth to be, according to Posidonius, about 76,400 stades;
consequently, if _D_ be that diameter, Posidonius made the distance of
the sun to be equal to 6545_D_ as compared with Hipparchus’s 1245_D_.

Ptolemy does not mention Hipparchus’s figures. His own estimate of
the sun’s distance was 605_D_, so that Hipparchus was far nearer the
truth. But Hipparchus’s estimate remained unknown and Ptolemy’s held
the field for many centuries; even Copernicus only made the distance
of the sun 750 times the earth’s diameter, and it was not till 1671–3
that a substantial improvement was made; observations of Mars carried
out in those years by Richer enabled Cassini to conclude that the sun’s
parallax was about 9·5″ corresponding to a distance between the sun
and the earth of 87,000,000 miles.

Ptolemy made the distance of the moon from the earth to be 29½ times
the earth’s diameter, and the diameter of the earth to be 3⅖ times that
of the moon. He estimated the diameter of the sun at 18⅘ times that of
the moon and therefore about 5½ times that of the earth, a figure again
much inferior to that given by Hipparchus.



BIBLIOGRAPHY.


On the astronomy of the early Greek philosophers much information is
given by Aristotle (especially in the _De Caelo_); for Aristotle was
fortunately in the habit of stating the views of earlier thinkers as
a preliminary to enunciating his own. Apart from what we learn from
Aristotle, we are mainly dependent on the fragmentary accounts of
the opinions of philosophers which were collected in the _Doxographi
Graeci_ of Hermann Diels (Berlin, 1879), to which must be added, for
the period before Socrates, _Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker_ by the
same editor (2nd edition, with index, 1906–10, 3rd edition, 1912).
The doxographic data and the fragments for the period from Thales to
Empedocles were translated and explained by Paul Tannery in _Pour
l’histoire de la Science Hellène_ (Paris, 1887). A History of Astronomy
was written by Eudemus of Rhodes, a pupil of Aristotle; this is lost,
but a fair number of fragments are preserved by later writers. Of the
theory of concentric spheres we have a short account in Aristotle’s
_Metaphysics_, but a more elaborate and detailed description is
contained in Simplicius’s commentary on the _De Caelo_; Simplicius
quotes largely from Sosigenes the Peripatetic (second century A.D.) who
drew upon Eudemus.

There are a number of valuable histories of Greek astronomy. In German
we have Schaubach, _Geschichte der griechischen Astronomie bis auf
Eratosthenes_, 1809; R. Wolf, _Geschichte der Astronomie_, 1877;
and two admirable epitomes (1) by Siegmund Günther in Windelband’s
_Geschichte der alten Philosophie_ (Iwan von Müller’s _Handbuch der
klassischen Altertumswissenschaft_, Vol. V, Pt. 1), 2nd edition, 1894,
and (2) by Friedrich Hultsch in Pauly-Wissowa’s _Real-Encyclopädie der
classischen Altertumswissenschaft_ (Art. Astronomie in Vol. II, 2,
1896).

In French, besides the great work of Delambre, _Histoire de
l’astronomie ancienne_, 1817, we have the valuable studies of Paul
Tannery in _Recherches sur l’histoire de l’astronomie ancienne_, 1893,
and Pierre Duhem, _Le Système du Monde_, Vol. I, 1913.

In English, reference may be made to Sir G. Cornewall Lewis, _An
Historical Survey of the Astronomy of the Ancients_, 1863; J. L. E.
Dreyer, _History of the Planetary Systems from Thales to Kepler_,
Cambridge, 1906; and the historical portion of Sir Thomas Heath’s
_Aristarchus of Samos, the ancient Copernicus_, Oxford, 1913.

Aristarchus’s treatise _On the Sizes and Distances of the Sun and
Moon_ first appeared in a Latin translation by George Valla in 1488
and 1498, and next in a Latin translation by Commandinus (1572). The
_editio princeps_ of the Greek text was brought out by John Wallis,
Oxford, 1688, and was reprinted in _Johannis Wallis Opera Mathematica_,
1693–1699, Vol. III, in both cases along with Commandinus’s
translation. In 1810 there appeared an edition by the Comte de Fortia
d’Urban, _Histoire d’Aristarque de Samos_ ... including the Greek text
and Commandinus’s translation but without figures; a French translation
by Fortia d’Urban followed in 1823. The treatise was translated into
German by A. Nokk in 1854. Finally, Sir Thomas Heath’s work above cited
contains a new Greek text with English translation and notes.



CHRONOLOGY.

(_Approximate where precise dates are not known._)


            B.C.
          624–547       Thales.
          610–546       Anaximander.
          585–526       Anaximenes.
          572–497       Pythagoras.
  born 516 or 514       Parmenides.
  (possibly 540).
          500–428       Anaxagoras.
          494–434       Empedocles.
      5th century       { Œnopides of Chios.
                        { Philolaus.
          427–347       Plato.
          408–355       Eudoxus.
          388–315       Heraclides of Pontus.
          384–322       Aristotle.
          370–300       Callippus.
          310–230       Aristarchus of Samos.
          287–212       Archimedes.
          284–203       Eratosthenes.
          265–190       Apollonius of Perga.
      3rd century       Aratus.
          fl. 150       Hipparchus.
           135–51       Posidonius.
            A.D.
           50–125       Plutarch.
          100–178       Ptolemy.


ABERDEEN: THE UNIVERSITY PRESS



Transcriber’s Notes


Punctuation and spelling were made consistent when a predominant
preference was found in this book; otherwise they were not changed.

Simple typographical errors were corrected. One unbalanced parenthesis
was remedied.

Italics are indicated by _underscores_.





*** End of this LibraryBlog Digital Book "The Copernicus of Antiquity - Aristarchus of Samos" ***

Copyright 2023 LibraryBlog. All rights reserved.



Home