Home
  By Author [ A  B  C  D  E  F  G  H  I  J  K  L  M  N  O  P  Q  R  S  T  U  V  W  X  Y  Z |  Other Symbols ]
  By Title [ A  B  C  D  E  F  G  H  I  J  K  L  M  N  O  P  Q  R  S  T  U  V  W  X  Y  Z |  Other Symbols ]
  By Language
all Classics books content using ISYS

Download this book: [ ASCII ]

Look for this book on Amazon


We have new books nearly every day.
If you would like a news letter once a week or once a month
fill out this form and we will give you a summary of the books for that week or month by email.

Title: A New Era of Thought
Author: Hinton, Charles Howard
Language: English
As this book started as an ASCII text book there are no pictures available.


*** Start of this LibraryBlog Digital Book "A New Era of Thought" ***


  Transcriber’s Notes

  Text printed in italics is represented between _underscores_, bold
  face text between ~tildes~. Small capitals have been transcribed as
  ALL CAPITALS. A letter in square brackets preceded by an equal sign,
  as [=X], represents a letter with bar above.

  More Transcriber’s Notes may be found at the end of this text.



A NEW ERA OF THOUGHT.



  SCIENTIFIC ROMANCES.

  By C. HOWARD HINTON, M.A.

  Crown 8vo, cloth gilt, 6_s._; or separately, 1_s._ each.

  1. ~What is the Fourth Dimension?~ 1_s._

  GHOSTS EXPLAINED.

  “A short treatise of admirable clearness.  .  .  . Mr. Hinton brings
  us, panting but delighted, to at least a momentary faith in the Fourth
  Dimension, and upon the eye of this faith there opens a vista of
  interesting problems.  .  .  . His pamphlet exhibits a boldness of
  speculation, and a power of conceiving and expressing even the
  inconceivable, which rouses one’s faculties like a tonic.”--_Pall
  Mall._

  2. ~The Persian King; or, The Law of the Valley~, 1_s._

  THE MYSTERY OF PLEASURE AND PAIN.

  “A very suggestive and well-written speculation, by the inheritor of
  an honoured name.”--_Mind._

  “Will arrest the attention of the reader at once.”--_Knowledge._

  3. ~A Plane World~, 1_s._

  4. ~A Picture of our Universe~, 1_s._

  5. ~Casting out the Self~, 1_s._


  _SECOND SERIES._

  1. ~On the Education of the Imagination.~

  2. ~Many Dimensions~, 1_s._

  LONDON: SWAN SONNENSCHEIN & CO.



  _A New Era of Thought._

  BY

  CHARLES HOWARD HINTON, M.A., OXON.
  _Author of “What is the Fourth Dimension,” and other “Scientific
  Romances.”_

  [Illustration]

  London:
  SWAN SONNENSCHEIN & CO.,
  PATERNOSTER SQUARE.
  1888.


  BUTLER & TANNER,
  THE SELWOOD PRINTING WORKS,
  FROME, AND LONDON.



PREFACE.


The MSS. which formed the basis of this book were committed to us by the
author, on his leaving England for a distant foreign appointment. It was
his wish that we should construct upon them a much more complete
treatise than we have effected, and with that intention he asked us to
make any changes or additions we thought desirable. But long alliance
with him in this work has convinced us that his thought (especially that
of a general philosophical character) loses much of its force if
subjected to any extraneous touch.

This feeling has induced us to print Part I. almost exactly as it came
from his hands, although it would probably have received much
rearrangement if he could have watched it through the press himself.

Part II. has been written from a hurried sketch, which he considered
very inadequate, and which we have consequently corrected and
supplemented. Chapter XI. of this part has been entirely re-written by
us, and has thus not had the advantage of his supervision. This remark
also applies to Appendix E, which is an elaboration of a theorem he
suggested. Appendix H, and all the exercises have, in accordance with
his wish, been written solely by us. It will be apparent to the reader
that Appendix H is little more than a brief introduction to a very large
subject, which, being concerned with tessaracts and solids, is really
beyond treatment in writing and diagrams.

This difficulty recalls us to the one great fact, upon which we feel
bound to insist, that the matter of this book _must_ receive objective
treatment from the reader, who will find it quite useless even to
attempt to apprehend it without actually building in squares and cubes
all the facts of space which we ask him to impress on his consciousness.
Indeed, we consider that printing, as a method of spreading
space-knowledge, is but a “pis aller,” and we would go back to that
ancient and more fruitful method of the Greek geometers, and, while
describing figures on the sand, or piling up pebbles in series, would
communicate to others that spirit of learning and generalization
begotten in our consciousness by continuous contact with facts, and only
by continuous contact with facts vitally maintained.

  ALICIA BOOLE,

  H. JOHN FALK.

N.B. Models.--It is unquestionably a most important part of the process
of learning space to construct these, and the reader should do so,
however roughly and hastily. But, if Models are required as patterns,
they may be ordered from Messrs. Swan Sonnenschein & Co., Paternoster
Square, London, and will be supplied as soon as possible, the
uncertainty as to demand for same not allowing us to have a large number
made in advance. Much of the work can be done with plain cubes by using
names without colours, but further on the reader will find colours
necessary to enable him to grasp and retain the complex series of
observations. Coloured models can easily be made by covering
Kindergarten cubes with white paper and painting them with water-colour,
and, if permanence be desired, dipping them in size and copal varnish.



TABLE OF CONTENTS.


  PART I.
                                                                    PAGE
  INTRODUCTION                                                       1-7

  CHAPTER I.
  Scepticism and Science. Beginning of Knowledge                    8-13

  CHAPTER II.
  Apprehension of Nature. Intelligence. Study of Arrangement or
  Shape                                                            14-20

  CHAPTER III.
  The Elements of Knowledge                                        21-23

  CHAPTER IV.
  Theory and Practice                                              24-28

  CHAPTER V.
  Knowledge: Self-Elements                                         29-34

  CHAPTER VI.
  Function of Mind. Space against Metaphysics. Self-Limitation and
  its Test. A Plane World                                          35-46

  CHAPTER VII.
  Self Elements in our Consciousness                               47-50

  CHAPTER VIII.
  Relation of Lower to Higher Space. Theory of the Æther           51-60

  CHAPTER IX.
  Another View of the Æther. Material and Ætherial Bodies          61-66

  CHAPTER X.
  Higher Space and Higher Being. Perception and Inspiration        67-84

  CHAPTER XI.
  Space the Scientific Basis of Altruism and Religion              85-99


  PART II.

  CHAPTER I.
  Three-space. Genesis of a Cube. Appearances of a Cube to a
  Plane-being                                                    101-112

  CHAPTER II.
  Further Appearances of a Cube to a Plane-being                 113-117

  CHAPTER III.
  Four-space. Genesis of a Tessaract; its Representation in
  Three-space                                                    118-129

  CHAPTER IV.
  Tessaract moving through Three-space. Models of the Sections   130-134

  CHAPTER V.
  Representation of Three-space by Names and in a Plane          135-148

  CHAPTER VI.
  The Means by which a Plane-being would Acquire a Conception of
  our Figures                                                    149-155

  CHAPTER VII.
  Four-space: its Representation in Three-space                  156-166

  CHAPTER VIII.
  Representation of Four-space by Name. Study of Tessaracts      167-176

  CHAPTER IX.
  Further Study of Tessaracts                                    177-179

  CHAPTER X.
  Cyclical Projections                                           180-183

  CHAPTER XI.
  A Tessaractic Figure and its Projections                       184-194


  APPENDICES.

  A. 100 Names used for Plane Space                                  197

  B. 216 Names used for Cubic Space                                  198

  C. 256 Names used for Tessaractic Space                        200-201

  D. List of Colours, Names, and Symbols                         202-203

  E. A Theorem in Four-space                                     204-205

  F. Exercises on Shapes of Three Dimensions                     205-207

  G. Exercises on Shapes of Four Dimensions                      207-209

  H. Sections of the Tessaract                                   209-217

  K. Drawings of the Cubic Sides and Sections of the Tessaract
     (Models 1-12) with Colours and Names                        219-241



INTRODUCTORY NOTE TO PART I.


At the completion of a work, or at the completion of the first part of a
work, the feelings are necessarily very different from those with which
the work was begun; and the meaning and value of the work itself bear a
very different appearance. It will therefore be the simplest and
shortest plan, if I tell the reader briefly what the work is to which
these pages are a guide, and what I consider to be its value when done.

The task was to obtain a sense of the properties of higher space, or
space of four dimensions, in the same way as that by which we reach a
sense of our ordinary three-dimensional space. I now prefer to call the
task that of obtaining a familiarity with higher matter, which shall be
as intuitive to the mind as that of ordinary matter has become. The
expression “higher matter” is preferable to “higher space,” because it
is a somewhat hasty proceeding to split this concrete matter, which we
touch and feel, into the abstractions of extension and impenetrability.
It seems to me that I cannot think of space without matter, and
therefore, as no necessity compels me to such a course, I do not split
up the concrete object into subtleties, but I simply ask: “What is that
which is to a cube or block or shape of any kind as the cube is to a
square?”

In entering upon this inquiry we find the task is twofold. Firstly,
there is the theoretical part, which is easy, viz. to set clearly before
us the relative conditions which would obtain if there were a matter
physically higher than this matter of ours, and to choose the best
means of liberating our minds from the limitations imposed on it by the
particular conditions under which we are placed. The second part of the
task is somewhat laborious, and consists of a constant presentation to
the senses of those appearances which portions of higher matter would
present, and of a continual dwelling on them, until the higher matter
becomes familiar.

The reader must undertake this task, if he accepts it at all, as an
experiment. Those of us who have done it, are satisfied that there is
that in the results of the experiment which make it well worthy of a
trial.

And in a few words I may state the general bearings of this work, for
every branch of work has its general bearings. It is an attempt, in the
most elementary and simple domain, to pass from the lower to the higher.
In pursuing it the mind passes from one kind of intuition to a higher
one, and with that transition the horizon of thought is altered. It
becomes clear that there is a physical existence transcending the
ordinary physical existence; and one becomes inclined to think that the
right direction to look is, not away from matter to spiritual
existences, but towards the discovery of conceptions of higher matter,
and thereby of those material existences whose definite relations to us
are apprehended as spiritual intuitions. Thus, “material” would simply
mean “grasped by the intellect, become known and familiar.” Our
apprehension of anything which is not expressed in terms of matter, is
vague and indefinite. To realize and live with that which we vaguely
discern, we need to apply the intuition of higher matter to the world
around us. And this seems to me the great inducement to this study. Let
us form our intuition of higher space, and then look out upon the world.

Secondly, in this progress from ordinary to higher matter, as a general
type of progress from lower to higher, we make the following
observations. Firstly, we become aware that there are certain
limitations affecting our regard. Secondly, we discover by our reason
what those limitations are, and then force ourselves to go through the
experience which would be ours if the limitations did not affect us.
Thirdly, we become aware of a capacity within us for transcending those
limitations, and for living in the higher mode as we had lived in the
previous one.

We may remark that this progress from the ordinary to the higher kind of
matter demands an absolute attention to details. It is only in the
retention of details that such progress becomes possible. And as, in
this question of matter, an absolute and unconventional examination
gives us the indication of a higher, so, doubtless, in other questions,
if we but come to facts without presupposition, we begin to know that
there is a higher and to discover indications of the way whereby we can
approach. That way lies in the fulness of detail rather than in the
generalization.

Biology has shown us that there is a universal order of forms or
organisms, passing from lower to higher. Therein we find an indication
that we ourselves take part in this progress. And in using the little
cubes we can go through the process ourselves, and learn what it is in a
little instance.

But of all the ways in which the confidence gained from this lesson can
be applied, the nearest to us lies in the suggestion it gives,--and more
than the suggestion, if inclination to think be counted for
anything,--in the suggestion of that which is higher than ourselves. We,
as individuals, are not the limit and end-all, but there is a higher
being than ours. What our relation to it is, we cannot tell, for that is
unlike our relation to anything we know. But, perhaps all that happens
to us is, could we but grasp it, our relation to it.

At any rate, the discovery of it is the great object beside which all
else is as secondary as the routine of mere existence is to
companionship. And the method of discovery is full knowledge of each
other. Thereby is the higher being to be known. In as much as the least
of us knows and is known by another, in so much does he know the higher.
Thus, scientific prayer is when two or three meet together, and, in the
belief of one higher than themselves, mutually comprehend that vision of
the higher, which each one is, and, by absolute fulness of knowledge of
the facts of each other’s personality, strive to attain a knowledge of
that which is to each of their personalities as a higher figure is to
its solid sides.

  C. H. H.



A NEW ERA OF THOUGHT.



PART I.


INTRODUCTION.

There are no new truths in this book, but it consists of an effort to
impress upon and bring home to the mind some of the more modern
developments of thought. A few sentences of Kant, a few leading ideas of
Gauss and Lobatschewski form the material out of which it is built up.

It may be thought to be unduly long; but it must be remembered that in
these times there is a twofold process going on--one of discovery about
external nature, one of education, by which our minds are brought into
harmony with that which we know. In certain respects we find ourselves
brought on by the general current of ideas--we feel that matter is
permanent and cannot be annihilated, and it is almost an axiom in our
minds that energy is persistent, and all its transformations remains the
same in amount. But there are other directions in which there is need of
definite training if we are to enter into the thoughts of the time.

And it seems to me that a return to Kant, the creator of modern
philosophy, is the first condition. Now of Kant’s enormous work only a
small part is treated here, but with the difference that should be found
between the work of a master and that of a follower. Kant’s statements
are taken as leading ideas, suggesting a field of work, and it is in
detail and manipulation merely that there is an opportunity for
workmanship.

Of Kant’s work it is only his doctrine of space which is here
experimented upon. With Kant the perception of things as being in space
is not treated as it seems so obvious to do. We should naturally say
that there is space, and there are things in it. From a comparison of
those properties which are common to all things we obtain the properties
of space. But Kant says that this property of being in space is not so
much a quality of any definable objects, as the means by which we obtain
an apprehension of definable objects--it is the condition of our mental
work.

Now as Kant’s doctrine is usually commented on, the negative side is
brought into prominence, the positive side is neglected. It is generally
said that the mind cannot perceive things in themselves, but can only
apprehend them subject to space conditions. And in this way the space
conditions are as it were considered somewhat in the light of
hindrances, whereby we are prevented from seeing what the objects in
themselves truly are. But if we take the statement simply as it is--that
we apprehend by means of space--then it is equally allowable to consider
our space sense as a positive means by which the mind grasps its
experience.

There is in so many books in which the subject is treated a certain air
of despondency--as if this space apprehension were a kind of veil which
shut us off from nature. But there is no need to adopt this feeling. The
first postulate of this book is a full recognition of the fact, that it
is by means of space that we apprehend what is. Space is the instrument
of the mind.

And here for the purposes of our work we can avoid all metaphysical
discussion. Very often a statement which seems to be very deep and
abstruse and hard to grasp, is simply the form into which deep thinkers
have thrown a very simple and practical observation. And for the present
let us look on Kant’s great doctrine of space from a practical point of
view, and it comes to this--it is important to develop the space sense,
for it is the means by which we think about real things.

There is a doctrine which found much favour with the first followers of
Kant, that also affords us a simple and practical rule of work. It was
considered by Fichte that the whole external world was simply a
projection from the _ego_, and the manifold of nature was a recognition
by the spirit of itself. What this comes to as a practical rule is, that
we can only understand nature in virtue of our own activity; that there
is no such thing as mere passive observation, but every act of sight and
thought is an activity of our own.

Now according to Kant the space sense, or the intuition of space, is the
most fundamental power of the mind. But I do not find anywhere a
systematic and thoroughgoing education of the space sense. In every
practical pursuit it is needed--in some it is developed. In geometry it
is used; but the great reason of failure in education is that, instead
of a systematic training of the space sense, it is left to be organized
by accident and is called upon to act without having been formed.
According to Kant and according to common experience it will be found
that a trained thinker is one in whom the space sense has been well
developed.

With regard to the education of the space sense, I must ask the
indulgence of the reader. It will seem obvious to him that any real
pursuit or real observation trains the space sense, and that it is going
out of the way to undertake any special discipline.

To this I would answer that, according to my own experience, I was
perfectly ignorant of space relations myself before I actually worked at
the subject, and that directly I got a true view of space facts a whole
series of conceptions, which before I had known merely by repute and
grasped by an effort, became perfectly simple and clear to me.

Moreover, to take one instance: in studying the relations of space we
always have to do with coloured objects, we always have the sense of
weight; for if the things themselves have no weight, there is always a
direction of up and down--which implies the sense of weight, and to get
rid of these elements requires careful sifting. But perhaps the best
point of view to take is this--if the reader has the space sense well
developed he will have no difficulty in going through the part of the
book which relates to it, and the phraseology will serve him for the
considerations which come next.

Amongst the followers of Kant, those who pursued one of the lines of
thought in his works have attracted the most attention and have been
considered as his successors. Fichte, Schelling, Hegel have developed
certain tendencies and have written remarkable books. But the true
successors of Kant are Gauss and Lobatchewski.

For if our intuition of space is the means by which we apprehend, then
it follows that there may be different kinds of intuitions of space. Who
can tell what the absolute space intuition is? This intuition of space
must be coloured, so to speak, by the conditions of the being which uses
it.

Now, after Kant had laid down his doctrine of space, it was important to
investigate how much in our space intuition is due to experience--is a
matter of the physical circumstances of the thinking being--and how much
is the pure act of the mind.

The only way to investigate this is the practical way, and by a
remarkable analysis the great geometers above mentioned have shown that
space is not limited as ordinary experience would seem to inform us, but
that we are quite capable of conceiving different kinds of space.

Our space as we ordinarily think of it is conceived as limited--not in
extent, but in a certain way which can only be realized when we think of
our ways of measuring space objects. It is found that there are only
three independent directions in which a body can be measured--it must
have height, length and breadth, but it has no more than these
dimensions. If any other measurement be taken in it, this new
measurement will be found to be compounded of the old measurements. It
is impossible to find a point in the body which could not be arrived at
by travelling in combinations of the three directions already taken.

But why should space be limited to three independent directions?

Geometers have found that there is no reason why bodies should be thus
limited. As a matter of fact all the bodies which we can measure are
thus limited. So we come to this conclusion, that the space which we use
for conceiving ordinary objects in the world is limited to three
dimensions. But it might be possible for there to be beings living in a
world such that they would conceive a space of four dimensions. All that
we can say about such a supposition is, that it is not demanded by our
experience. It may be that in the very large or the very minute a fourth
dimension of space will have to be postulated to account for parts--but
with regard to objects of ordinary magnitudes we are certainly not in a
four dimensional world.

And this was the point at which about ten years ago I took up the
inquiry.

It is possible to say a great deal about space of higher dimensions than
our own, and to work out analytically many problems which suggest
themselves. But can we conceive four-dimensional space in the same way
in which we can conceive our own space? Can we think of a body in four
dimensions as a unit having properties in the same way as we think of a
body having a definite shape in the space with which we are familiar?

Now this question, as every other with which I am acquainted, can only
be answered by experiment. And I commenced a series of experiments to
arrive at a conclusion one way or the other.

It is obvious that this is not a scientific inquiry--but one for the
practical teacher.

And just as in experimental researches the skilful manipulator will
demonstrate a law of nature, the less skilled manipulator will fail; so
here, everything depended on the manipulation. I was not sure that this
power lay hidden in the mind, but to put the question fairly would
surely demand every resource of the practical art of education.

And so it proved to be; for after many years of work, during which the
conception of four-dimensional bodies lay absolutely dark, at length, by
a certain change of plan, the whole subject of four-dimensional
existence became perfectly clear and easy to impart.

There is really no more difficulty in conceiving four-dimensional
shapes, when we go about it the right way, than in conceiving the idea
of solid shapes, nor is there any mystery at all about it.

When the faculty is acquired--or rather when it is brought into
consciousness, for it exists in every one in imperfect form--a new
horizon opens. The mind acquires a development of power, and in this use
of ampler space as a mode of thought, a path is opened by using that
very truth which, when first stated by Kant, seemed to close the mind
within such fast limits. Our perception is subject to the condition of
being in space. But space is not limited as we at first think.

The next step after having formed this power of conception in ampler
space, is to investigate nature and see what phenomena are to be
explained by four-dimensional relations.

But this part of the subject is hardly one for the same worker as the
one who investigates how to think in four-dimensional space. The work of
building up the power is the work of the practical educator, the work of
applying it to nature is the work of the scientific man. And it is not
possible to accomplish both tasks at the same time. Consequently the
crown is still to be won. Here the method is given of training the mind;
it will be an exhilarating moment when an investigator comes upon
phenomena which show that external nature cannot be explained except by
the assumption of a four-dimension space.

The thought of the past ages has used the conception of a
three-dimensional space, and by that means has classified many phenomena
and has obtained rules for dealing with matters of great practical
utility. The path which opens immediately before us in the future is
that of applying the conception of four-dimensional space to the
phenomena of nature, and of investigating what can be found out by this
new means of apprehension.

In fact, what has been passed through may be called the
three-dimensional era; Gauss and Lobatchewski have inaugurated the
four-dimensional era.


CHAPTER I.

SCEPTICISM AND SCIENCE. BEGINNING OF KNOWLEDGE.

The following pages have for their object to induce the reader to apply
himself to the study, in the first place of Space, and then of Higher
Space; and, therefore, I have tried by indirect means to show forth
those thoughts and conceptions to which the practical work leads.

And I feel that I have a great advantage in this project, inasmuch as
many of the thoughts which spring up in the mind of one who studies
higher space, and many of the conceptions to which he is driven, turn
out to be nothing more nor less than old truths--the property of every
mind that thinks and feels--truths which are not generally associated
with the scientific apprehension of the world, but which are not for
that reason any the less valuable.

And for my own part I cannot do more than put them forward in a very
feeble and halting manner. For I have come upon them, not in the way of
feeling or direct apprehension, but as the result of a series of works
undertaken purely with the desire to know--a desire which did not lift
itself to the height of expecting or looking for the beautiful or the
good, but which simply asked for something to know.

For I found myself--and many others I find do so also--I found myself in
respect to knowledge like a man who is in the midst of plenty and yet
who cannot find anything to eat. All around me were the evidences of
knowledge--the arts, the sciences, interesting talk, useful
inventions--and yet I myself was profited nothing at all; for somehow,
amidst all this activity, I was left alone, I could get nothing which I
could know.

The dialect was foreign to me--its inner meaning was hidden. If I would,
imitating the utterance of my fellows, say a few words, the effort was
forced, the whole result was an artificiality, and, if successful, would
be but a plausible imposture.

The word “sceptical” has a certain unpleasant association attached to
it, for it has been used by so many people who are absolutely certain in
a particular line, and attack other people’s convictions. But to be
sceptical in the real sense is a far more unpleasant state of mind to
the sceptic than to any one of his companions. For to a mind that
inquires into what it really does know, it is hardly possible to
enunciate complete sentences, much less to put before it those complex
ideas which have so large a part in true human life.

Every word we use has so wide and fugitive a meaning, and every
expression touches or rather grazes fact by so very minute a point,
that, if we wish to start with something which we do know, and thence
proceed in a certain manner, we are forced away from the study of
reality and driven to an artificial system, such as logic or
mathematics, which, starting from postulates and axioms, develops a body
of ideal truth which rather comes into contact with nature than is
nature.

Scientific achievement is reserved for those who are content to absorb
into their consciousness, by any means and by whatever way they come,
the varied appearances of nature, whence and in which by reflection they
find floating as it were on the sea of the unknown, certain
similarities, certain resemblances and analogies, by means of which they
collect together a body of possible predictions and inferences; and in
nature they find correspondences which are actually verified. Hence
science exists, although the conceptions in the mind cannot be said to
have any real correspondence in nature.

We form a set of conceptions in the mind, and the relations between
these conceptions give us relations which we find actually vibrating in
the world around us. But the conceptions themselves are essentially
artificial.

We have a conception of atoms; but no one supposes that atoms actually
exist. We suppose a force varying inversely as the square of the
distance; but no one supposes such a mysterious thing to really be in
nature. And when we come to the region of descriptive science, when we
come to simple observation, we do not find ourselves any better provided
with a real knowledge of nature. If, for instance, we think of a plant,
we picture to ourselves a certain green shape, of a more or less
definite character. This green shape enables us to recognise the plant
we think of, and to describe it to a certain extent. But if we inquire
into our imagination of it, we find that our mental image very soon
diverges from the fact. If, for instance, we cut the plant in half, we
find cells and tissues of various kinds. If we examine our idea of the
plant, it has merely an external and superficial resemblance to the
plant itself. It is a mental drawing meeting the real plant in external
appearance; but the two things, the plant and our thought of it, come as
it were from different sides--they just touch each other as far as the
colour and shape are concerned, but as structures and as living
organisms they are as wide apart as possible.

Of course by observation and study the image of a plant which we bear in
our minds may be made to resemble a plant as found in the fields more
and more. But the agreement with nature lies in the multitude of points
superadded on to the notion of greenness which we have at first--there
is no natural starting-point where the mind meets nature, and whence
they can travel hand in hand.

It almost seems as if, by sympathy and feeling, a human being was easier
to know than the simplest object. To know any object, however simple, by
the reason and observation requires an endless process of thought and
looking, building up the first vague impression into something like in
more and more respects. While, on the other hand, in dealing with human
beings there is an inward sympathy and capacity for knowing which is
independent of, though called into play by, the observation of the
actions and outward appearance of the human being.

But for the purpose of knowing we must leave out these human
relationships. They are an affair of instinct and inherited unconscious
experience. The mind may some day rise to the level of these inherited
apprehensions, and be able to explain them; but at present it is far
more than overtasked to give an account of the simplest portions of
matter, and is quite inadequate to give an account of the nature of a
human being.

Asking, then, what there was which I could know, I found no point of
beginning. There were plenty of ways of accumulating observations, but
none in which one could go hand in hand with nature.

A child is provided in the early part of its life with a provision of
food adapted for it. But it seemed that our minds are left without a
natural subsistence, for on the one hand there are arid mathematics, and
on the other there is observation, and in observation there is, out of
the great mass of constructed mental images, but little which the mind
can assimilate. To the worker at science of course this crude and
omnivorous observation is everything; but if we ask for something which
we can know, it is like a vast mass of indigestible material with every
here and there a fibre or thread which we can assimilate.

In this perplexity I was reduced to the last condition of mental
despair; and in default of finding anything which I could understand in
nature, I was sufficiently humbled to learn anything which seemed to
afford a capacity of being known.

And the objects which came before me for this endeavour were the simple
ones which will be plentifully used in the practical part of this book.
For I found that the only assertion I could make about external objects,
without bringing in unknown and unintelligible relations, was this: I
could say how things were arranged. If a stone lay between two others,
that was a definite and intelligible fact, and seemed primary. As a
stone itself, it was an unknown somewhat which one could get more and
more information about the more one studied the various sciences. But
granting that there were some things there which we call stones, the way
they were arranged was a simple and obvious fact which could be easily
expressed and easily remembered.

And so in despair of being able to obtain any other kind of mental
possession in the way of knowledge, I commenced to learn arrangements,
and I took as the objects to be arranged certain artificial objects of a
simple shape. I built up a block of cubes, and giving each a name I
learnt a mass of them.

Now I do not recommend this as a thing to be done. All I can say is that
genuinely then and now it seemed and seems to be the only kind of mental
possession which one can call knowledge. It is perfectly definite and
certain. I could tell where each cube came and how it was related to
each of the others. As to the cube itself, I was profoundly ignorant of
that; but assuming that as a necessary starting-point, taking that as
granted, I had a definite mass of knowledge.

But I do not wish to say that this is better than any kind of knowledge
which other people may find come home to them. All I want to do is to
take this humble beginning of knowledge and show how inevitably, by
devotion to it, it leads to marvellous and far-distant truths, and how,
by a strange path, it leads directly into the presence of some of the
highest conceptions which great minds have given us.

I do not think it ought to be any objection to an inquiry, that it
begins with obvious and common details. In fact I do not think that it
is possible to get anything simpler, with less of hypothesis about it,
and more obviously a simple taking in of facts than the study of the
arrangement of a block of cubes.

Many philosophers have assumed a starting point for their thought. I
want the reader to accept a very humble one and see what comes of it. If
this leads us to anything, no doubt greater results will come from more
ambitious beginnings.

And now I feel that I have candidly exposed myself to the criticism of
the reader. If he will have the patience to go on, we will begin and
build up on our foundations.


CHAPTER II.

APPREHENSION OF NATURE. INTELLIGENCE. STUDY OF ARRANGEMENT OR SHAPE.

Nature is that which is around us. But it is by no means easy to get to
nature. The savage living we may say in the bosom of nature, is
certainly unapprehensive of it, in fact it has needed the greatness of a
Wordsworth and of generations of poets and painters to open our eyes
even in a slight measure to the wonder of nature.

Thus it is clear that it is not by mere passivity that we can comprehend
nature; it is the goal of an activity, not a free gift.

And there are many ways of apprehending nature. There are the sounds and
sights of nature which delight the senses, and the involved harmonies
and the secret affinities which poetry makes us feel; then, moreover,
there is the definite knowledge of natural facts in which the memory and
reason are employed.

Thus we may divide our means of coming into contact with nature into
three main channels: the senses, the imagination, and the mind. The
imagination is perhaps the highest faculty, but we leave it out of
consideration here, and ask: How can we bring our minds into contact
with nature?

Now when we see two people of diverse characters we sometimes say that
they cannot understand one another--there is nothing in the one by which
he can understand the other--he is shut out by a limitation of his own
faculties.

And thus our power of understanding nature depends on our own
possession; it is in virtue of some mental activity of our own that we
can apprehend that outside activity which we call nature. And thus the
training to enable us to approach nature with our minds will be some
active process on our own part.

In the course of my experience as a teacher I have often been struck by
the want of the power of reason displayed by pupils; they are not able
to put two and two together, as the saying goes, and I have been at some
pains to investigate wherein this curious deficiency lies, and how it
can be supplied. And I have found that there is in the curriculum no
direct cure for it--the discipline which supplies it is not one which
comes into school methods, it is a something which most children obtain
in the natural and unsupervised education of their first contact with
the world, and lies before any recognised mode of distinction. They can
only understand in virtue of an activity of their own, and they have not
had sufficient exercise in this activity.

In the present state of education it is impossible to diverge from the
ordinary routine. But it is always possible to experiment on children
who are out of the common line of education. And I believe I am amply
justified by the result of my experiments.

I have seen that the same activity which I have found makes that habit
of mind which we call intelligence in a child, is the source of our
common and everyday rational intellectual work, and that just as the
faculties of a child can be called forth by it, so also the powers of a
man are best prepared by the same means, but on an ampler scale.

A more detailed development of the practical work of Part II., would be
the best training for the mind of a child. An extension of the work of
that Part would be the training which, hand in hand with observation
and recapitulation, would best develop a man’s thought power.

In order to tell what the activity is by the prosecution of which we can
obtain mental contact with nature we should observe what it is which we
say we “understand” in any phenomenon of nature which has become clear
to us.

When we look at a bright object it seems very different from a dull one.
A piece of bright steel hardly looks like the same substance as a piece
of dull steel. But the difference of appearance in the two is easily
accounted for by the different nature of the surface in the two cases;
in the one all the irregularities are done away with, and the rays of
light which fall on it are sent off again without being dispersed and
broken up. In the case of the dull iron the rays of light are broken up
and divided, so that they are not transmitted with intensity in any one
direction, but flung off in all sorts of directions.

Here the difference between the bright object and the dull object lies
in the arrangement of the particles on its surface and their influence
on the rays of light.

Again, with light itself the differences of colour are explained as
being the effect on us of rays of different rates of vibration. Now a
vibration is essentially this, a series of arrangements of matter which
follow each other in a closed order, so that when the set has been run
through, the first arrangement follows again. The whole theory of light
is an account of arrangements of the particles in the transmitting
medium, only the arrangements alter--are not permanent in any one
characteristic, but go through a complete cycle of varieties.

Again, when the movements of the heavenly bodies are deduced from the
theory of universal gravitation, what we primarily do is to take
account of arrangement; for the law of gravity connects the movements
which the attracted bodies tend to make with their distances, that is,
it shows how their movements depend on their arrangement. And if gravity
as a force is to be explained itself, the suppositions which have been
put forward resolve it into the effect of the movements of small bodies;
that is to say, gravity, if explained at all, is explained as the result
of the arrangement and altering arrangements of small particles.

Again, to take the idea which proceeding from Goethe casts such an
influence on botanical observation. Goethe (and also Wolf) laid down
that the parts of a flower were modified leaves--and traced the stages
and intermediate states between the ordinary green leaf and the most
gorgeous petal or stamen or carpel, so unlike a leaf in form and
function.

Now the essential value in this conception is, that it enables us to
look, upon these different organs of a plant as modifications of one and
the same organ--it enables us to think about the different varieties of
the flower head as modifications of one single plant form. We can trace
correspondences between them, and are led to possible explanations of
their growth. And all this is done by getting rid of pistil and stamen
as separate entities, and looking on them as leaves, and their parts due
to different arrangement of the leaf structure. We have reduced these
diverse objects to a common element, we have found the unit by whose
arrangements the whole is produced. And in this department of thought,
as also to take another instance, in chemistry, to understand is
practically this: we find units (leaves or atoms) combinations of which
account for the results which we see. Thus we see that that which the
mind essentially apprehends is arrangement.

And this holds over the whole range of mental work, from the simplest
observation to the most complex theory. When the eye takes in the form
of an external object there is something more than a sense impression,
something more than a sensation of greenness and light and dark. The
mind works as well as the sense, and these sense impressions are
definitely grouped in what we call the shape of the object. The
essential act of perceiving lies in the apprehension of a shape, and a
shape is an arrangement of parts. It does not matter what these parts
are; if we take meaningless dots of colour and arrange them we obtain a
shape which represents the appearance of a stone or a leaf to a certain
degree. If we want to make our representation still more like, we must
treat each of the dots as in themselves arrangements, we must compose
each of them by many strokes and dots of the brush. But even in this
case we have not got anything else besides arrangement. The ultimate
element, the small items of light and shade or of colour, are in
themselves meaningless; it is in their arrangement that the likeness of
the representation consists.

Thus, from a drawing to our notion of the planetary system, all our
contact with nature lies in this, in an appreciation of arrangement.

Hence to prepare ourselves for the understanding of nature, we must
“arrange.” In virtue of our activity in making arrangements we prepare
ourselves to do what is called understand nature. Or we may say, that
which we call understanding nature is to discern something similar in
nature to that which we do when we arrange elements into compounded
groups.

Now if we study arrangement in the active way, we must have something to
arrange; and the things we work with may be either all alike, or each of
them varying from every other.

If the elements are not alike then we are not studying pure arrangement;
but our knowledge is affected by the compound nature of that with which
we deal. If the elements are all alike, we have what we call units.
Hence the discipline preparatory for the understanding of nature is the
active arrangement of like units.

And this is very much the case with all educational processes; only the
things chosen to arrange are in general words, which are so complicated
and carry such a train of association that, unless the mind has already
acquired a knowledge of arrangement, it is puzzled and hampered, and
never gets a clear apprehension of what its work is.

Now what shall we choose for our units? Any unit would do; but it ought
to be a real thing--it ought to be something which can be touched and
seen, not something which no one has ever touched or seen, and which is
even incapable of definition, like a “number.”

I would divide studies into two classes: those which create the faculty
of arrangement, and those which use it and exercise it. Mathematics
exercises it, but I do not think it creates it; and unfortunately, in
mathematics as it is now often taught, the pupil is launched , into a
vast system of symbols--the whole use and meaning of symbols (namely, as
means to acquire a clear grasp of facts) is lost to him.

Of the possible units which will serve, I take the cube; and I have
found that whenever I took any other unit I got wrong, puzzled and lost
my way. With the cube one does not get along very fast, but everything
is perfectly obvious and simple, and builds up into a whole of which
every part is evident.

And I must ask the reader to absolutely erase from his mind all desire
or wish to be able to predict or assert anything about nature, and he
must please look with horror on any mental process by which he gets at
a truth in an ingenious but obscure and inexplicable way. Let him take
nothing which is not perfectly clear, patent and evident, demonstrable
to his senses, a simple repetition of obvious fact.

Our work will then be this: a study, by means of cubes, of the facts of
arrangement. And the process of learning will be an active one of
actually putting up the cubes. In this way we do for the mind what
Wordsworth does for the imagination--we bring it into contact with
nature.


CHAPTER III.

THE ELEMENTS OF KNOWLEDGE.

There are two elements which enter into our knowledge with respect to
any phenomenon.

If, for instance, we take the sun, and ask ourselves what we observe, we
notice that it is a bright, moving body; and of these two qualities, the
brightness and the movement, each seems equally predicable of the sun.
It does move, and it is bright.

Now further study discloses to us that there is a difference between
these two affirmations. The motion of the sun in its diurnal course
round the earth is only apparent; but it is really a bright, hot body.

Now of these two assertions which the mind naturally makes about the
sun, one--that it is moving--depends on the relation of the beholder to
the sun, the other is true about the sun itself. The observed motion
depends on a fact affecting oneself and having nothing to do with the
sun, while the brightness is really a quality of the sun itself.

Now we will call those qualities or appearances which we notice in a
body which are due to the particular conditions under which oneself is
placed in observing it, the self elements; those facts about it which
are independent of the observer’s particular relationship we will call
the residual element. Thus the sun’s motion is a self element in our
thought of the sun, its brightness is a residual element.

It is not, of course, possible to draw a line distinctly between the
self elements and the residual elements. For instance, some people have
denied that brightness is a quality of things, but that it depends on
the capacity of the being for receiving sensations; and for brightness
they would substitute the assertion that the sun is giving forth a great
deal of energy in the form of heat and light.

But there is no object in pursuing the discussion further. The main
distinction is sufficiently obvious. And it is important to separate the
self elements involved in our knowledge as far as possible, so that the
residual elements may be kept for our closer attention. By getting rid
of the self elements we put ourselves in a position in which we can
propound sensible questions. By getting rid of the notion of its
circular motion round the earth we prepare our way to study the sun as
it really is. We get the subject clear of complications and extraneous
considerations.

It would hardly be worth while to dwell on this consideration were it
not of importance in our study of arrangement. But the fact is that
directly a subject has been cleared of the self elements, it seems so
absurd to have had them introduced at all that the great difficulty
there was in getting rid of them is forgotten.

With regard to the knowledge we have at the present day about scientific
matters, there do not seem to be any self elements present. But the
worst about a self element is, that its presence is never dreamed of
till it is got rid of; to know that it is there is to have done away
with it. And thus our body of knowledge is like a fluid which keeps
clear, not because there are no substances in solution, but because
directly they become evident they fall down as precipitates.

Now one of our serious pieces of work will be to get rid of the self
elements in the knowledge of arrangement.

And the kind of knowledge which we shall try to obtain will be somewhat
different from the kind of knowledge which we have about events or
natural phenomena. In the large subjects which generally occupy the mind
the things thought of are so complicated that every detail cannot
possibly be considered. The principles of the whole are realized, and
then at any required time the principles can be worked out. Thus, with
regard to a knowledge of the planetary system, it is said to be known if
the law of movement of each of the planets is recognized, and their
positions at any one time committed to memory. It is not our habit to
remember their relative positions with regard to one another at many
intervals, so as to have an exhaustive catalogue of them in our minds.
But with regard to the elements of knowledge with which we shall work,
the subject is so simple that we may justly demand of ourselves that we
will know every detail.

And the knowledge we shall acquire will be much more one of the sense
and feeling than of the reason. We do not want to have a rule in our
minds by which we can recall the positions of the different cubes, but
we want to have an immediate apprehension of them. It was Kant who first
pointed out how much of thought there was embodied in the sense
impressions; and it is this embodied thought which we wish to form.


CHAPTER IV.

THEORY AND PRACTICE.

Both in science and in morals there is an important distinction to be
drawn between theory and practice. A knowledge of chemistry does not
consist in the intellectual appreciation of different theories and
principles, but in being able to act in accordance with the facts of
chemical combination, so that by means of the appliances of chemistry
practical results are produced. And so in morals--the theoretic
acquaintance with the principles of human action may consist with a
marked degree of ignorance of how to act amongst other human beings.

Now the use of the word “learn” has been much restricted to merely
theoretic studies. It requires to be enlarged to the scientific meaning.
And to know, should include practice in actual manipulation.

Let us take an instance. We all know what justice is, and any child can
be taught to tell the difference between acting justly and acting
unjustly. But it is a different thing to teach them to act with justice.
Something is done which affects them unpleasantly. They feel an impulse
to retaliate. In order to see what justice demands they have to put
their personal feeling on one side. They have to get rid of those
conditions under which they apprehended the effects of the action at
first, and they have to look on it from another point of view. Then they
have to act in accordance with this view.

Now there are two steps--one an intellectual one of understanding, one a
practical one of carrying out the view. Neither is a moral step. One
demands intelligence, the other the formation of a habit, and this habit
can be inculcated by precept, by reward and punishment, by various
means. But as human nature is constituted, if the habit of justice is
inculcated it touches a part of the being. There is an emotional
response. We know but little of a human being, but we can safely say
that there are depths in it, beyond the feelings of momentary resentment
and the stimulus of pleasurable or painful sensation, to which justice
is natural.

How little adequate is our physical knowledge of a human being as a
bodily frame to explain the fact of human life. Now and again we see one
of these isolated beings bound up in another, as if there was an
undiscovered physical bond between them. And in all there is this sense
of justice--a kind of indwelling verdict of the universal mind, if we
may use such an expression, in virtue of which a man feels not as a
single individual but as all men.

With respect to justice, it is not only necessary to take the view of
one other person than oneself, but that of many. There may be justice
which is very good justice from the point of view of a party, but very
bad justice from the point of view of a nation. And if we suppose an
agency outside the human race, gifted with intelligence, and affecting
the race, in the way for instance of causing storms or disturbances of
the ground, in order to judge it with justice we should have to take a
standpoint outside the race of men altogether. We could not say that
this agency was bad. We should have to judge it with reference to its
effect on other sentient beings.

There are some words which are often used in contrast with each
other--egoism and altruism; and each seems to me unmeaning except as
terms in a contrast.

Let us take an instance. A boy has a bag of cakes, and is going to enjoy
them by himself. His parent stops him, and makes him set up some stumps
and begin to learn to play cricket with another boy. The enjoyment of
the cakes is lost--he has given that up; but after a little while he has
a pleasure which is greater than that of cakes in solitude. He enters
into the life of the game. He has given up, or been forced to give up,
the pleasure he knew, and he has found a greater one. What he thought
about himself before was that he liked cakes, now what he thinks about
himself is that he likes cricket. Which of these is the true thought
about himself? Neither, probably, but at any rate it is more near the
truth to say that he likes the cricket. If now we use the word self to
mean that which a person knows of himself, and it is difficult to see
what other meaning it can have, his self as he knew it at first was
thwarted, was given up, and through that he discovered his true self.
And again with the cricket; he will make the sacrifice of giving that
up, voluntarily or involuntarily, and will find a truer self still.

In general there is not much difficulty in making a boy find out that he
likes cricket; and it is quite possible for him to eat his cakes first
and learn to play cricket afterwards--the cricket will not come to him
as a thwarting in any sense of what he likes better. But this ease in
entering in to the pursuit only shows that the boy’s nature is already
developed to the level of enjoying the game. The distinct moral advance
would come in such a case when something which at first was hard to him
to do was presented to him--and the hardness, the unpleasantness is of a
double kind, the giving up of a pursuit or indulgence to which he is
accustomed, and the exertion of forming the habits demanded by the new
pursuit.

Now it is unimportant whether the renunciation is forced or willingly
taken. But as a general rule it may be laid down, that by giving up his
own desires as he feels them at the moment, to the needs and advantage
of those around him, or to the objects which he finds before him
demanding accomplishment, a human being passes to the discovery of his
true self on and on. The process is limited by the responsibilities
which a man finds come upon him.

The method of moral advance is to acquire a practical knowledge; he must
first see what the advantage of some one other than himself would be,
and then he must act in accordance with that view of things. Then having
acted and formed a habit, he discovers a response in himself. He finds
that he really cares, and that his former limited life was not really
himself. His body and the needs of his body, so far as he can observe
them, externally are the same as before; but he has obtained an inner
and unintellectual, but none the less real, apprehension of what he is.

Thus altruism, or the sacrifice of egoism to others, is followed by a
truer egoism, or assertion of self, and this process flashed across by
the transcendent lights of religion, wherein, as in the sense of justice
and duty, untold depths in the nature of man are revealed entirely
unexpressed by the intellectual apprehension which we have of him as an
animal frame of a very high degree of development, is the normal one by
which from childhood a human being develops into the full
responsibilities of a man.

Now both in science and in conduct there are self elements. In science,
getting rid of the self elements means a truer apprehension of the facts
about one; in conduct, getting rid of the self elements means obtaining
a truer knowledge of what we are--in the way of feeling more strongly
and deeply and being bound and linked in a larger scale.

Thus without pretending to any scientific accuracy in the use of terms,
we can assign a certain amount of meaning to the expression--getting rid
of self elements. And all that we can do is to take the rough idea of
this process, and then taking our special subject matter, apply it. In
affairs of life experiments lead to disaster. But happily science is
provided wherein the desire to put theories into practice can be safely
satisfied--and good results sometimes follow. Were it not for this the
human race might before now have been utopiad from off the face of the
earth.

In experiment, manipulation is everything; we must be certain of all our
conditions, otherwise we fail assuredly and have not even the
satisfaction of knowing that our failure is due to the wrongness of our
conjectures.

And for our purposes we use a subject matter so simple that the
manipulation is easy.


CHAPTER V.

KNOWLEDGE: SELF-ELEMENTS.


I must now go with somewhat of detail into the special subject in which
these general truths will be exhibited. Everything I have to say would
be conceived much more clearly by a very little practical manipulation.

But here I want to put the subject in as general a light as possible, so
that there may be no hindrance to the judgment of the reader.

And when I use the word “know,” I assume something else than the
possession of a rule, by which it can be said how facts are. By knowing
I mean that the facts of a subject all lie in the mind ready to come out
vividly into consciousness when the attention is directed on them.
Michael Angelo knew the human frame, he could tell every little fact
about it; if he chose to call up the image, he would see mentally how
each muscle and fold of the skin lay with regard to the surrounding
parts. We want to obtain a knowledge as good as Michael Angelo’s. There
is a great difference between Michael Angelo and us; but let that
difference be expressed, not in our way of knowing, but in the
difference between the things he knew and the things we know. We take a
very simple structure and know it as absolutely as he knew the
complicated structure of the human body.

And let us take a block of cubes; any number will do, but for
convenience sake let us take a set of twenty-seven cubes put together
so as to form a large cube of twenty-seven parts. And let each of these
cubes be marked so as to be recognized, and let each have a name so that
it can be referred to. And let us suppose that we have learnt this block
of cubes so that each one is known--that is to say, its position in the
block is known and its relation to the other blocks.

Now having obtained this knowledge of the block as it stands in front of
us, let us ask ourselves if there is any self element present in our
knowledge of it.

And there is obviously this self element present. We have learnt the
cubes as they stand in accordance with our own convenience in putting
them up. We put the lowest ones first, and the others on the top of
them, and we distinctly conceive the lower ones as supporting the upper
ones. Now this fact of support has nothing to do with the block of cubes
itself, it depends on the conditions under which we come to apprehend
the block of cubes, it depends on our position on the surface of the
earth, whereby gravity is an all important factor in our experience. In
fact our sight has got so accustomed to take gravity into consideration
in its view of things, that when we look at a landscape or object with
our head upside down we do not see it inverted, but we superinduce on
the direct sense impressions our knowledge of the action of gravity, and
obtain a view differing very little from what we see when in an upright
position.

It will be found that every fact about the cubes has involved in it a
reference to up and down. It is by being above or below that we chiefly
remember where the cubes are. But above and below is a relation which
depends simply on gravity. If it were not for gravity above and below
would be interchangeable terms, instead of expressing a difference of
marked importance to us under our conditions of existence. Now we put
“being above” or “being below” into the cubes themselves and feel it a
quality in them--it defines their position. But this above or below
really comes from the conditions in which we are. It is a self element,
and as such, to obtain a true knowledge of the cubes we must get rid of
it.

And now, for the sake of a process which will be explained afterwards,
let us suppose that we cannot move the block of cubes which we have put
up. Let us keep it fixed.

In order to learn how it is independent of gravity the best way would be
to go to a place where gravity has virtually ceased to act; at the
centre of the earth, for instance, or in a freely falling shell.

But this is impossible, so we must choose another way. Let us, then,
since we cannot get rid of gravity, see what we have done already. We
have learnt the cubes, and however they are learnt, it will be found
that there is a certain set of them round which the others are mentally
grouped, as being on the right or left, above or below. Now to get our
knowledge as perfect as we can before getting rid of the self element up
and down, we have to take as central cubes in our mind different sets
again and again, until there are none which are primary to us.

Then there remains only the distinction of some being above others. Now
this can only be made to sink out of the primary place in our thoughts
by reversing the relation. If we turned the block upside down, and
learnt it in this new position, then we should learn the position of the
cubes with regard to each other with that element in them, which comes
from the action of gravity, reversed. And the true nature of the
arrangement to which we added something in virtue of our sensation of
up and down, would become purer and more isolated in our minds.

We have, however, supposed that the cubes are fixed. Then, in order to
learn them, we must put up another block showing what they would be like
in the supposed new position. We then take a set of cubes, models of the
original cubes, and by consideration we can put them in such positions
as to be an exact model of what the block of cubes would be if turned
upside down.

And here is the whole point on which the process depends. We can tell
where each cube would come, but we do not _know_ the block in this new
position. I draw a distinction between the two acts, “to tell where it
would be,” and to “know.” Telling where it would be is the preparation
for knowing. The power of assigning the positions may be called the
theory of the block. The actual knowledge is got by carrying out the
theory practically, by putting up the blocks and becoming able to
realize without effort where each one is.

It is not enough to put up the model blocks in the reverse position. It
is found that this up and down is a very obstinate element indeed, and a
good deal of work is requisite to get rid of it completely. But when it
is got rid of in one set of cubes, the faculty is formed of appreciating
shape independently of the particular parts which are above or below on
first examination. We discover in our own minds the faculty of
appreciating the facts of position independent of gravity and its
influence on us. I have found a very great difference in different minds
in this respect. To some it is easy, to some it is hard.

And to use our old instance, the discovery of this capacity is like the
discovery of a love of justice in the being who has forced himself to
act justly. It is a capacity for being able to take a view independent
of the conditions under which he is placed, and to feel in accordance
with that view. There is, so far as I know, no means of arriving
immediately at this impartial appreciation of shape. It can only be done
by, as it were, extending our own body so as to include certain cubes,
and appreciating then the relation of the other cubes to those. And
after this, by identifying ourselves with other cubes, and in turn
appreciating the relation of the other cubes to these. And the practical
putting up of the cubes is the way in which this power is gained. It
springs up with a repetition of the mechanical acts. Thus there are
three processes. 1st, An apprehension of what the position of the cubes
would be. 2nd, An actual putting of them up in accordance with that
apprehension, 3rd, The springing up in the mind of a direct feeling of
what the block is, independent of any particular presentation.

Thus the self element of up and down can be got rid of out of a block of
cubes.

And when even a little block is known like this, the mind has gained a
great deal.

Yet in the apprehension and knowledge of the block of cubes with the up
and down relation in them, there is more than in the absolute
apprehension of them. For there is the apprehension of their position
and also of the effect of gravity on them in their position.

Imagine ourselves to be translated suddenly to another part of the
universe, and to find there intelligent beings, and to hold conversation
with them. If we told them that we came from a world, and were to
describe the sun to them, saying that it was a bright, hot body which
moved round us, they would reply: You have told us something about the
sun, but you have also told us something about yourselves.

Thus in the apprehension of the sun as a body moving round us there is
more than in the apprehension of it as not moving round, for we really
in this case apprehend two things--the sun and our own conditions. But
for the purpose of further knowledge it is most important that the more
abstract knowledge should be acquired. The self element introduced by
the motion of the earth must be got rid of before the true relations of
the solar system can be made out.

And in our block of cubes, it will be found that feelings about
arrangement, and knowledge of space, which are quite unattainable with
our ordinary view of position, become simple and clear when this
discipline has been gone through.

And there can be no possible mental harm in going through this bit of
training, for all that it comes to is looking at a real thing as it
actually is--turning it round and over and learning it from every point
of view.


CHAPTER VI.

FUNCTION OF MIND. SPACE AGAINST METAPHYSICS. SELF-LIMITATION AND ITS
TEST. A PLANE WORLD.

We now pass on to the question: Are there any other self elements
present in our knowledge of the block of cubes?

When we have learnt to free it from up and down, is there anything else
to be got rid of?

It seems as if, when the cubes were thus learnt, we had got as abstract
and impersonal a bit of knowledge as possible.

But, in reality, in the relations of the cubes as we thus apprehend them
there is present a self element to which the up and down is a mere
trifle. If we think we have got absolute knowledge we are indeed walking
on a thin crust in unconsciousness of the depths below.

We are so certain of that which we are habituated to, we are so sure
that the world is made up of the mechanical forces and principles which
we familiarly deal with, that it is more of a shock than a welcome
surprise to us to find how mistaken we were.

And after all, do we suppose that the facts of distance and size and
shape are the ultimate facts of the world--is it in truth made up like a
machine out of mechanical parts? If so, where is there room for that
other which we know--more certainly, because inwardly--that reverence
and love which make life worth having? No; these mechanical relations
are our means of knowing about the world; they are not reality itself,
and their primary place in our imaginations is due to the familiarity
which we have with them, and to the peculiar limitations under which we
are.

But I do not for a moment wish to go in thought beyond physical
nature--I do not suppose that in thought we can. To the mind it is only
the body that appears, and all that I hope to do is to show material
relations, mechanism, arrangements.

But much depends on what kind of material relations we perceive outside
us. A human being, an animal and a machine are to the mind all merely
portions of matter arranged in certain ways. But the mind can give an
exhaustive account of the machine, account fairly well for the animal,
while the human being it only defines externally, leaving the real
knowledge to be supplied by other faculties.

But we must not under-estimate the work of the mind, for it is only by
the observation of and thought about the bodies with which we come into
contact that we know human beings. It is the faculty of thought that
puts us in a position to recognize a soul.

And so, too, about the universe--it is only by correct thought about it
that we can perceive its true moral nature.

And it will be found that the deadness which we ascribe to the external
world is not really there, but is put in by us because of our own
limitations. It is really the self elements in our knowledge which make
us talk of mechanical necessity, dead matter. When our limitations fall,
we behold the spirit of the world like we behold the spirit of a
friend--something which is discerned in and through the material
presentation of a body to us.

Our thought means are sufficient at present to show us human souls; but
all except human beings is, as far as science is concerned, inanimate.
One self element must be got rid of from our perception, and this will
be changed.

The one thing necessary is, that in matters of thinking we will not
admit anything that is not perfectly clear, palpable and evident. On the
mind the only conceivable demand is to seek for facts. The rock on which
so many systems of philosophy have come to grief is the attempt to put
moral principles into nature. Our only duty is to accept what we find.
Man is no more the centre of the moral world than he is of the physical
world. Then relegate the intellect to its right position of dealing with
facts of arrangement--it can appreciate structure--and let it simply
look on the world and report on it. We have to choose between
metaphysics and space thought. In metaphysics we find lofty
ideals--principles enthroned high in our souls, but which reduce the
world to a phantom, and ourselves to the lofty spectators of an arid
solitude. On the other hand, if we follow Kant’s advice, we use our
means and find realities linked together, and in the physical interplay
of forces and connexion of structure we behold the relations between
spirits--those dwelling in man and those above him.

It is difficult to explain this next self element that has to be removed
from the block of cubes; it requires a little careful preparation, in
fact our language hardly affords us the means. But it is possible to
approach indirectly, and to detect the self-element by means of an
analogy.

If we suspect there be some condition affecting ourselves which make us
perceive things not as they are, but falsely, then it is possible to
test the matter by making the supposition of other beings subject to
certain conditions, and then examining what the effect on their
experience would be of these conditions.

Thus if we make up the appearances which would present themselves to a
being subject to a limitation or condition, we shall find that this
limitation or condition, when unrecognized by him, presents itself as a
general law of his outward world, or as properties and qualities of the
objects external to him. He will, moreover, find certain operations
possible, others impossible, and the boundary line between the possible
and impossible will depend quite as much on the conditions under which
he is as on the nature of the operations.

And if we find that in our experience of the outward world there are
analogous properties and qualities of matter, analogous possibilities
and impossibilities, then it will show to us that we in our turn are
under analogous limitations, and that what we perceive as the external
world is both the external world and our own conditions. And the task
before us will be to separate the two. Now the problem we take up here
is this--to separate the self elements from the true fact. To separate
them not merely as an outward theory and intelligent apprehension, but
to separate them in the consciousness itself, so that our power of
perception is raised to a higher level. We find out that we are under
limitations. Our next step is to so familiarize ourselves with the real
aspect of things, that we perceive like beings not under our
limitations. Or more truly, we find that inward soul which itself not
subject to these limitations, is awakened to its own natural action,
when the verdicts conveyed to it through the senses are purged of the
self elements introduced by the senses.

Everything depends on this--Is there a native and spontaneous power of
apprehension, which springs into activity when we take the trouble to
present to it a view from which the self elements are eliminated? About
this every one must judge for himself. But the process whereby this
inner vision is called on is a definite one.

And just as a human being placed in natural human relationships finds in
himself a spontaneous motive towards the fulfilment of them, discovers
in himself a being whose motives transcend the limits of bodily
self-regard, so we should expect to find in our minds a power which is
ready to apprehend a more absolute order of fact than that which comes
through the senses.

I do not mean a theoretical power. A theory is always about it, and
about it only. I mean an inner view, a vision whereby the seeing mind as
it were identifies itself with the thing seen. Not the tree of
knowledge, but of the inner and vital sap which builds up the tree of
knowledge.

And if this point is settled, it will be of some use in answering the
question: What are we? Are we then bodies only? This question has been
answered in the negative by our instincts. Why should we despair of a
rational answer? Let us adopt our space thought and develop it.

The supposition which we must make is the following. Let us imagine a
smooth surface--like the surface of a table; but let the solid body at
which we are looking be very thin, so that our surface is more like the
surface of a thin sheet of metal than the top of a table.

And let us imagine small particles, like particles of dust, to lie on
this surface, and to be attracted downwards so that they keep on the
surface. But let us suppose them to move freely over the surface. Let
them never in their movements rise one over the other; let them all
singly and collectively be close to the surface. And let us suppose all
sorts of attractions and repulsions between these atoms, and let them
have all kinds of movements like the atoms of our matter have.

Then there may be conceived a whole world, and various kinds of beings
as formed out of this matter. The peculiarity about this world and these
beings would be, that neither the inanimate nor the animate members of
it would move away from the surface. Their movements would all lie in
one plane, a plane parallel to and very near the surface on which they
are.

And if we suppose a vast mass to be formed out of these atoms, and to
lie like a great round disk on the surface, compact and cohering closely
together, then this great disk would afford a support for the smaller
shapes, which we may suppose to be animate beings. The smaller shapes
would be attracted to the great disk, but would be arrested at its rim.
They would tend to the centre of the disk, but be unable to get nearer
to the centre than its rim.

Thus, as we are attracted to the centre of the earth, but walk on its
surface, the beings on this disk would be attracted to its centre, but
walk on its rim. The force of attraction which they would feel would be
the attraction of the disk. The other force of attraction, acting
perpendicularly to the plane which keeps them and all the matter of
their world to the surface, they would know nothing about. For they
cannot move either towards this force or away from it; and the surface
is quite smooth, so that they feel no friction in their movement over
it.

Now let us realize clearly one of these beings as he proceeds along the
rim of his world. Let us imagine him in the form of an outline of a
human being, with no thickness except that of the atoms of his world. As
to the mode in which he walks, we must imagine that he proceeds by
springs or hops, because there would be no room for his limbs to pass
each other.

Imagine a large disk on the table before you, and a being, such as the
one described, proceeding round it. Let there be small movable particles
surrounding him, which move out of his way as he goes along, and let
these serve him for respiration; let them constitute an atmosphere.

Forwards and backwards would be to such a being direction along the
rim--the direction in which he was proceeding and its reverse.

Then up and down would evidently be the direction away from the disk’s
centre and towards it. Thus backwards and forwards, up and down, would
both lie in the plane in which he was.

And he would have no other liberty of movement except these. Thus the
words right and left would have no meaning to him. All the directions in
which he could move, or could conceive movement possible, would be
exhausted when he had thought of the directions along the rim and at
right angles to it, both in the plane.

What he would call solid bodies, would be groups of the atoms of
his world cohering together. Such a mass of atoms would, we know,
have a slight thickness; namely, the thickness of a single atom. But
of this he would know nothing. He would say, “A solid body has two
dimensions--height (by how much it goes away from the rim) and thickness
(by how much it lies along the rim).” Thus a solid would be a
two-dimensional body, and a solid would be bounded by lines. Lines would
be all that he could see of a solid body.

Thus one of the results of the limitations under which he exists would
be, that he would say, “There are only two dimensions in real things.”

In order for his world to be permanent, we must suppose the surface on
which he is to be very compact, compared to the particles of his matter;
to be very rigid; and, if he is not to observe it by the friction of
matter moving on it, to be very smooth. And if it is very compact with
regard to his matter, the vibrations of the surface must have the effect
of disturbing the portions of his matter, and of separating compound
bodies up into simpler ones.

[Illustration: Fig. 1.]

[Illustration: Fig. 2.]

Another consequence of the limitation under which this being lies, would
be the following:--If we cut out from the corners of a piece of paper
two triangles, A B C and A′ B′ C′, and suppose them to be reduced to
such a thinness that they are capable of being put on to the imaginary
surface, and of being observed by the flat being like other bodies known
to him; he will, after studying the bounding lines, which are all that
he can see or touch, come to the conclusion that they are equal and
similar in every respect; and he can conceive the one occupying the same
space as the other occupies, without its being altered in any way.

If, however, instead of putting down these triangles into the surface on
which the supposed being lives, as shown in Fig. 1, we first of all turn
one of them over, and then put them down, then the plane-being has
presented to him two triangles, as shown in Fig. 2.

And if he studies these, he finds that they are equal in size and
similar in every respect. But he cannot make the one occupy the same
space as the other one; this will become evident if the triangles be
moved about on the surface of a table. One will not lie on the same
portion of the table that the other has marked out by lying on it.

Hence the plane-being by no means could make the one triangle in this
case coincide with the space occupied by the other, nor would he be able
to conceive the one as coincident with the other.

The reason of this impossibility is, not that the one cannot be made to
coincide, but that before having been put down on his plane it has been
turned round. It has been turned, using a direction of motion which the
plane-being has never had any experience of, and which therefore he
cannot use in his mental work any more than in his practical endeavours.

Thus, owing to his limitations, there is a certain line of possibility
which he cannot overstep. But this line does not correspond to what is
actually possible and impossible. It corresponds to a certain condition
affecting him, not affecting the triangle. His saying that it is
impossible to make the two triangles coincide, is an assertion, not
about the triangles, but about himself.

Now, to return to our own world, no doubt there are many assertions
which we make about the external world which are really assertions about
ourselves. And we have a set of statements which are precisely similar
to those which the plane-being would make about his surroundings.

Thus, he would say, there are only two independent directions; we say
there are only three.

He would say that solids are bounded by lines; we say that solids are
bounded by planes.

Moreover, there are figures about which we assert exactly the same kind
of impossibility as his plane-being did about the triangles in Fig. 2.

We know certain shapes which are equal the one to the other, which are
exactly similar, and yet which we cannot make fit into the same portion
of space, either practically or by imagination.

If we look at our two hands we see this clearly, though the two hands
are a complicated case of a very common fact of shape. Now, there is one
way in which the right hand and the left hand may practically be brought
into likeness. If we take the right-hand glove and the left-hand glove,
they will not fit any more than the right hand will coincide with the
left hand. But if we turn one glove inside out, then it will fit. Now,
to suppose the same thing done with the solid hand as is done with the
glove when it is turned inside out, we must suppose it, so to speak,
pulled through itself. If the hand were inside the glove all the time
the glove was being turned inside out, then, if such an operation were
possible, the right hand would be turned into an exact model of the left
hand. Such an operation is impossible. But curiously enough there is a
precisely similar operation which, if it were possible, would, in a
plane, turn the one triangle in Fig. 2 into the exact copy of the other.

[Illustration]

Look at the triangle in Fig. 2, A B C, and imagine the point A to move
into the interior of the triangle and to pass through it, carrying after
it the parts of the lines A B and A C to which it is attached, we should
have finally a triangle A B C, which was quite like the other of the two
triangles A′ B′ C′ in Fig. 2.

Thus we know the operation which produces the result of the “pulling
through” is not an impossible one when the plane-being is concerned.
Then may it not be that there is a way in which the results of the
impossible operation of pulling a hand through could be performed? The
question is an open one. Our feeling of it being impossible to produce
this result in any way, may be because it really is impossible, or it
may be a useful bit of information about ourselves.

Now at this point my special work comes in. If there be really a
four-dimensional world, and we are limited to a space or
three-dimensional view, then either we are absolutely three-dimensional
with no experience at all or capacity of apprehending four-dimensional
facts, or we may be, as far as our outward experience goes, so limited;
but we may really be four-dimensional beings whose consciousness is by
certain undetermined conditions limited to a section of the real space.

Thus we may really be like the plane-beings mentioned above, or we may
be in such a condition that our perceptions, not ourselves, are so
limited. The question is one which calls for experiment.

We know that if we take an animal, such as a dog or cat, we can by
careful training, and by using rewards and punishment, make them act in
a certain way, in certain defined cases, in accordance with justice; we
can produce the mechanical action. But the feeling of justice will not
be aroused; it will be but a mere outward conformity. But a human being,
if so trained, and seeing others so acting, gets a feeling of justice.

Now, if we are really four-dimensional, by going through those acts
which correspond to a four-dimensional experience (so far as we can), we
shall obtain an apprehension of four-dimensional existence--not with the
outward eye, but essentially with the mind.

And after a number of years of experiment which were entirely nugatory,
I can now lay it down as a verifiable fact, that by taking the proper
steps we can feel four-dimensional existence, that the human being
somehow, and in some way, is not simply a three-dimensional being--in
what way it is the province of science to discover. All that I shall do
here is, to put forward certain suppositions which, in an arbitrary and
forced manner, give an outline of the relation of our body to
four-dimensional existence, and show how in our minds we have faculties
by which we recognise it.


CHAPTER VII.

SELF ELEMENTS IN OUR CONSCIOUSNESS.

It is often taken for granted that our consciousness of ourselves and of
our own feelings has a sort of direct and absolute value.

It is supposed to afford a testimony which does not require to be sifted
like our consciousness of external events. But in reality it needs far
more criticism to be applied to it than any other mode of apprehension.

To a certain degree we can sift our experience of the external world,
and divide it into two portions. We can determine the self elements and
the realities. But with regard to our own nature and emotions, the
discovery which makes a science possible has yet to be made.

There are certain indications, however, springing from our observation
of our own bodies, which have a certain degree of interest.

It is found that the processes of thought and feeling are connected with
the brain. If the brain is disturbed, thoughts, sights, and sounds come
into the consciousness which have no objective cause in the external
world. Hence we may conclusively say that the human being, whatever he
is, is in contact with the brain, and through the brain with the body,
and through the body with the external world.

It is the structures and movements in the brain which the human being
perceives. It is by a structure in the brain that he apprehends nature,
not immediately. The most beautiful sights and sounds have no effect on
a human being unless there is the faculty in the brain of taking them in
and handing them on to the consciousness.

Hence, clearly, it is the movements and structure of the minute portions
of matter forming the brain which the consciousness perceives. And it is
only by models and representations made in the stuff of the brain that
the mind knows external changes.

Now, our brains are well furnished with models and representations of
the facts and events of the external world.

But a most important fact still requires its due weight to be laid upon
it.

These models and representations are made on a very minute scale--the
particles of brain matter which form images and representations are
beyond the power of the microscope in their minuteness. Hence the
consciousness primarily apprehends the movements of matter of a degree
of smallness which is beyond the power of observation in any other way.

Hence we have a means of observing the movements of the minute portions
of matter. Let us call those portions of the brain matter which are
directly instrumental in making representations of the external
world--let us call them brain molecules.

Now, these brain molecules are very minute portions of matter indeed;
generally they are made to go through movements and form structures in
such a way as to represent the movements and structures of the external
world of masses around us.

But it does not follow that the structures and movements which they
perform of their own nature are identical with the movements of the
portions of matter which we see around us in the world of matter.

It may be that these brain molecules have the power of four-dimensional
movement, and that they can go through four-dimensional movements and
form four-dimensional structures.

If so, there is a practical way of learning the movements of the very
small particles of matter--by observing, not what we can see, but what
we can think.

For, suppose these small molecules of the brain were to build up
structures and go through movements not in accordance with the rule of
representing what goes on in the external world, but in accordance with
their own activity, then they might go through four-dimensional
movements and form four-dimensional structures.

And these movements and structures would be apprehended by the
consciousness along with the other movements and structures, and would
seem as real as the others--but would have no correspondence in the
external world.

They would be thoughts and imaginations, not observations of external
facts.

Now, this field of investigation is one which requires to be worked at.

At present it is only those structures and movements of the brain
molecules which correspond to the realities of our three-dimensional
space which are in general worked at consistently. But in the practical
part of this book it will be found that by proper stimulus the brain
molecules will arrange themselves in structures representing a
four-dimensional existence. It only requires a certain amount of care to
build up mental models of higher space existences. In fact, it is
probably part of the difficulty of forming three-dimensional brain
models, that the brain molecules have to be limited in their own
freedom of motion to the requirements of the limited space in which our
practical daily life is carried on.

  _Note._--For my own part I should say that all those confusions in
  remembering which come from an image taking the place of the original
  mental model--as, for instance, the difficulty in remembering which
  way to turn a screw, and the numerous cases of images in thought
  transference--may be due to a toppling over in the brain,
  four-dimensionalwise, of the structures formed--which structures would
  be absolutely safe from being turned into image structures if the
  brain molecules moved only three-dimensionalwise.

It is remarkable how in science “explaining” means the reference of the
movements and tendencies to movement of the masses about us to the
movements and tendencies to movement of the minute portions of matter.

Thus, the behaviour of gaseous bodies--the pressure which they exert,
the laws of their cooling and intermixture are explained by tracing the
movements of the very minute particles of which they are composed.


CHAPTER VIII.

RELATION OF LOWER TO HIGHER SPACE. THEORY OF THE ÆTHER.

At this point of our inquiries the best plan is to turn to the practical
work, and try if the faculty of thinking in higher space can be awakened
in the mind.

The general outline of the method is the same as that which has been
described for getting rid of the limitation of up and down from a block
of cubes. We supposed that the block was fixed; and to get the sense of
what it would be when gravity acted in a different way with regard to
it, we made a model of it as it would be under the new circumstances. We
thought out the relations which would exist; and by practising this new
arrangement we gradually formed the direct apprehension.

And so with higher-space arrangements. We cannot put them up actually,
but we can say how they would look and be to the touch from various
sides. And we can put up the actual appearances of them, not altogether,
but as models succeeding one another; and by contemplation and active
arrangement of these different views we call upon our inward power to
manifest itself.

In preparing our general plan of work, it is necessary to make definite
assumptions with regard to our world, our universe, or we may call it
our space, in relation to the wider universe of four-dimensional space.

What our relation to it may be, is altogether undetermined. The real
relationship will require a great deal of study to apprehend, and when
apprehended will seem as natural to us as the position of the earth
among the other planets does to us now.

But we have not got to wait for this exploration in order to commence
our work of higher-space thought, for we know definitely that whatever
our real physical relationship to this wider universe may be, we are
practically in exactly the same relationship to it as the creature we
have supposed living on the surface of a smooth sheet is to the world of
threefold space.

And this relationship of a surface to a solid or of a solid, as we
conjecture, to a higher solid, is one which we often find in nature. A
surface is nothing more nor less than the relation between two things.
Two bodies touch each other. The surface is the relationship of one to
the other.

Again, we see the surface of water.

Thus our solid existence may be the contact of two four-dimensional
existences with each other; and just as sensation of touch is limited to
the surface of the body, so sensation on a larger scale may be limited
to this solid surface.

And it is a fact worthy of notice, that in the surface of a fluid
different laws obtain from those which hold throughout the mass. There
are a whole series of facts which are grouped together under the name of
surface tensions, which are of great importance in physics, and by which
the behaviour of the surfaces of liquids is governed.

And it may well be that the laws of our universe are the surface
tensions of a higher universe.

But these expressions, it is evident, afford us no practical basis for
investigation. We must assume something more definite, and because more
definite (in the absence of details drawn from experience), more
arbitrary.

And we will assume that the conditions under which we human beings are,
exactly resemble those under which the plane-beings are placed, which
have been described.

This forms the basis of our work; and the practical part of it consists
in doing, with regard to higher space, that which a plane-being would do
with regard to our space in order to enable himself to realize what it
was.

If we imagine one of these limited creatures whose life is cramped and
confined studying the facts of space existence, we find that he can do
it in two ways. He can assume another direction in addition to those
which he knows; and he can, by means of abstract reasoning, say what
would take place in an ampler kind of space than his own. All this would
be formal work. The conclusions would be abstract possibilities.

The other mode of study is this. He can take some of these facts of his
higher space and he can ponder over them in his mind, and can make up in
his plane world those different appearances which one and the same solid
body would present to him, and then he may try to realize inwardly what
his higher existence is.

Now, it is evident that if the creature is absolutely confined to a
two-dimensional existence, then anything more than such existence will
always be a mere abstract and formal consideration to him.

But if this higher-space thought becomes real to him, if he finds in his
mind a possibility of rising to it, then indeed he knows that somehow he
is not limited to his apparent world. Everything he sees and comes into
contact with may be two-dimensional; but essentially, somehow, himself
he is not two-dimensional merely.

And a precisely similar piece of work is before us. Assuming as we must
that our outer experience is limited to three-dimensional space, we
shall make up the appearances which the very simplest higher bodies
would present to us, and we shall gradually arrive at a more than merely
formal and abstract appreciation of them. We shall discover in ourselves
a faculty of apprehension of higher space similar to that which we have
of space. And thus we shall discover, each for himself, that, limited as
his senses are, he essentially somehow is not limited.

The mode and method in which this consciousness will be made general, is
the same in which the spirit of an army is formed.

The individuals enter into the service from various motives, but each
and all have to go through those movements and actions which correspond
to the unity of a whole formed out of different members. The inner
apprehension which lies in each man of a participation in a life wider
than that of his individual body, is awakened and responds; and the
active spirit of the army is formed. So with regard to higher space,
this faculty of apprehending intuitively four-dimensional relationships
will be taken up because of its practical use. Individuals will be
practically employed to do it by society because of the larger faculty
of thought which it gives. In fact, this higher-space thought means as
an affair of mental training simply the power of apprehending the
results arising from four independent causes. It means the power of
dealing with a greater number of details.

And when this faculty of higher-space thought has been formed, then the
faculty of apprehending that higher existence in which men have part,
will come into being.

It is necessary to guard here against there being ascribed to this
higher-space thought any other than an intellectual value. It has no
moral value whatever. Its only connexion with moral or ethical
considerations is the possibility it will afford of recognizing more of
the facts of the universe than we do now. There is a gradual process
going on which may be described as the getting rid of self elements.
This process is one of knowledge and feeling, and either may be
independent of the other. At present, in respect of feeling, we are much
further on than in respect to understanding, and the reason is very much
this: When a self element has been got rid of in respect of feeling, the
new apprehension is put into practice, and we live it into our
organization. But when a self element has been got rid of
intellectually, it is allowed to remain a matter of theory, not vitally
entering into the mental structure of individuals.

Thus up and down was discovered to be a self element more than a
thousand years ago; but, except as a matter of theory, we are perfect
barbarians in this respect up to the present day.

We have supposed a being living in a plane world, that is, a being of a
very small thickness in a direction perpendicular to the surface on
which he is.

Now, if we are situated analogously with regard to an ampler space,
there must be some element in our experience corresponding to each
element in the plane-being’s experience.

And it is interesting to ask, in the case of the plane-being, what his
opinion would be with respect to the surface on which he was.

He would not recognize it as a surface with which he was in contact; he
would have no idea of a motion away from it or towards it.

But he would discover its existence by the fact that movements were
transmitted along it. By its vibrating and quivering, it would impart
movement to the particles of matter lying on it.

Hence, he would consider this surface to be a medium lying between
bodies, and penetrating them. It would appear to him to have no weight,
but to be a powerful means of transmitting vibrations. Moreover, it
would be unlike any other substance with which he was acquainted,
inasmuch as he could never get rid of it. However perfect a vacuum be
made, there would be in this vacuum just as much of this unknown medium
as there was before.

Moreover, this surface would not hinder the movement of the particles of
matter over it. Being smooth, matter would slide freely over it. And
this would seem to him as if matter went freely through the medium.

Then he would also notice the fact that vibrations of this medium would
tear asunder portions of matter. The plane surface, being very compact,
compared to the masses of matter on it, would, by its vibrations, shake
them into their component parts.

Hence he would have a series of observations which tended to show that
this medium was unlike any ordinary matter with which he was acquainted.
Although matter passed freely through it, still by its shaking it could
tear matter in pieces. These would be very difficult properties to
reconcile in one and the same substance. Then it is weightless, and it
is everywhere.

It might well be that he would regard the supposition of there being a
plane surface, on which he was, as a preferable one to the hypothesis of
this curious medium; and thus he might obtain a proof of his limitations
from his observations.

Now, is there anything in our experience which corresponds to this
medium which the plane-being gets to observe?

Do we suppose the existence of any medium through which matter freely
moves, which yet by its vibrations destroys the combinations of
matter--some medium which is present in every vacuum, however perfect,
which penetrates all bodies, and yet can never be laid hold of?

These are precisely observations which have been made.

The substance which possesses all these qualities is called the æther.
And the properties of the æther are a perpetual object of investigation
in science.

Now, it is not the place here to go into details, as all we want is a
basis for work; and however arbitrary it may be, it will serve if it
enables us to investigate the properties of higher space.

We will suppose, then, that we are not in, but on the æther, only not on
it in any known direction, but that the new direction is that which
comes in. The æther is a smooth body, along which we slide, being
distant from it at every point about the thickness of an atom; or, if we
take our mean distance, being distant from it by half the thickness of
an atom measured in this new direction.

Then, just as in space objects, a cube, for instance, can stand on the
surface of a table, or on the surface over which the plane-being moves,
so on the æther can stand a higher solid.

All that the plane-being sees or touches of a cube, is the square on
which it rests.

So all that we could see or touch of a higher solid would be that part
by which it stood on the æther; and this part would be to us exactly
like any ordinary solid body. The base of a cube would be to the
plane-being like a square which is to him an ordinary solid.

Now, the two ways, in which a plane-being would apprehend a solid body,
would be by the successive appearances to him of it as it passed through
his plane; and also by the different views of one and the same solid
body which he got by turning the body over, so that different parts of
its surface come into contact with his plane.

And the practical work of learning to think in four-dimensional space,
is to go through the appearances which one and the same higher solid
has.

Often, in the course of investigation in nature, we come across objects
which have a certain similarity, and yet which are in parts entirely
different. The work of the mind consists in forming an idea of that
whole in which they cohere, and of which they are simple presentations.

The work of forming an idea of a higher solid is the most simple and
most definite of all such mental operations.

If we imagine a plane world in which there are objects which correspond
to our sun, to the planets, and, in fact, to all our visible universe,
we must suppose a surface of enormous extent on which great disks slide,
these disks being worlds of various orders of magnitude.

These disks would some of them be central, and hot, like our sun; round
them would circulate other disks, like our planets.

And the systems of sun and planets must be conceived as moving with
great velocity over the surface which bears them all.

And the movements of the atoms of these worlds will be the course of
events in such worlds. As the atoms weave together, and form bodies
altering, becoming, and ceasing, so will bodies be formed and
disappear.

And the plane which bears them all on its smooth surface will simply be
a support to all these movements, and influence them in no way.

Is to be conscious of being conscious of being hot, the same thing as to
be conscious of being hot? It is not the same. There is a standing
outside, and objectivation of a state of mind which every one would say
in the first state was very different from the simple consciousness. But
the consciousness must do as much in the first case as in the second.
Hence the feeling hot is very different from the consciousness of
feeling hot.

A feeling which we always have, we should not be conscious of--a sound
always present ceases to be heard. Hence consciousness is a concomitant
of change, that is, of the contact between one state and another.

If a being living on such a plane were to investigate the properties, he
would have to suppose the solid to pass through his plane in order to
see the whole of its surface. Thus we may imagine a cube resting on a
table to begin to penetrate through the table. If the cube passes
through the surface, making a clean cut all round it, so that the
plane-being can come up to it and investigate it, then the different
parts of the cube as it passes through the plane will be to him squares,
which he apprehends by the boundary lines. The cut which there is in his
plane must be supposed not to be noticed, he must be able to go right up
to the cube without hindrance, and to touch and see that thin slice of
it which is just above the plane.

And so, when we study a higher solid, we must suppose that it passes
through the æther, and that we only see that thin three-dimensional
section of it which is just about to pass from one side to the other of
the æther.

When we look on a solid as a section of a higher solid, we have to
suppose the æther broken through, only we must suppose that it runs up
to the edge of the body which is penetrating it, so that we are aware of
no breach of continuity.

The surface of the æther must then be supposed to have the properties of
the surface of a fluid; only, of course, it is a solid three-dimensional
surface, not a two-dimensional surface.


CHAPTER IX.

ANOTHER VIEW OF THE ÆTHER. MATERIAL AND ÆTHERIAL BODIES.

We have supposed in the case of a plane world that the surface on which
the movements take place is inactive, except by its vibrations. It is
simply a smooth support.

For the sake of simplicity let us call this smooth surface “the æther”
in the case of a plane world.

The æther then we have imagined to be simply a smooth, thin sheet, not
possessed of any definite structure, but excited by real disturbances of
the matter on it into vibrations, which carry the effect of these
disturbances as light and heat to other portions of matter. Now, it is
possible to take an entirely different view of the æther in the case of
a plane world.

Let us imagine that, instead of the æther being a smooth sheet serving
simply as a support, it is definitely marked and grooved.

Let us imagine these grooves and channels to be very minute, but to be
definite and permanent.

Then, let us suppose that, instead of the matter which slides in the
æther having attractions and repulsions of its own, that it is quite
inert, and has only the properties of inertia.

That is to say, taking a disk or a plane world as a specimen, the whole
disk is sliding on the æther in virtue of a certain momentum which it
has, and certain portions of its matter fit into the grooves in the
æther, and move along those grooves.

The size of the portions is determined by the size of the grooves. And
let us call those portions of matter which occupy the breadth of a
groove, atoms. Then it is evident that the disk sliding along over the
æther, its atoms will move according to the arrangement of the grooves
over which the disk slides. If the grooves at any one particular place
come close together, there will be a condensation of matter at that
place when the disk passes over it; and if the grooves separate, there
will be a rarefaction of matter.

If we imagine five particles, each slipping along in its own groove, if
the particles are arranged in the form of a regular pentagon, and the
grooves are parallel, then these five particles, moving evenly on, will
maintain their positions with regard to one another, and a body would
exist like a pentagon, lasting as long as the groves remained parallel.

But if, after some distance had been traversed by the disk, and these
five particles were brought into a region where one of the grooves
tended away from the others, the shape of the pentagon would be
destroyed, it would become some irregular figure. And it is easy to see
that if the grooves separated, and other grooves came in amongst them,
along which other portions of matter were sliding, that the pentagon
would disappear as an isolated body, that its constituent matter would
be separated, and that its particles would enter into other shapes as
constituents of them, and not of the original pentagon.

Thus, in cases of greater complication, an elaborate structure may be
supposed to be formed, to alter, and to pass away; its origin, growth,
and decay being due, not to any independent motion of the particles
constituting it, but to the movement of the disk whereby its portions of
matter were brought to regions where there was a particular disposition
of the grooves.

Then the nature of the shape would really be determined by the grooves,
not by the portions of matter which passed over them--they would become
manifest as giving rise to a material form when a disk passed over them,
but they would subsist independently of the disk; and if another disk
were to pass over the same grooves, exactly the same material structures
would spring up as came into being before.

If we make a similar supposition about our æther along which our earth
slides, we may conceive the movements of the particles of matter to be
determined, not by attractions or repulsions exerted on one another, but
to be set in existence by the alterations in the directions of the
grooves of the æther along which they are proceeding.

If the grooves were all parallel, the earth would proceed without any
other motion than that of its path in the heavens.

But with an alteration in the direction of the grooves, the particles,
instead of proceeding uniformly with the mass of the earth, would begin
to move amongst each other. And by a sufficiently complicated
arrangement of grooves it may be supposed that all the movements of the
forms we see around us are due to interweaving and variously disposed
grooves.

Thus the movements, which any body goes through, would depend on the
arrangement of the æthereal grooves along which it was passing. As long
as the grooves remain grouped together in approximately the same way, it
would maintain its existence as the same body; but when the grooves
separated, and became involved with the grooves of other objects, this
body would cease to exist separately.

Thus the separate existences of the earth might conceivably be due to
the disposition of those parts of the æther over which the earth
passed. And thus any object would have to be separated into two parts,
one the æthereal form, or modification which lasted, the other the
material particles which, coming on with blind momentum, were directed
into such movements as to produce the actual objects around us.

In this way there would be two parts in any organism, the material part
and the æthereal part. There would be the material body, which soon
passes and becomes indistinguishable from any other material body, and
the æthereal body which remains.

Now, if we direct our attention to the material body, we see the
phenomena of growth, decay, and death, the coming and the passing away
of a living being, isolated during his existence, absolutely merged at
his death into the common storehouse of matter.

But if we regard the æthereal body, we find something different. We find
an organism which is not so absolutely separated from the surrounding
organisms--an organism which is part of the æther, and which is linked
to other æthereal organisms by its very substance--an organism between
which and others there exists a unity incapable of being broken, and a
common life which is rather marked than revealed by the matter which
passes over it. The æthereal body moreover remains permanently when the
material body has passed away.

The correspondences between the æthereal body and the life of an
organism such as we know, is rather to be found in the emotional region
than in the one of outward observation. To the æthereal form, all parts
of it are equally one; but part of this form corresponds to the future
of the material being, part of it to his past. Thus, care for the future
and regard for the past would be the way in which the material being
would exhibit the unity of the æthereal body, which is both his past,
his present, and his future. That is to say, suppose the æthereal body
capable of receiving an injury, an injury in one part of it would
correspond to an injury in a man’s past; an injury in another
part,--that which the material body was traversing,--would correspond to
an injury to the man at the present moment; injury to the æthereal body
at another part, would correspond to injury coming to the man at some
future time. And the self-preservation of the æthereal body, supposing
it to have such a motive, would in the last case be the motive of
regarding his own future to the man. And inasmuch as the man felt the
real unity of his æthereal body, and did not confine his attention to
his material body, which is absolutely disunited at every moment from
its future and its past--inasmuch as he apprehended his æthereal unity,
insomuch would he care for his future welfare, and consider it as equal
in importance to his present comfort. The correspondence between emotion
and physical fact would be, that the emotion of regard corresponded to
an undiscerned æthereal unity. And then also, just as the two tips of
two fingers put down on a plane, would seem to a plane-being to be two
completely different bodies, not connected together, so one and the same
æthereal body might appear as two distinct material bodies, and any
regard between the two would correspond to an apprehension of their
æthereal unity. In the supposition of an æthereal body, it is not
necessary to keep to the idea of the rigidity and permanence of the
grooves defining the motion of the matter which, passing along, exhibits
the material body. The æthereal body may have a life of its own,
relations with other æthereal bodies, and a life as full of vicissitudes
as that of the material body, which in its total orbit expresses in the
movements of matter one phase in the life of the æthereal body.

But there are certain obvious considerations which prevent any serious
dwelling on these speculations--they are only introduced here in order
to show how the conception of higher space lends itself to the
representation of certain indefinite apprehensions,--such as that of the
essential unity of the race,--and affords a possible clue to
correspondences between the emotional and the physical life.

The whole question of our relation to the æther has to be settled. That
which we call the æther is far more probably the surface of a liquid,
and the phenomena we observe due to surface tensions. Indeed, the
physical questions concern us here nothing at all. It is easy enough to
make some supposition which gives us a standing ground to discipline our
higher-space perception; and when that is trained, we shall turn round
and look at the facts.

The conception which we shall form of the universe will undoubtedly be
as different from our present one, as the Copernican view differs from
the more pleasant view of a wide immovable earth beneath a vast vault.
Indeed, any conception of our place in the universe will be more
agreeable than the thought of being on a spinning ball, kicked into
space without any means of communication with any other inhabitants of
the universe.


CHAPTER X.

HIGHER SPACE AND HIGHER BEING. PERCEPTION AND INSPIRATION.

In the instinctive and sense perception of man and nature there is all
hidden, which reflection afterwards brings into consciousness.

We are conscious of somewhat higher than each individual man when we
look at men. In some, this consciousness reaches an extreme pitch, and
becomes a religious apprehension. But in none is it otherwise than
instinctive. The apprehension is sufficiently definite to be certain.
But it is not expressible to us in terms of the reason.

Now, I have shown that by using the conception of higher space it is
easy enough to make a supposition which shall show all mankind as
physical parts of one whole. Our apparent isolation as bodies from each
other is by no means so necessary to assume as it would appear. But, of
course, a supposition of that kind is of no value, except as showing a
possibility. If we came to examine into the matter closely, we should
find a natural relationship which accounted for our consciousness being
limited as at present it is.

The first thing to be done, is to organize our higher-space perception,
and then look. We cannot tell what external objects will blend together
into the unity of a higher being. But just as the riddle of the two
hands becomes clear to us from our first inspection of higher space, so
will there grow before our eyes greater unities and greater surprises.

We have been subject to a limitation of the most absurd character. Let
us open our eyes and see the facts.

Now, it requires some training to open the eyes. For many years I worked
at the subject without the slightest success. All was mere formalism.
But by adopting the simplest means, and by a more thorough knowledge of
space, the whole flashed clear.

Space shapes can only be symbolical of four-dimensional shapes; and if
we do not deal with space shapes directly, but only treat them by
symbols on the plane--as in analytical geometry--we are trying to get a
perception of higher space through symbols of symbols, and the task is
hopeless. But a direct study of space leads us to the knowledge of
higher space. And with the knowledge of higher space there come into our
ken boundless possibilities. All those things may be real, whereof
saints and philosophers have dreamed.

Looking on the fact of life, it has become clear to the human mind, that
justice, truth, purity, are to be sought--that they are principles which
it is well to serve. And men have invented an abstract devotion to
these, and all comes together in the grand but vague conception of Duty.

But all these thoughts are to those which spring up before us as the
shadow on a bank of clouds of a great mountain is to the mountain
itself. On the piled-up clouds falls the shadow--vast, imposing, but
dark, colourless. If the beholder but turns, he beholds the mountain
itself, towering grandly with verdant pines, the snowline, and the awful
peaks.

So all these conceptions are the way in which now, with vision confined,
we apprehend the great existences of the universe. Instead of an
abstraction, what we have to serve is a reality, to which even our real
things are but shadows. We are parts of a great being, in whose
service, and with whose love, the utmost demands of duty are satisfied.

How can it not be a struggle, when the claims of righteousness mean
diminished life,--even death,--to the individual who strives? And yet to
a clear and more rational view it will be seen that in his extinction
and loss, that which he loves,--that real being which is to him shadowed
forth in the present existence of wife and child,--that being lives more
truly, and in its life those he loves are his for ever.

But, of course, there are mistakes in what we consider to be our duty,
as in everything else; and this is an additional reason for pursuing the
quest of this reality. For by the rational observance of other material
bodies than our own, we come to the conclusion that there are other
beings around us like ourselves, whom we apprehend in virtue of two
processes--the one simply a sense one of observation and reflection--the
other a process of direct apprehension.

Now, if we did not go through the sense process of observation, we
might, it is true, know that there were other human beings around us in
some subtle way--in some mesmeric feeling; but we should not have that
organized human life which, dealing with the things of the world, grows
into such complicated forms. We should for ever be good-humoured
babies--a sensuous, affectionate kind of jelly-fish.

And just so now with reference to the high intelligences by whom we are
surrounded. We feel them, but we do not realize them.

To realize them, it will be necessary to develop our power of
perception.

The power of seeing with our bodily eye is limited to the
three-dimensional section.

But I have shown that the inner eye is not thus limited; that we can
organize our power of seeing in higher space, and that we can form
conceptions of realities in this higher space, just as we can in our
ordinary space.

And this affords the groundwork for the perception and study of these
other beings than man. Just as some mechanical means are necessary for
the apprehension of our fellows in space, so a certain amount of
mechanical education is necessary for the perception of higher beings in
higher space.

Let us turn the current of our thought right round; instead of seeking
after abstractions, and connecting our observations by ideas, let us
train our sense of higher space and build up conceptions of greater
realities, more absolute existences.

It is really a waste of time to write or read more generalities. Here is
the grammar of the knowledge of higher being--let us learn it, not spend
time in speculating as to whither it will lead us.

Yet one thing more. We are, with reference to the higher things of life,
like blind and puzzled children. We know that we are members of one
body, limbs of one vine; but we cannot discern, except by instinct and
feeling, what that body is, what the vine is. If to know it would take
away our feeling, then it were well never to know it. But fuller
knowledge of other human beings does not take away our love for them;
what reason is there then to suppose that a knowledge of the higher
existences would deaden our feelings?

And then, again, we each of us have a feeling that we ourselves have a
right to exist. We demand our own perpetuation. No man, I believe, is
capable of sacrificing his life to any abstract idea; in all cases it is
the consciousness of contact with some being that enables him to make
the last human sacrifice. And what we can do by this study of higher
space, is to make this consciousness, which has been reserved for a few,
the property of all. Do we not all feel that there is a limit to our
devotion to abstractions, none to beings whom we love. And to love them,
we must know them.

Then, just as our own individual life is empty and meaningless without
those we love, so the life of the human race is empty and meaningless
without a knowledge of those that surround it. And although to some an
inner knowledge of the oneness of all men is vouchsafed, it remains to
be demonstrated to the many.

The perpetual struggle between individual interests and the common good
can only be solved by merging both impulses in a love towards one being
whose life lies in the fulfilment of each.

And this search, it seems to me, affords the needful supplement to the
inquiries of one with whose thought I have been very familiar, and to
which I return again, after having abandoned it for the purely
materialistic views which seem forced upon us by the facts of science.

All that he said seemed to me unsupported by fact, unrelated to what we
know.

But when I found that my knowledge was merely an empty pretence, that it
was the vanity of being able to predict and foretell that stood to me in
the place of an absolute apprehension of fact--when all my intellectual
possessions turned to nothingness, then I was forced into that simple
quest for fact, which, when persisted in and lived in, opens out to the
thoughts like a flower to the life-giving sun.

It is indeed a far safer course, to believe that which appeals to us as
noble, than simply to ask what is true; to take that which great minds
have given, than to demand that our puny ones should be satisfied. But
I suppose there is some good to some one in the scepticism and struggle
of those who cannot follow in the safer course.

The thoughts of the inquirer to whom I allude may roughly be stated
thus:--

He saw in human life the working out of a great process, in the toil and
strain of our human history he saw the becoming of man. There is a
defect whereby we fall short of the true measure of our being, and that
defect is made good in the course of history.

It is owing to that defect that we perceive evil; and in the perception
of evil and suffering lies our healing, for we shall be forced into that
path at last, after trying every other, which is the true one.

And this, the history of the redemption of man, is what he saw in all
the scenes of life; each most trivial occurrence was great and
significant in relation to this.

And, further, he put forward a definite statement with regard to this
defect, this lack of true being, for it lay, he said, in the
self-centredness of our emotions, in the limitation of them to our
bodily selves. He looked for a time when, driven from all thoughts of
our own pain or pleasure, good or evil, we should say, in view of the
miseries of our fellow-creatures, Let me be anyhow, use my body and my
mind in any way, so that I serve.

And this, it seems to me, is the true aspiration; for, just as a note of
music flings itself into the march of the melody, and, losing itself in
it, is used for it and lost as a separate being, so we should throw
these lives of ours as freely into the service of--whom?

Here comes the difficulty. Let it be granted that we should have no
self-rights, limit our service in no way, still the question comes, What
shall we serve?

It is far happier to have some concrete object to which we are devoted,
or to be bound up in the ceaseless round of active life, wherein each
day presents so many necessities that we have no room for choice.

But besides and apart from all these, there comes to some the question,
“What does it all mean?” To others, an unlovable and gloomy aspect is
presented, wherein their life seems to be but used as a material
worthless in itself and ungifted with any dignity or honour; while to
others again, with the love of those they love, comes a cessation of all
personal interest in life, and a disappointment and feeling of
valuelessness.

And in all these cases some answer is needed. And here human duty
ceases. We cannot make objects to love. We can make machines and works
of art, but nothing which directly excites our love. To give us that
which rouses our love, is the duty of one higher than ourselves.

And yet in one respect we have a duty--we must look.

What good would it be, to surround us with objects of loving interest,
if we bury our regards in ourselves and will not see?

And does it not seem as if with lowered eyelids, till only the thinnest
slit was open, we gazed persistently, not on what is, but on the
thinnest conceivable section of it?

Let it be granted that our right attitude is, so to devote ourselves
that there is no question as to what we will do or what we will not do,
but we are perfectly obedient servants. The question is, Whom are we to
serve?

It cannot be each individual, for their claims are conflicting, and as
often as not there is more need of a master than of a servant. Moreover,
the aspect of our fellows does not always excite love, which is the only
possible inducer of the right attitude of service. If we do not love,
we can only serve for a self motive, because it is in some way good for
ourselves.

Thus it seems to me that we are reduced to this: our only duty is to
look for that which it is given us to love.

But this looking is not mere gazing. To know, we must act.

Let any one try it. He will find that unless he goes through a series of
actions corresponding to his knowledge, he gets merely a theoretic and
outside view of any facts. The way to know is this: Get somehow a means
of telling what your perceptions would be if you knew, and act in
accordance with those perceptions.

Thus, with regard to a fellow-creature, if we knew him we should feel
what his feelings are. Let us then learn his feelings, and act as if we
had them. It is by the practical work of satisfying his needs that we
get to know him.

Then, may-be, we love him; or perchance it is said we may find that
through him we have been brought into contact with one greater than him.

This is our duty--to know--to know, not merely theoretically, but
practically; and then, when we know, we have done our part; if there is
nothing, we cannot supply it. All we have to do is to look for
realities.

We must not take this view of education--that we are horribly pressed
for time, and must learn, somehow, a knack of saying how things must be,
without looking at them.

But rather, we must say that we have a long time--all our lives, in
which we will press facts closer and closer to our minds; and we begin
by learning the simplest. There is an idea in that home of our
inspiration--the fact that there are certain mechanical processes by
which men can acquire merit. This is perfectly true. It is by mechanical
processes that we become different; and the science of education
consists largely in systematizing these processes.

Then, just as space perceptions are necessary for the knowledge of our
fellow-men, and enable us to enter into human relationships with them in
all the organized variety of civilized life, so it is necessary to
develop our perceptions of higher space, so that we can apprehend with
our minds the relationship which we have to beings higher than
ourselves, and bring our instinctive knowledge into clearer
consciousness.

It appears to me self-evident, that in the particular disposition of any
portion of matter, that is, in any physical action, there can be neither
right nor wrong; the thing done is perfectly indifferent.

At the same time, it is only in things done that we come into
relationship with the beings about us and higher than us. Consequently,
in the things we do lies the whole importance of our lives.

Now, many of our impulses are directly signs of a relationship in us to
a being of which we are not immediately conscious. The feeling of love,
for instance, is always directed towards a particular individual; but by
love man tends towards the preservation and improvement of his race;
thus in the commonest and most universal impulses lie his relations to
higher beings than the individuals by whom he is surrounded. Now, along
with these impulses are many instincts of a modifying tendency; and,
being altogether in the dark as to the nature of the higher beings to
whom we are related, it is difficult to say in what the service of the
higher beings consists, in what it does not. The only way is, as in
every other pre-rational department of life, to take the verdict of
those with the most insight and inspiration.

And any striving against such verdicts, and discontent with them, should
be turned into energy towards finding out exactly what relation we have
towards these higher beings by the study of Space.

Human life at present is an art constructed in its regulations and rules
on the inspirations of those who love the undiscerned higher beings, of
which we are a part. They love these higher beings, and know their
service.

But our perceptions are coarser; and it is only by labour and toil that
we shall be brought also to see, and then lose the restraints that now
are necessary to us in the fulness of love.

Exactly what relationship there is towards us on the part of these
higher beings we cannot say in the least. We cannot even say whether
there is more than humanity before the highest; and any conception which
we form now must use the human drama as its only possible mode of
presentation.

But that there is such a relation seems clear; and the ludicrous manner,
in which our perceptions have been limited, is a sufficient explanation
of why they have not been scientifically apprehended.

The mode, in which an apprehension of these higher beings or being is at
present secured, is as follows; and it bears a striking analogy to the
mode by which the self is cut out of a block of cubes.

When we study a block of cubes, we first of all learn it, by starting
from a particular cube, and learning how all the others come with regard
to that. All the others are right or left, up or down, near or far, with
regard to that particular cube. And the line of cubes starting from this
first one, which we take as the direction in which we look, is, as it
were, an axis about which the rest of the cubes are grouped. We learn
the block with regard to this axis, so that we can mentally conceive the
disposition of every cube as it comes regarded from one point of view.
Next we suppose ourselves to be in another cube at the extremity of
another axis; and, looking from this axis, we learn the aspects of all
the cubes, and so on.

Thus we impress on the feeling what the block of cubes is like from
every axis. In this way we get a knowledge of the block of cubes.

Now, to get a knowledge of humanity, we must feel with many individuals.
Each individual is an axis as it were, and we must regard human beings
from many different axes. And as, in learning the block of cubes,
muscular action, as used in putting up the block of cubes, is the means
by which we impress on the feeling the different views of the block; so,
with regard to humanity, it is by acting with regard to the view of each
individual that a knowledge is obtained. That is to say, that, besides
sympathizing with each individual, we must act with regard to his view;
and acting so, we shall feel his view, and thus get to know humanity
from more than one axis. Thus there springs up a feeling of humanity,
and of more.

Those who feel superficially with a great many people, are like those
learners who have a slight acquaintance with a block of cubes from many
points of view. Those who have some deep attachments, are like those who
know them well from one or two points of view.

Thus there are two definite paths--one by which the instinctive feeling
is called out and developed, the other by which we gain the faculty of
rationally apprehending and learning the higher beings.

In the one way it is by the exercise of a sympathetic and active life;
in the other, by the study of higher space.

Both should be followed; but the latter way is more accessible to those
who are not good. For we at any rate have the industry to go through
mechanical operations, and know that we need something.

And after all, perhaps, the difference between the good and the rest of
us, lies rather in the former being aware. There is something outside
them which draws them to it, which they see while we do not.

There is no reason, however, why this knowledge should not become
demonstrable fact. Surely, it is only by becoming demonstrable fact that
the errors which have been necessarily introduced into it by human
weakness will fall away from it.

The rational knowledge will not replace feeling, but will form the
vehicle by which the facts will be presented to our consciousness. Just
as we learn to know our fellows by watching their deeds,--but it is
something beyond the mere power of observing them that makes us regard
them,--so the higher existences need to be known; and, when known, then
there is a chance that in the depths of our nature they will awaken
feelings towards them like the natural response of one human being to
another.

And when we reflect on what surrounds us, when we think that the beauty
of fruit and flower, the blue depths of the sky, the majesty of rock and
ocean,--all these are but the chance and arbitrary view which we have of
true being,--then we can imagine somewhat of the glories that await our
coming. How set out in exquisite loveliness are all the budding trees
and hedgerows on a spring day--from here, where they almost sing to us
in their nearness, to where, in the distance, they stand up delicately
distant and distinct in the amethyst ocean of the air! And there, quiet
and stately, revolve the slow moving sun and the stars of the night. All
these are the fragmentary views which we have of great beings to whom we
are related, to whom we are linked, did we but realize it, by a bond of
love and service in close connexions of mutual helpfulness.

Just as here and there on the face of a woman sits the divine spirit of
beauty, so that all cannot but love who look--so, presenting itself to
us in all this mingled scene of air and ocean, plain and mountain, is a
being of such loveliness that, did we but know with one accord in one
stream, all our hearts would be carried in a perfect and willing
service. It is not that we need to be made different; we have but to
look and gaze, and see that centre whereunto with joyful love all
created beings move.

But not with effortless wonder will our days be filled, but in toil and
strong exertion; for, just as now we all labour and strive for an
object, our service is bound up with things which we do--so then we find
no rest from labour, but the sense of solitude and isolation is gone.
The bonds of brotherhood with our fellow-men grow strong, for we know
one common purpose. And through the exquisite face of nature shines the
spiritual light that gives us a great and never-failing comrade.

Our task is a simple one--to lift from our mind that veil which somehow
has fallen on us, to take that curious limitation from our perception,
which at present is only transcended by inspiration.

And the means to do it is by throwing aside our reason--by giving up the
idea that what we think or are has any value. We too often sit as judges
of nature, when all we can be are her humble learners. We have but to
drink in of the inexhaustible fulness of being, pressing it close into
our minds, and letting our pride of being able to foretell vanish into
dust.

There is a curious passage in the works of Immanuel Kant,[1] in which he
shows that space must be in the mind before we can observe things in
space. “For,” he says, “since everything we conceive is conceived as
being in space, there is nothing which comes before our minds from which
the idea of space can be derived; it is equally present in the most
rudimentary perception and the most complete.” Hence he says that space
belongs to the perceiving soul itself. Without going into this argument
to abstract regions, it has a great amount of practical truth. All our
perceptions are of things in space; we cannot think of any detail,
however limited or isolated, which is not in space.

  [1] The idea of space can “nicht aus den Verhältnissen der äusseren
  Erscheinung durch Erfahrung erborgt sein, sondern diese äussere
  Erfahrung ist nur durch gedachte Vorstellung allererst möglich.”

Hence, in order to exercise our perceptive powers, it is well to have
prepared beforehand a strong apprehension of space and space relations.

And so, as we pass on, is it not easily conceivable that, with our power
of higher space perception so rudimentary and so unorganized, we should
find it impossible to perceive higher existences? That mode of
perception which it belongs to us to exercise is wanting. What wonder,
then, that we cannot see the objects which are ready, were but our own
part done?

Think how much has come into human life through exercising the power of
the three-dimensional space perception, and we can form some measure, in
a faint way, of what is in store for us.

There is a certain reluctance in us in bringing anything, which before
has been a matter of feeling, within the domain of conscious reason. We
do not like to explain why the grass is green, flowers bright, and,
above all, why we have the feelings which we pass through.

But this objection and instinctive reluctance is chiefly derived from
the fact that explaining has got to mean explaining away. We so often
think that a thing is explained, when it can be shown simply to be
another form of something which we know already. And, in fact, the
wearied mind often does long to have a phenomenon shown to be merely a
deduction from certain known laws.

But explanation proper is not of this kind; it is introducing into the
mind the new conception which is indicated by the phenomenon already
present. Nature consists of many entities towards the apprehension of
which we strive. If for a time we break down the bounds which we have
set up, and unify vast fields of observation under one common law, it is
that the conceptions we formed at first are inadequate, and must be
replaced by greater ones. But it is always the case, that, to understand
nature, a conception must be formed in the mind. This process of growth
in the mental history is hidden; but it is the really important one. The
new conception satisfies more facts than the old ones, is truer
phenomenally; and the arguments for it are its simplicity, its power of
accounting for many facts. But the conception has to be formed first.
And the real history of advance lies in the growth of the new
conceptions which every now and then come to light.

When the weather-wise savage looked at the sky at night, he saw many
specks of yellow light, like fire-flies, sprinkled amidst whitish
fleece; and sometimes the fleece remained, the fire-spots went, and rain
came; sometimes the fire-spots remained, and the night was fine. He did
not see that the fire-points were ever the same, the clouds different;
but by feeling dimly, he knew enough for his purpose.

But when the thinking mind turned itself on these appearances, there
sprang up,--not all at once, but gradually,--the knowledge of the
sublime existences of the distant heavens, and all the lore of the
marvellous forms of water, of air, and the movements of the earth.
Surely these realities, in which lies a wealth of embodied poetry, are
well worth the delighted sensuous apprehension of the savage as he
gazed.

Perhaps something is lost, but in the realities, of which we know, there
is compensation. And so, when we learn to understand the meaning of
these mysterious changes, this course of natural events, we shall find
in the greater realities amongst which we move a fair exchange for the
instinctive reverence, which they now awaken in us.

In this book the task is taken up of forming the most simple and
elementary of the great conceptions that are about us. In the works of
the poets, and still more in the pages of religious thinkers, lies an
untold wealth of conception, the organization of which in our every-day
intellectual life is the work of the practical educator.

But none is capable of such simple demonstration and absolute
presentation as this of higher space, and none so immediately opens our
eyes to see the world as a different place. And, indeed, it is very
instructive; for when the new conception is formed, it is found to be
quite simple and natural. We ask ourselves what we have gained; and we
answer: Nothing; we have simply removed an obvious limitation.

And this is universally true; it is not that we must rise to the higher
by a long and laborious process. We may have a long and laborious
process to go through, but, when we find the higher, it is this: we
discover our true selves, our essential being, the fact of our lives. In
this case, we pass from the ridiculous limitation, to which our eyes
and hands seem to be subject, of acting in a mere section of space, to
the fuller knowledge and feeling of space as it is. How do we pass to
this truer intellectual life? Simply by observing, by laying aside our
intellectual powers, and by looking at what is.

We take that which is easiest to observe, not that which is easiest to
define; we take that which is the most definitely limited real thing,
and use it as our touchstone whereby to explore nature.

As it seems to me, Kant made the great and fundamental statement in
philosophy when he exploded all previous systems, and all physics were
reft from off the perceiving soul. But what he did once and for all, was
too great to be a practical means of intellectual work. The dynamic form
of his absolute insight had to be found; and it is in other works that
the practical instances of the Kantian method are to be found. For,
instead of looking at the large foundations of knowledge, the ultimate
principles of experience, late writers turned to the details of
experience, and tested every phenomenon, not with the question, What is
this? but with the question, “What makes me perceive thus?”

And surely the question, as so put, is more capable of an answer; for it
is only the percipient, as a subject of thought, about which we can
speak. The absolute soul, since it is the thinker, can never be the
subject of thought; but, as physically conditioned, it can be thought
about. Thus we can never, without committing a ludicrous error, think of
the mind of man except as a material organ of some kind; and the path of
discovery lies in investigating what the devious line of his thought
history is due to, which winds between two domains of physics--the
unknown conditions which affect the perceiver, the partially known
physics which constitute what we call the external world.

It is a pity to spend time over these reflections; if they do not seem
tame and poor compared to the practical apprehension which comes of
working with the models, then there is nothing in the whole subject. If
in the little real objects which the reader has to handle and observe
does not lie to him a poetry of a higher kind than any expressed
thought, then all these words are not only useless, but false. If, on
the other hand, there is true work to be done with them, then these
suggestions will be felt to be but mean and insufficient apprehensions.

For, in the simplest apprehension of a higher space lies a knowledge of
a reality which is, to the realities we know, as spirit is to matter;
and yet to this new vision all our solid facts and material conditions
are but as a shadow is to that which casts it. In the awakening light of
this new apprehension, the flimsy world quivers and shakes, rigid solids
flow and mingle, all our material limitations turn into graciousness,
and the new field of possibility waits for us to look and behold.


CHAPTER XI.

SPACE THE SCIENTIFIC BASIS OF ALTRUISM AND RELIGION.

The reader will doubtless ask for some definite result corresponding to
these words--something not of the nature of an hypothesis or a might-be.
And in that I can only satisfy him after my own powers. My only strength
is in detail and patience; and if he will go through the practical part
of the book, it will assuredly dawn upon him that here is the beginning
of an answer to his request. I only study the blocks and stones of the
higher life. But here they are definite enough. And the more eager he is
for personal and spiritual truth, the more eagerly do I urge him to take
up the practical work, for the true good comes to us through those who,
aspiring greatly, still submit their aspirations to fact, and who,
desiring to apprehend spirit, still are willing to manipulate matter.

The particular problem at which I have worked for more than ten years,
has been completely solved. It is possible for the mind to acquire a
conception of higher space as adequate as that of our three-dimensional
space, and to use it in the same manner.

There are two distinct ways of studying space--our familiar space at
present in use. One is that of the analyst, who treats space relations
by his algebra, and discovers marvellous relations. The other is that of
the observer or mechanician, who studies the shapes of things in space
directly.

A practical designer of machines would not find the knowledge of
geometrical analysis of immediate help to him; and an artist or
draughtsman still less so.

Now, my inquiry was, whether it was possible to get the same power of
conception of four-dimensional space, as the designer and draughtsman
have of three-dimensional space. It is possible.

And with this power it is possible for us to design machines in higher
space, and to conceive objects in this space, just as a draughtsman or
artist does.

Analytical skill is not of much use in designing a statue or inventing a
machine, or in appreciating the detail of either a work of art or a
mechanical contrivance.

And hitherto the study of four-dimensional space has been conducted by
analysis. Here, for the first time, the fact of the power of conception
of four-dimensional space is demonstrated, and the means of educating it
are given.

And I propose a complete system of work, of which the volume on four
space[2] is the first instalment.

  [2] “Science Romance,” No. I., by C. H. Hinton. Published by Swan
  Sonnenschein & Co.

I shall bring forward a complete system of four-dimensional
thought--mechanics, science, and art. The necessary condition is, that
the mind acquire the power of using four-dimensional space as it now
does three-dimensional.

And there is another condition which is no less important. We can never
see, for instance, four-dimensional pictures with our bodily eyes, but
we can with our mental and inner eye. The condition is, that we should
acquire the power of mentally carrying a great number of details.

If, for instance, we could think of the human body right down to every
minute part in its right position, and conceive its aspect, we should
have a four-dimensional picture which is a solid structure. Now, to do
this, we must form the habit of mental painting, that is, of putting
definite colours in definite positions, not with our hands on paper, but
with our minds in thought, so that we can recall, alter, and view
complicated arrangements of colour existing in thought with the same
ease with which we can paint on canvas. This is simply an affair of
industry; and the mental power latent in us in this direction is simply
marvellous.

In any picture, a stroke of the brush put on without thought is
valueless. The artist is not conscious of the thought process he goes
through. For our purpose it is necessary that the manipulation of colour
and form which the artist goes through unconsciously, should become a
conscious power, and that, at whatever sacrifice of immediate beauty,
the art of mental painting should exist beside our more unconscious art.
All that I mean is this--that in the course of our campaign it is
necessary to take up the task of learning pictures by heart, so that,
just as an artist thinks over the outlines of a figure he wants to draw,
so we think over each stroke in our pictures. The means by which this
can be done will be given in a future volume.

We throw ourselves on an enterprise in which we have to leave altogether
the direct presentation to the senses. We must acquire a
sense-perception and memory of so keen and accurate a kind that we can
build up mental pictures of greater complexity than any which we can
see. We have a vast work of organization, but it is merely organization.
The power really exists and shows itself when it is looked for.

Much fault may be found with the system of organization which I have
adopted, but it is the survivor of many attempts; and although I could
better it in parts, still I think it is best to use it until, the full
importance of the subject being realized, it will be the lifework of men
of science to reorganize the methods.

The one thing on which I must insist is this--that knowledge is of no
value, it does not exist unless it comes into the mind. To know that a
thing must be is no use at all. It must be clearly realized, and in
detail as it _is_, before it can be used.

A whole world swims before us, the apprehension of which simply demands
a patient cultivation of our powers; and then, when the faculty is
formed, we shall recognize what the universe in which we are is like. We
shall learn about ourselves and pass into a new domain.

And I would speak to some minds who, like myself, share to a large
extent the feeling of unsettledness and unfixedness of our present
knowledge.

Religion has suffered in some respects from the inaccuracy of its
statements; and it is not always seen that it consists of two parts--one
a set of rules as to the management of our relations to the physical
world about us, and to our own bodies; another, a set of rules as to our
relationship to beings higher than ourselves.

Now, on the former of these subjects, on physical facts, on the laws of
health, science has a fair standing ground of criticism, and can correct
the religious doctrines in many important respects.

But on the other part of the subject matter, as to our relationship to
beings higher than ourselves, science has not yet the materials for
judging. The proposition which underlies this book is, that we should
begin to acquire the faculties for judging.

To judge, we must first appreciate; and how far we are from appreciating
with science the fundamental religious doctrines I leave to any one to
judge.

There is absolutely no scientific basis for morality, using morality in
the higher sense of other than a code of rules to promote the greatest
physical and mental health and growth of a human being. Science does not
give us any information which is not equally acceptable to the most
selfish and most generous man; it simply tells him of means by which he
may attain his own ends, it does not show him ends.

The prosecution of science is an ennobling pursuit; but it is of
scientific knowledge that I am now speaking in itself. We have no
scientific knowledge of any existences higher than ourselves--at least,
not recognized as higher. But we have abundant knowledge of the actions
of beings less developed than ourselves, from the striking unanimity
with which all inorganic beings tend to move towards the earth’s centre,
to the almost equally uniform modes of response in elementary organized
matter to different stimuli.

The question may be put: In what way do we come into contact with these
higher beings at present? And evidently the answer is, In those ways in
which we tend to form organic unions--unions in which the activities of
individuals coalesce in a living way.

The coherence of a military empire or of a subjugated population,
presenting no natural nucleus of growth, is not one through which we
should hope to grow into direct contact with our higher destinies. But
in friendship, in voluntary associations, and above all, in the family,
we tend towards our greater life.

And it seems that the instincts of women are much more relative to this,
the most fundamental and important side of life, than are those of men.
In fact, until we know, the line of advance had better be left to the
feeling of women, as they organize the home and the social life
spreading out therefrom. It is difficult, perhaps, for a man to be
still and perceive; but if he is so, he finds that what, when thwarted,
are meaningless caprices and empty emotionalities, are, on the part of
woman, when allowed to grow freely and unchecked, the first beginnings
of a new life--the shadowy filaments, as it were, by which an organism
begins to coagulate together from the medium in which it makes its
appearance.

In very many respects men have to make the conditions, and then learn to
recognize. How can we see the higher beings about us, when we cannot
even conceive the simplest higher shapes? We may talk about space, and
use big words, but, after all, the preferable way of putting our efforts
is this: let us look first at the simplest facts of higher existence,
and then, when we have learnt to realize these, We shall be able to see
what the world presents. And then, also, light will be thrown on the
constituent organisms of our own bodies, when we see in the thorough
development of our social life a relation between ourselves and a larger
organism similar to that which exists between us and the minute
constituents of our frame.

The problem, as it comes to me, is this: it is clearly demonstrated that
self-regard is to be put on one side--and self-regard in every
respect--not only should things painful and arduous be done, but things
degrading and vile, so that they serve.

I am to sign any list of any number of deeds which the most foul
imagination can suggest, as things which I would do did the occasion
come when I could benefit another by doing them; and, in fact, there is
to be no characteristic in any action which I would shrink from did the
occasion come when it presented itself to be done for another’s sake.
And I believe that the soul is absolutely unstained by the action,
provided the regard is for another.

But this is, in truth, a dangerous doctrine; at one Sweep it puts away
all absolute commandments, all absolute verdicts of right about things,
and leaves the agent to his own judgment.

It is a kind of rule of life which requires most absolute openness, and
demands that society should frame severe and insuperable regulations;
for otherwise, with the motives of the individual thus liberated from
absolute law, endless varieties of conduct would spring forth, and the
wisdom of individual men is hardly enough to justify their irresponsible
action.

Still, it does seem that, as an ideal, the absolute absence of
self-regard is to be aimed at.

With a strong religious basis, this would work no harm, for the rules of
life, as laid down by religions, would suffice. But there are many who
do not accept these rules as any absolute indication of the will of God,
but only as the regulations of good men, which have a claim to respect
and nothing more.

And thus it seems to me that altruism--thoroughgoing altruism--hands
over those who regard it as an ideal, and who are also of a sceptical
turn of mind, to the most absolute unfixedness of theory, and, very
possibly, to the greatest errors in life.

And here we come to the point where the study of space becomes so
important.

For if this rule of altruism is the right one, if it appeals with a
great invitation to us, we need not therefore try it with less
precaution than we should use in other affairs of infinitely less
importance. When we want to know if a plank will bear, we entrust it
with a different load from that of a human body.

And if this law of altruism is the true one, let us try it where failure
will not mean the ruin of human beings.

Now, in knowledge, pure altruism means so to bury the mind in the thing
known that all particular relations of one’s self pass away. The
altruistic knowledge of the heavens would be, to feel that the stars
were vast bodies, and that I am moving rapidly. It would be, to know
this, not as a matter of theory, but as a matter of habitual feeling.

Whether this is possible, I do not know; but a somewhat similar attempt
can be made with much simpler means.

In a different place I have described the process of acquiring an
altruistic knowledge of a block of cubes; and the results of the
laborious processes involved are well worth the trouble. For as a
clearly demonstrable fact this comes before one. To acquire an absolute
knowledge of a block of cubes, so that all self relations are cast out,
means that one has to take the view of a higher being.

It suddenly comes before one, that the particular relations which are so
fixed and important, and seem so absolutely sure when one begins the
process of learning, are by no means absolute facts, but marks of a
singular limitation, almost a degradation, on one’s own part. In the
determined attempt to know the most insignificant object perfectly and
thoroughly, there flashes before one’s eyes an existence infinitely
higher than one’s own. And with that vision there comes,--I do not speak
from my own experience only,--a conviction that our existence also is
not what we suppose--that this bodily self of ours is but a limit too.
And the question of altruism, as against self-regard, seems almost to
vanish, for by altruism we come to know what we truly are.

“What we truly are,” I do not mean apart from space and matter, but what
we really are as beings having a space existence; for our way of
thinking about existence is to conceive it as the relations of bodies in
space. To think is to conceive realities in space.

Just as, to explore the distant stars of the heavens, a particular
material arrangement is necessary which we call a telescope, so to
explore the nature of the beings who are higher than us, a mental
arrangement is necessary. We must prepare our power of thinking as we
prepare a more extended power of looking. We want a structure developed
inside the skull for the one purpose, while an exterior telescope will
do for the other.

And thus it seems that the difficulties which we first apprehended fall
away.

To us, looking with half-blinded eyes at merely our own little slice of
existence, our filmy all, it seemed that altruism meant disorder,
vagary, danger.

But when we put it into practice in knowledge, we find that it means the
direct revelation of a higher being and a call to us to participate
ourselves too in a higher life--nay, a consciousness comes that we are
higher than we know.

And so with our moral life as with our intellectual life. Is it not the
case that those, who truly accept the rule of altruism, learn life in
new dangerous ways?

It is true that we must give up the precepts of religion as being the
will of God; but then we shall learn that the will of God shows itself
partly in the religious precepts, and comes to be more fully and more
plainly known as an inward spirit.

And that difficulty, too, about what we may do and what we may not,
vanishes also. For, if it is the same about our fellow-creatures as it
is about the block of cubes, when we have thrown out the self-regard
from our relationship to them, we shall feel towards them as a higher
being than man feels towards them, we shall feel towards them as they
are in their true selves, not in their outward forms, but as eternal
loving spirits.

And then those instincts which humanity feels with a secret impulse to
be sacred and higher than any temporary good will be justified--or
fulfilled.

There are two tendencies--one towards the direct cultivation of the
religious perceptions, the other to reducing everything to reason. It
will be but just for the exponents of the latter tendency to look at the
whole universe, not the mere section of it which we know, before they
deal authoritatively with the higher parts of religion.

And those who feel the immanence of a higher life in us will be needed
in this outlook on the wider field of reality, so that they, being
fitted to recognize, may tell us what lies ready for us to know.

The true path of wisdom consists in seeing that our intellect is
foolishness--that our conclusions are absurd and mistaken, not in
speculating on the world as a form of thought projected from the
thinking principle within us--rather to be amazed that our thought has
so limited the world and hidden from us its real existences. To think of
ourselves as any other than things in space and subject to material
conditions, is absurd, it is absurd on either of two hypotheses. If we
are really things in space, then of course it is absurd to think of
ourselves as if we were not so. On the other hand, if we are not things
in space, then conceiving in space is the mode in which that unknown
which we are exists as a mind. Its mental action is space-conception,
and then to give up the idea of ourselves as in space, is not to get a
truer idea, but to lose the only power of apprehension of ourselves
which we possess.

And yet there is, it must be confessed, one way in which it may be
possible for us to think without thinking of things in space.

That way is, not to abandon the use of space-thought, but to pass
through it.

When we think of space, we have to think of it as infinity extended, and
we have to think of it as of infinite dimensions. Now, as I have shown
in “The Law of the Valley,”[3] when we come upon infinity in any mode of
our thought, it is a sign that that mode of thought is dealing with a
higher reality than it is adapted for, and in struggling to represent
it, can only do so by an infinite number of terms. Now, space has an
infinite number of positions and turns, and this may be due to the
attempt forced upon us to think of things higher than space as in space.
If so, then the way to get rid of space from our thoughts, is, not to go
away from it, but to pass through it--to think about larger and larger
systems of space, and space of more and more dimensions, till at last we
get to such a representation in space of what is higher than space, that
we can pass from the space-thought to the more absolute thought without
that leap which would be necessary if we were to try to pass beyond
space with our present very inadequate representation in it of what
really is.

  [3] “Science Romances,” No. II.

Again and again has human nature aspired and fallen. The vision has
presented itself of a law which was love, a duty which carried away the
enthusiasm, and in which the conflict of the higher and lower natures
ceased because all was enlisted in one loving service. But again and
again have such attempts failed. The common-sense view, that man is
subject to law, external law, remains--that there are fates whom he must
propitiate and obey. And there is a strong sharp curb, which, if it be
not brought to bear by the will, is soon pulled tight by the world, and
one more tragedy is enacted, and the over-confident soul is brought low.

And the rock on which such attempts always split, is in the indulgence
of some limited passion. Some one object fills the soul with its image,
and in devotion to that, other things are sacrificed, until at last all
comes to ruin.

But what does this mean? Surely it is simply this, that where there
should be knowledge there is ignorance. It is not that there is too much
devotion, too much passion, but that we are ignorant and blind, and
wander in error. We do not know what it is we care for, and waste our
effort on the appearance. There is no such thing as wrong love; there is
good love and bad knowledge, and men who err, clasp phantoms to
themselves. Religion is but the search for realities; and thought,
conscious of its own limitations, is its best aid.

Let a man care for any one object--let his regard for it be as
concentrated and exclusive as you will, there will be no danger if he
truly apprehends that which he cares for. Its true being is bound up
with all the rest of existence, and, if his regard is true to one, then,
if that one is really known, his regard is true to all.

There is a question sometimes asked, which shows the mere formalism into
which we have fallen.

We ask: What is the end of existence? A mere play on words! For to
conceive existence is to feel ends. The knowledge of existence is the
caring for objects, the fear of dangers, the anxieties of love. Immersed
in these, the triviality of the question, what is the end of existence?
becomes obvious. If, however, letting reality fade away, we play with
words, some questions of this kind are possible; but they are mere
questions of words, and all content and meaning has passed out of them.

The task before us is this: we strive to find out that physical unity,
that body which men are parts of, and in the life of which their true
unity lies. The existence of this one body we know from the utterances
of those whom we cannot but feel to be inspired; we feel certain
tendencies in ourselves which cannot be explained except by a
supposition of this kind.

And, now, we set to work deliberately to form in our minds the means of
investigation, the faculty of higher-space conception. To our ordinary
space-thought, men are isolated, distinct, in great measure
antagonistic. But with the first use of the weapon of higher thought, it
is easily seen that all men may really be members of one body, their
isolation may be but an affair of limited consciousness. There is, of
course, no value as science in such a supposition. But it suggests to us
many possibilities; it reveals to us the confined nature of our present
physical views, and stimulates us to undertake the work necessary to
enable us to deal adequately with the subject.

The work is entirely practical and detailed; it is the elaboration,
beginning from the simplest objects of an experience in thought, of a
higher-space world.

To begin it, we take up those details of position and relation which are
generally relegated to symbolism or unconscious apprehension, and bring
these waste products of thought into the central position of the
laboratory of the mind. We turn all our attention on the most simple and
obvious details of our every-day experience, and thence we build up a
conception of the fundamental facts of position and arrangement in a
higher world. We next study more complicated higher shapes, and get our
space perception drilled and disciplined. Then we proceed to put a
content into our framework.

The means of doing this are twofold--observation and inspiration.

As to observation, it is hardly possible to describe the feelings of
that investigator who shall distinctly trace in the physical world, and
experimentally demonstrate the existence of the higher-space facts which
are so curiously hidden from us. He will lay the first stone for the
observation and knowledge of the higher beings to whom we are related.

As to the other means, it is obvious, surely, that if there has ever
been inspiration, there is inspiration now. Inspiration is not a unique
phenomenon. It has existed in absolutely marvellous degree in some of
the teachers of the ancient world; but that, whatever it was, which they
possessed, must be present now, and, if we could isolate it, be a
demonstrable fact.

And I would propose to define inspiration as the faculty, which, to take
a particular instance, does the following:--

If a square penetrates a line cornerwise, it marks out on the line a
segment bounded by two points--that is, we suppose a line drawn on a
piece of paper, and a square lying on the paper to be pushed so that its
corner passes over the line. Then, supposing the paper and the line to
be in the same plane, the line is interrupted by the square; and, of the
square, all that is observable in the line, is a segment bounded by two
points.

Next, suppose a cube to be pushed cornerwise through a plane, and let
the plane make a section of the cube. The section will be a plane
figure, and it will be a triangle.

Now, first, the section of a square by a line is a segment bounded by
two points; second, the section of a cube by a plane is a triangle
bounded by three lines.

Hence, we infer that the section of a figure in four dimensions
analogous to a cube, by three-dimensional space, will be a
tetrahedron--a figure bounded by four planes.

This is found to be true; with a little familiarity with
four-dimensional movements this is seen to be obvious. But I would
define inspiration as the faculty by which without actual experience
this conclusion is formed.

How it is we come to this conclusion I am perfectly unable to say.
Somehow, looking at mere formal considerations, there comes into the
mind a conclusion about something beyond the range of actual experience.

We may call this reasoning from analogy; but using this phrase does not
explain the process. It seems to me just as rational to say that the
facts of the line and plane remind us of facts which we know already
about four-dimensional figures--that they tend to bring these facts out
into consciousness, as Plato shows with the boy’s knowledge of the cube.
We must be really four-dimensional creatures, or we could not think
about four dimensions.

But whatever name we give to this peculiar and inexplicable faculty,
that we do possess it is certain; and in our investigations it will be
of service to us. We must carefully investigate existence in a plane
world, and then, making sure, and impressing on our inward sense, as we
go, every step we take with regard to a higher world, we shall be
reminded continually of fresh possibilities of our higher existence.



PART II.


CHAPTER I.

THREE-SPACE. GENESIS OF A CUBE. APPEARANCES OF A CUBE TO A PLANE-BEING.

The models consist of a set of eight and a set of four cubes. They are
marked with different colours, so as to show the properties of the
figure in Higher Space, to which they belong.

The simplest figure in one-dimensional space, that is, in a straight
line, is a straight line bounded at the two extremities. The figure in
this case consists of a length bounded by two points.

Looking at Cube 1, and placing it so that the figure 1 is uppermost, we
notice a straight line in contact with the table, which is coloured
Orange. It begins in a Gold point and ends in a Fawn point. The Orange
extends to some distance on two faces of the Cube; but for our present
purpose we suppose it to be simply a thin line.

This line we conceive to be generated in the following way. Let a point
move and trace out a line. Let the point be the Gold point, and let it,
moving, trace out the Orange line and terminate in the Fawn point. Thus
the figure consists of the point at which it begins, the point at which
it ends, and the portion between. We may suppose the point to start as a
Gold point, to change its colour to Orange during the motion, and when
it stops to become Fawn. The motion we suppose from left to right, and
its direction we call X.

If, now, this Orange line move away from us at right angles, it will
trace out a square. Let this be the Black square, which is seen
underneath Model 1. The points, which bound the line, will during this
motion trace out lines, and to these lines there will be terminal
points. Also, the Square will be terminated by a line on the opposite
side. Let the Gold point in moving away trace out a Blue line and end in
a Buff point; the Fawn point a Crimson line ending in a Terracotta
point. The Orange line, having traced a Black square, ends in a
Green-grey line. This direction, away from the observer, we call Y.

Now, let the whole Black square traced out by the Orange line move
upwards at right angles. It will trace out a new figure, a Cube. And the
edges of the square, while moving upwards, will trace out squares.
Bounding the cube, and opposite to the Black square, will be another
square. Let the Orange line moving upwards trace a Dark Blue square and
end in a Reddish line. The Gold point traces a Brown line; the Fawn
point traces a French-grey line, and these lines end in a Light-blue and
a Dull-purple point. Let the Blue line trace a Vermilion square and end
in a Deep-yellow line. Let the Buff point trace a Green line, and end in
a Red point. The Green-grey line traces a Light-yellow square and ends
in a Leaden line; the Terracotta point traces a Dark-slate line and ends
in a Deep-blue point. The Crimson line traces a Blue-green square and
ends in a Bright-blue line.

Finally, the Black square traces a Cube, the colour of which is
invisible, and ends in a white square. We suppose the colour of the cube
to be a Light-buff. The upward direction we call Z. Thus we say: The
Gold point moved Z, traces a Brown line, and ends in a Light-blue point.

We can now clearly realize and refer to each region of the cube by a
colour.

At the Gold point, lines from three directions meet, the X line Orange,
the Y line Blue, the Z line Brown.

Thus we began with a figure of one dimension, a line, we passed on to a
figure of two dimensions, a square, and ended with a figure of three
dimensions, a cube.

       *       *       *       *       *

The square represents a figure in two dimensions; but if we want to
realize what it is to a being in two dimensions, we must not look down
on it. Such a view could not be taken by a plane-being.

Let us suppose a being moving on the surface of the table and unable to
rise from it. Let it not know that it is upon anything, but let it
believe that the two directions and compounds of those two directions
are all possible directions. Moreover, let it not ask the question: “On
what am I supported?” Let it see no reason for any such question, but
simply call the smooth surface, along which it moves, Space.

Such a being could not tell the colour of the square traced by the
Orange line. The square would be bounded by the lines which surround it,
and only by breaking through one of those lines could the plane-being
discover the colour of the square.

In trying to realize the experience of a plane-being it is best to
suppose that its two dimensions are upwards and sideways, _i.e._, Z and
X, because, if there be any matter in the plane-world, it will, like
matter in the solid world, exert attractions and repulsions. The matter,
like the beings, must be supposed very thin, that is, of so slight
thickness that it is quite unnoticed by the being. Now, if there be a
very large mass of such matter lying on the table, and a plane-being be
free to move about it, he will be attracted to it in every direction.
“Towards this huge mass” would be “Down,” and “Away from it” would be
“Up,” just as “Towards the earth” is to solid beings “Down,” and “Away
from it” is “Up,” at whatever part of the globe they may be. Hence, if
we want to realize a plane-being’s feelings, we must keep the sense of
up and down. Therefore we must use the Z direction, and it is more
convenient to take Z and X than Z and Y.

Any direction lying between these is said to be compounded of the two;
for, if we move slantwise for some distance, the point reached might
have been also reached by going a certain distance X, and then a certain
distance Z, or _vice versâ_.

Let us suppose the Orange line has moved Z, and traced the Dark-blue
square ending in the Reddish line. If we now place a piece of stiff
paper against the Dark-blue square, and suppose the plane-beings to move
to and fro on that surface of the paper, which touches the square, we
shall have means of representing their experience.

To obtain a more consistent view of their existence, let us suppose the
piece of paper extended, so that it cuts through our earth and comes out
at the antipodes, thus cutting the earth in two. Then suppose all the
earth removed away, both hemispheres vanishing, and only a very thin
layer of matter left upon the paper on that side which touches the
Dark-blue square. This represents what the world would be to a
plane-being.

It is of some importance to get the notion of the directions in a
plane-world, as great difficulty arises from our notions of up and down.
We miss the right analogy if we conceive of a plane-world without the
conception of up and down.

A good plan is, to use a slanting surface, a stiff card or book cover,
so placed that it slopes upwards to the eye. Then gravity acts as two
forces. It acts (1) as a force pressing all particles upon the slanting
surface into it, and (2) as a force of gravity along the plane, making
particles tend to slip down its incline. We may suppose that in a
plane-world there are two such forces, one keeping the beings thereon to
the plane, the other acting between bodies in it, and of such a nature
that by virtue of it any large mass of plane-matter produces on small
particles around it the same effects as the large mass of solid matter
called our earth produces on small objects like our bodies situated
around it. In both cases the larger draws the smaller to itself, and
creates the sensations of up and down.

If we hold the cube so that its Dark-blue side touches a sheet of paper
held upwards to the eye, and if we then look straight down along the
paper, confining our view to that which is in actual contact with the
paper, we see the same view of the cube as a plane-being would get. We
see a Light-blue point, a Reddish line, and a Dull-purple point. The
plane-being only sees a line, just as we only see a square of the cube.

The line where the paper rests on the table may be taken as
representative of the surface of the plane-being’s earth. It would be
merely a line to him, but it would have the same property in relation to
the plane-world, as a square has in relation to a solid world; in
neither case can the notion of what in the latter is termed solidity be
quite excluded. If the plane-being broke through the line bounding his
earth, he would find more matter beyond it.

Let us now leave out of consideration the question of “up and down” in
a plane-world. Let us no longer consider it in the vertical, or ZX,
position, but simply take the surface (XY) of the table as that which
supports a plane-world. Let us represent its inhabitants by thin pieces
of paper, which are free to move over the surface of the table, but
cannot rise from it. Also, let the thickness (_i.e._, height above the
surface) of these beings be so small that they cannot discern it. Lastly
let us premise there is no attraction in their world, so that they have
not any up and down.

Placing Cube 1 in front of us, let us now ask how a plane-being could
apprehend such a cube. The Black face he could easily study. He would
find it bounded by Gold point, Orange line, Fawn point, Crimson line,
and so on. And he would discover it was Black by cutting through any of
these lines and entering it. (This operation would be equivalent to the
mining of a solid being).

But of what came above the Black square he would be completely ignorant.
Let us now suppose a square hole to be made in the table, so that the
cube could pass through, and let the cube fit the opening so exactly
that no trace of the cutting of the table be visible to the plane-being.
If the cube began to pass through, it would seem to him simply to
change, for of its motion he could not be aware, as he would not know
the direction in which it moved. Let it pass down till the White square
be just on a level with the surface of the table. The plane-being would
then perceive a Light-blue point, a Reddish line, a Dull-purple point, a
Bright-blue line, and so on. These would surround a White square, which
belonged to the same body as that to which the Black square belonged.
But in this body there would be a dimension, which was not in the
square. Our upward direction would not be apprehended by him directly.
Motion from above downwards would only be apprehended as a change in the
figure before him. He would not say that he had before him different
sections of a cube, but only a changing square. If he wanted to look at
the upper square, he could only do so when the Black square had gone an
inch below his plane. To study the upper square simultaneously with the
lower, he would have to make a model of it, and then he could place it
beside the lower one.

Looking at the cube, we see that the Reddish line corresponds precisely
to the Orange line, and the Deep-yellow to the Blue line. But if the
plane-being had a model of the upper square, and placed it on the
right-hand side of the Black square, the Deep-yellow line would come
next to the Crimson line of the Black square. There would be a
discontinuity about it. All that he could do would be to observe which
part in the one square corresponded to which part in the other.
Obviously too there lies something between the Black square and the
White.

The plane-being would notice that when a line moves in a direction not
its own, it traces out a square. When the Orange line is moved away, it
traces out the Black square. The conception of a new direction thus
obtained, he would understand that the Orange line moving so would trace
out a square, and the Blue line moving so would do the same. To us these
squares are visible as wholes, the Dark-blue, and the Vermilion. To him
they would be matters of verbal definition rather than ascertained
facts. However, given that he had the experience of a cube being pushed
through his plane, he would know there was some figure, whereof his
square was part, which was bounded by his square on one side, and by a
White square on another side. We have supposed him to make models of
these boundaries, a Black square and a White square. The Black square,
which is his solid matter, is only one boundary of a figure in Higher
Space.

But we can suppose the cube to be presented to him otherwise than by
passing through his plane. It can be turned round the Orange line, in
which case the Blue line goes out, and, after a time, the Brown line
comes in. It must be noticed that the Brown line comes into a direction
opposite to that in which the Blue line ran. These two lines are at
right angles to each other, and, if one be moved upwards till it is at
right angles to the surface of the table, the other comes on to the
surface, but runs in a direction opposite to that in which the first
ran. Thus, by turning the cube about the Orange line and the Blue line,
different sides of it can be shown to a plane-being. By combining the
two processes of turning and pushing through the plane, all the sides
can be shown to the plane-being. For instance, if the cube be turned so
that the Dark-blue square be on the plane, and it be then passed
through, the Light-yellow square will come in.

Now, if the plane-being made a set of models of these different
appearances and studied them, he could form some rational idea of the
Higher Solid which produced them. He would become able to give some
consistent account of the properties of this new kind of existence; he
could say what came into his plane space, if the other space penetrated
the plane edge-wise or corner-wise, and could describe all that would
come in as it turned about in any way.

He would have six models. Let us consider two of them--the Black and the
White squares. We can observe them on the cube. Every colour on the one
is different from every colour on the other. If we now ask what lies
between the Orange line and the Reddish line, we know it is a square,
for the Orange line moving in any direction gives a square. And, if the
six models were before the plane-being, he could easily select that
which showed what he wanted. For that which lies between Orange line and
Reddish line must be bounded by Orange and Reddish lines. He would
search among the six models lying beside each other on his plane, till
he found the Dark-blue square. It is evident that only one other square
differs in all its colours from the Black square, viz., the White
square. For it is entirely separate. The others meet it in one of their
lines. This total difference exists in all the pairs of opposite
surfaces on the cube.

Now, suppose the plane-being asked himself what would appear if the cube
turned round the Blue line. The cube would begin to pass through his
space. The Crimson line would disappear beneath the plane and the
Blue-green square would cut it, so that opposite to the Blue line in the
plane there would be a Blue-green line. The French-grey line and the
Dark-slate line would be cut in points, and from the Gold point to the
French-grey point would be a Dark-blue line; and opposite to it would be
a Light-yellow line, from the Buff point to the Dark-slate point. Thus
the figure in the plane world would be an oblong instead of a square,
and the interior of it would be of the same Light-buff colour as the
interior of the cube. It is assumed that the plane closes up round the
passing cube, as the surface of a liquid does round any object immersed.

[Illustration: Fig. 1.]

[Illustration: Fig. 2.]

[Illustration: Fig. 3.]

[Illustration: Fig. 4.]

[Illustration: Fig. 5.]

But, in order to apprehend what would take place when this twisting
round the Blue line began, the plane-being would have to set to work by
parts. He has no conception of what a solid would do in twisting, but he
knows what a plane does. Let him, then, instead of thinking of the
whole Black square, think only of the Orange line. The Dark-blue square
stands on it. As far as this square is concerned, twisting round the
Blue line is the same as twisting round the Gold point. Let him imagine
himself in that plane at right angles to his plane-world, which contains
the Dark-blue square. Let him keep his attention fixed on the line where
the two planes meet, viz., that which is at first marked by the Orange
line. We will call this line the line of his plane, for all that he
knows of his own plane is this line. Now, let the Dark-blue square turn
round the Gold point. The Orange line at once dips below the line of his
plane, and the Dark-blue square passes through it. Therefore, in his
plane he will see a Dark-blue line in place of the Orange one. And in
place of the Fawn point, only further off from the Gold point, will be a
French-grey point. The Diagrams (1), (2) show how the cube appears as it
is before and after the turning. G is the Gold, F the Fawn point. In (2)
G is unmoved, and the plane is cut by the French-grey line, Gr.

Instead of imagining a direction he did not know, the plane-being could
think of the Dark-blue square as lying in his plane. But in this case
the Black square would be out off his plane, and only the Orange line
would remain in it. Diagram (3) shows the Dark-blue square lying in his
plane, and Diagram (4) shows it turning round the Gold point. Here,
instead of thinking about his plane and also that at right angles to it,
he has only to think how the square turning round the Gold point will
cut the line, which runs left to right from G, viz., the dotted line.
The French-grey line is cut by the dotted line in a point. To find out
what would come in at other parts, he need only treat a number of the
plane sections of the cube perpendicular to the Black square in the
same manner as he had treated the Dark-blue square. Every such section
would turn round a point, as the whole cube turned round the Blue line.
Thus he would treat the cube as a number of squares by taking parallel
sections from the Dark-blue to the Light-yellow square, and he would
turn each of these round a corner of the same colour as the Blue line.
Combining these series of appearances, he would discover what came into
his plane as the cube turned round the Blue line. Thus, the problem of
the turning of the cube could be settled by the consideration of the
turnings of a number of squares.

As the cube turned, a number of different appearances would be presented
to the plane-being. The Black square would change into a Light-buff
oblong, with Dark-blue, Blue-green, Light-yellow, and Blue sides, and
would gradually elongate itself until it became as long as the diagonal
of the square side of the cube; and then the bounding line opposite to
the Blue line would change from Blue-green to Bright-blue, the other
lines remaining the same colour. If the cube then turned still further,
the Bright-blue line would become White, and the oblong would diminish
in length. It would in time become a Vermilion square, with a
Deep-yellow line opposite to the Blue line. It would then pass wholly
below the plane, and only the Blue line would remain.

If the turning were continued till half a revolution had been
accomplished, the Black square would come in again. But now it would
come up into the plane from underneath. It would appear as a Black
square exactly similar to the first; but the Orange line, instead of
running left to right from Gold point, would run right to left. The
square would be the same, only differently disposed with regard to the
Blue line. It would be the looking-glass image of the first square.
There would be a difference in respect of the lie of the particles of
which it was composed. If the plane-being could examine its thickness,
he would find that particles which, in the first case, lay above others,
now lay below them. But, if he were really a plane-being, he would have
no idea of thickness in his squares, and he would find them both quite
identical. Only the one would be to the other as if it had been pulled
through itself. In this phenomenon of symmetry he would apprehend the
difference of the lie of the line, which went in the, to him, unknown
direction of up-and-down.


CHAPTER II.

FURTHER APPEARANCES OF A CUBE TO A PLANE-BEING.

Before leaving the observation of the cube, it is well to look at it for
a moment as it would appear to a plane-being, in whose world there was
such a fact as attraction. To do this, let the cube rest on the table,
so that its Dark-blue face is perpendicular in front of us. Now, let a
sheet of paper be placed in contact with the Dark-blue square. Let up
and sideways be the two dimensions of the plane-being, and away the
unknown direction. Let the line where the paper meets the table,
represent the surface of his earth. Then, there is to him, as all that
he can apprehend of the cube, a Dark-blue square standing upright; and,
when we look over the edge of the paper, and regard merely the part in
contact with the paper, we see what the plane-being would see.

If the cube be turned round the up line, the Brown line, the Orange line
will pass to the near side of the paper, and the section made by the
cube in the paper will be an oblong. Such an oblong can be cut out; and
when the cube is fitted into it, it can be seen that it is bounded by a
Brown line and a Blue-green line opposite thereto, while the other
boundaries are Black and White lines. Next, if we take a section
half-way between the Black and White squares, we shall have a square
cutting the plane of the aforesaid paper in a single line. With regard
to this section, all we have to inquire is, What will take the place of
this line as the cube turns? Obviously, the line will elongate. From a
Dark-blue line it will change to a Light-buff line, the colour of the
inside of the section, and will terminate in a Blue-green point instead
of a French-grey. Again, it is obvious that, if the cube turns round the
Orange line, it will give rise to a series of oblongs, stretching
upwards. This turning can be continued till the cube is wholly on the
near side of the paper, and only the Orange line remains. And, when the
cube has made half a revolution, the Dark-blue square will return into
the plane; but it will run downwards instead of upwards as at first.
Thereafter, if the cube turn further, a series of oblongs will appear,
all running downwards from the Orange line. Hence, if all the
appearances produced by the revolution of the cube have to be shown, it
must be supposed to be raised some distance above the plane-being’s
earth, so that those appearances may be shown which occur when it is
turned round the Orange line downwards, as well as when it is turned
upwards. The unknown direction comes into the plane either upwards or
downwards, but there is no special connection between it and either of
these directions. If it come in upwards, the Brown line goes nearwards
or -Y; if it come in downwards, or -Z, the Brown line goes away, or Y.

Let us consider more closely the directions which the plane-being would
have. Firstly, he would have up-and-down, that is, away from his earth
and towards it on the plane of the paper, the surface of his earth being
the line where the paper meets the table. Then, if he moved along the
surface of his earth, there would only be a line for him to move in, the
line running right and left. But, being the direction of his movement,
he would say it ran forwards and backwards. Thus he would simply have
the words up and down, forwards and backwards, and the expressions right
and left would have no meaning for him. If he were to frame a notion of
a world in higher dimensions, he must invent new words for distinctions
not within his experience.

To repeat the observations already made, let the cube be held in front
of the observer, and suppose the Dark-blue square extended on every side
so as to form a plane. Then let this plane be considered as independent
of the Dark-blue square. Now, holding the Brown line between finger and
thumb, and touching its extremities, the Gold and Light-blue points,
turn the cube round the Brown line. The Dark-blue square will leave the
plane, the Orange line will tend towards the -Y direction, and the Blue
line will finally come into the plane pointing in the +X direction. If
we move the cube so that the line which leaves the plane runs +Y, then
the line which before ran +Y will come into the plane in the direction
opposite to that of the line which has left the plane. The Blue line,
which runs in the unknown direction can come into either of the two
known directions of the plane. It can take the place of the Orange line
by turning the cube round the Brown line, or the place of the Brown line
by turning it round the Orange line. If the plane-being made models to
represent these two appearances of the cube, he would have identically
the same line, the Blue line, running in one of his known directions in
the first model, and in the other of his known directions in the second.
In studying the cube he would find it best to turn it so that the line
of unknown direction ran in that direction in the positive sense. In
that case, it would come into the plane in the negative sense of the
known directions.

Starting with the cube in front of the observer, there are two ways in
which the Vermilion square can be brought into the imaginary plane, that
is the extension of the Dark-blue square. If the cube turn round the
Brown line so that the Orange line goes away, (_i.e._ +Y), the Vermilion
square comes in on the left of the Brown line. If it turn in the
opposite direction, the Vermilion square comes in on the right of the
Brown line. Thus, if we identify the plane-being with the Brown line,
the Vermilion square would appear either behind or before him. These two
appearances of the Vermilion square would seem identical, but they could
not be made to coincide by any movement in the plane. The diagram (Fig.
5.) shows the difference in them. It is obvious that no turn in the
plane could put one in the place of the other, part for part. Thus the
plane-being apprehends the reversal of the unknown direction by the
disposition of his figures. If a figure, which lay on one side of a
line, changed into an identical figure on the other side of it, he could
be sure that a line of the figure, which at first ran in the positive
unknown direction, now ran in the negative unknown direction.

We have dwelt at great length on the appearances, which a cube would
present to a plane-being, and it will be found that all the points which
would be likely to cause difficulty hereafter, have been explained in
this obvious case.

There is, however, one other way, open to a plane-being of studying a
cube, to which we must attend. This is, by steady motion. Let the cube
come into the imaginary plane, which is the extension of the Dark-blue
square, _i.e._ let it touch the piece of paper which is standing
vertical on the table. Then let it travel through this plane at right
angles to it at the rate of an inch a minute. The plane-being would
first perceive a Dark-blue square, that is, he would see the coloured
lines bounding that square, and enclosed therein would be what he would
call a Dark-blue solid. In the movement of the cube, however, this
Dark-blue square would not last for more than a flash of time. (The
edges and points on the models are made very large; in reality they must
be supposed very minute.) This Dark-blue square would be succeeded by
one of the colour of the cube’s interior, _i.e._ by a Light-buff square.
But this colour of the interior would not be visible to the plane-being.
He would go round the square on his plane, and would see the bounding
lines, _viz._ Vermilion, White, Blue-green, Black. And at the corners he
would see Deep-yellow, Bright-blue, Crimson, and Blue points. These
lines and points would really be those parts of the faces and lines of
the cube, which were on the point of passing through his plane. Now,
there would be one difference between the Dark-blue square and the
Light-buff with their respective boundaries. The first only lasted for a
flash; the second would last for a minute or all but a minute. Consider
the Vermilion square. It appears to the plane-being as a line. The Brown
line also appears to him as a line. But there is a difference between
them. The Brown line only lasts for a flash, whereas the Vermilion line
lasts for a minute. Hence, in this mode of presentation, we may say that
for a plane-being a lasting line is the mode of apprehending a plane,
and a lasting plane (which is a plane-being’s solid) is the mode of
apprehending our solids. In the same way, the Blue line, as it passes
through his plane, gives rise to a point. This point lasts for a minute,
whereas the Gold point only lasted for a flash.


CHAPTER III.

FOUR-SPACE. GENESIS OF A TESSARACT. ITS REPRESENTATION IN THREE-SPACE.

Hitherto we have only looked at Model 1. This, with the next seven,
represent what we can observe of the simplest body in Higher Space. A
few words will explain their construction. A point by its motion traces
a line. A line by its motion traces either a longer line or an area; if
it moves at right angles to its own direction, it traces a rectangle.
For the sake of simplicity, we will suppose all movements to be an inch
in length and at right angles to each other. Thus, a point moving traces
a line an inch long; a line moving traces a square inch; a square moving
traces a cubic inch. In these cases each of these movements produces
something intrinsically different from what we had before. A square is
not a longer line, nor a cube a larger square. When the cube moves, we
are unable to see any new direction in which it can move, and are
compelled to make it move in a direction which has previously been used.
Let us suppose there is an unknown direction at right angles to all our
known directions, just as a third direction would be unknown to a being
confined to the surface of the table. And let the cube move in this
unknown direction for an inch. We call the figure it traces a Tessaract.
The models are representations of the appearances a Tessaract would
present to us if shown in various ways. Consider for a moment what
happens to a square when moved to form a cube. Each of its lines, moved
in the new direction, traces a square; the square itself traces a new
figure, a cube, which ends in another square. Now, our cube, moved in a
new direction, will trace a tessaract, whereof the cube itself is the
beginning, and another cube the end. These two cubes are to the
tessaract as the Black square and White square are to the cube. A
plane-being could not see both those squares at once, but he could make
models of them and let them both rest in his plane at once. So also we
can make models of the beginning and end of the tessaract. Model 1 is
the cube, which is its beginning; Model 2 is the cube which is its end.
It will be noticed that there are no two colours alike in the two
models. The Silver point corresponds to the Gold point, that is, the
Silver point is the termination of the line traced by the Gold point
moving in the new direction. The sides correspond in the following
manner:--

SIDES.

  _Model 1._                     _Model 2._
  Black         corresponds to  Bright-green
  White            „         „  Light-grey
  Vermilion        „         „  Indian-red
  Blue-green       „         „  Yellow-ochre
  Dark-blue        „         „  Burnt-sienna
  Light-yellow     „         „  Dun

The two cubes should be looked at and compared long enough to ensure
that the corresponding sides can be found quickly. Then there are the
following correspondencies in points and lines.

POINTS.

  _Model 1._                     _Model 2._
  Gold         corresponds to   Silver
  Fawn            „         „   Turquoise
  Terra-cotta     „         „   Earthen
  Buff            „         „   Blue tint
  Light-blue      „         „   Quaker-green
  Dull-purple     „         „   Peacock-blue
  Deep-blue       „         „   Orange-vermilion
  Red             „         „   Purple

LINES.

  _Model 1._                     _Model 2._
  Orange       corresponds to   Leaf-green
  Crimson         „       „     Dull-green
  Green-grey      „       „     Dark-purple
  Blue            „       „     Purple-brown
  Brown           „       „     Dull-blue
  French-grey     „       „     Dark-pink
  Dark-slate      „       „     Pale-pink
  Green           „       „     Indigo
  Reddish         „       „     Brown-green
  Bright-blue     „       „     Dark-green
  Leaden          „       „     Pale-yellow
  Deep-yellow     „       „     Dark

The colour of the cube itself is invisible, as it is covered by its
boundaries. We suppose it to be Sage-green.

These two cubes are just as disconnected when looked at by us as the
black and white squares would be to a plane-being if placed side by side
on his plane. He cannot see the squares in their right position with
regard to each other, nor can we see the cubes in theirs.

Let us now consider the vermilion side of Model 1. If it move in the X
direction, it traces the cube of Model 1. Its Gold point travels along
the Orange line, and itself, after tracing the cube, ends in the
Blue-green square. But if it moves in the new direction, it will also
trace a cube, for the new direction is at right angles to the up and
away directions, in which the Brown and Blue lines run. Let this square,
then, move in the unknown direction, and trace a cube. This cube we
cannot see, because the unknown direction runs out of our space at once,
just as the up direction runs out of the plane of the table. But a
plane-being could see the square, which the Blue line traces when moved
upwards, by the cube being turned round the Blue line, the Orange line
going upwards; then the Brown line comes into the plane of the table in
the -X direction. So also with our cube. As treated above, it runs from
the Vermilion square out of our space. But if the tessaract were turned
so that the line which runs from the Gold point in the unknown direction
lay in our space, and the Orange line lay in the unknown direction, we
could then see the cube which is formed by the movement of the Vermilion
square in the new direction.

Take Model 5. There is on it a Vermilion square. Place this so that it
touches the Vermilion square on Model 1. All the marks of the two
squares are identical. This Cube 5, is the one traced by the Vermilion
square moving in the unknown direction. In Model 5, the whole figure,
the tessaract, produced by the movement of the cube in the unknown
direction, is supposed to be so turned that the Orange line passes into
the unknown direction, and that the line which went in the unknown
direction, runs opposite to the old direction of the Orange line.
Looking at this new cube, we see that there is a Stone line running to
the left from the Gold point. This line is that which the Gold point
traces when moving in the unknown direction.

It is obvious that, if the Tessaract turns so as to show us the side, of
which Cube 5 is a model, then Cube 1 will no longer be visible. The
Orange line will run in the unknown or fourth direction, and be out of
our sight, together with the whole cube which the Vermilion square
generates, when the Gold point moves along the Orange line. Hence, if we
consider these models as real portions of the tessaract, we must not
have more than one before us at once. When we look at one, the others
must necessarily be beyond our sight and touch. But we may consider them
simply as models, and, as such, we may let them lie alongside of each
other. In this case, we must remember that their real relationships are
not those in which we see them.

We now enumerate the sides of the new Cube 5, so that, when we refer to
it, any colour may be recognised by name.

The square Vermilion traces a Pale-green cube, and ends in an Indian-red
square.

(The colour Pale-green of this cube is not seen, as it is entirely
surrounded by squares and lines of colour.)

Each Line traces a Square and ends in a Line.

  The Blue        line}      {Light-brown square} and{Purple-brown line
   „  Brown        „  }traces{Yellow        „   }ends{Dull-blue      „
   „  Deep-yellow  „  }   a  {Light-red     „   } in {Dark           „
   „  Green        „  }      {Deep-crimson  „   }  a {Indigo         „.

Each Point traces a Line and ends in a Point.

  The Gold       point}      {Stone       line} and{Silver       point
   „  Buff         „  }traces{Light-green   „ }ends{Blue-tint      „
   „  Light-blue   „  }   a  {Rich-red      „ } in {Quaker-green   „
   „  Red          „  }      {Emerald       „ }  a {Purple         „.

It will be noticed that besides the Vermilion square of this cube
another square of it has been seen before. A moment’s comparison with
the experience of a plane-being will make this more clear. If a
plane-being has before him models of the Black and White squares of the
Cube, he sees that all the colours of the one are different from all the
colours of the other. Next, if he looks at a model of the Vermilion
square, he sees that it starts from the Blue line and ends in a line of
the White square, the Deep-yellow line. In this square he has two lines
which he had before, the Blue line with Gold and Buff points, the
Deep-yellow line with Light-blue and Red points. To him the Black and
White squares are his Models 1 and 2, and the Vermilion square is to him
as our Model 5 is to us. The left-hand square of Model 5 is Indian-red,
and is identical with that of the same colour on the left-hand side of
Model 2. In fact, Model 5 shows us what lies between the Vermilion face
of 1, and the Indian-red face of 2.

From the Gold point we suppose four perfectly independent lines to
spring forth, each of them at right angles to all the others. In our
space there is only room for three lines mutually at right angles. It
will be found, if we try to introduce a fourth at right angles to each
of three, that we fail; hence, of these four lines one must go out of
the space we know. The colours of these four lines are Brown, Orange,
Blue, Stone. In Model 1 are shown the Brown, Orange, and Blue. In Model
5 are shown the Brown, Blue, and Stone. These lines might have had any
directions at first, but we chose to begin with the Brown line going up,
or Z, the Orange going X, the Blue going Y, and the Stone line going in
the unknown direction, which we will call W.

Consider for a moment the Stone and the Orange lines. They can be seen
together on Model 7 by looking at the lower face of it. They are at
right angles to each other, and if the Orange line be turned to take the
place of the Stone line, the latter will run into the negative part of
the direction previously occupied by the former. This is the reason that
the Models 3, 5, and 7 are made with the Stone line always running in
the reverse direction of that line of Model 1, which is wanting in each
respectively. It will now be easy to find out Models 3 and 7. All that
has to be done is, to discover what faces they have in common with 1 and
2, and these faces will show from which planes of 1 they are generated
by motion in the unknown direction.

Take Model 7. On one side of it there is a Dark-blue square, which is
identical with the Dark-blue square of Model 1. Placing it so that it
coincides with 1 by this square line for line, we see that the square
nearest to us is Burnt-sienna, the same as the near square on Model 2.
Hence this cube is a model of what the Dark-blue square traces on moving
in the unknown direction. Here the unknown direction coincides with the
negative away direction. In fact, to see this cube, we have been obliged
to suppose the Blue line turned into the unknown direction, for we
cannot look at more than three of these rectangular lines at once in our
space, and in this Model 7 we have the Brown, Orange, and Stone lines.
The faces, lines, and points of Cube 7 can be identified by the
following list.

The Dark-blue square traces a Dark-stone cube (whose interior is
rendered invisible by the bounding squares), and ends in a Burnt-sienna
square.

Each Line traces a Square and ends in a Line.

  The Orange      line}      {Azure        square} and{Leaf-green  line
   „  Brown         „ }traces{Yellow          „  }ends{Dull-blue    „
   „  French-grey   „ }  an  {Yellow-green    „  } in {Dark-pink    „
   „  Reddish       „ }      {Ochre           „  }  a {Brown-green  „.

Each Point traces a Line and ends in a Point.

  The Gold       point }      {Stone      line } and{Silver       point
   „ Fawn          „   }traces{Smoke        „  }ends{Turquoise      „
   „ Light-blue    „   }   a  {Rich-red     „  } in {Quaker-green   „
   „ Dull-purple   „   }      {Green-blue   „  }  a {Peacock-blue   „.

If we now take Model 3, we see that it has a Black square uppermost, and
has Blue and Orange lines. Hence, it evidently proceeds from the Black
square in Model 1; and it has in it Blue and Orange lines, which proceed
from the Gold point. But besides these, it has running downwards a Stone
line. The line wanting is the Brown line, and, as in the other cases,
when one of the three lines of Model 1 turns out into the unknown
direction, the Stone line turns into the direction opposite to that from
which the line has turned. Take this Model 3 and place it underneath
Model 1, raising the latter so that the Black squares on the two
coincide line for line. Then we see what would come into our view if the
Brown line were to turn into the unknown direction, and the Stone line
come into our space downwards. Looking at this cube, we see that the
following parts of the tessaract have been generated.

The Black square traces a Brick-red cube (invisible because covered by
its own sides and edges), and ends in a Bright-green square.

Each Line traces a Square and ends in a Line.

  The Orange    line}      {Azure       square } and{Leaf-green   line
   „ Crimson      „ }traces{Rose           „   }ends{Dull-green     „
   „ Green-grey   „ }  an  {Sea-blue       „   } in {Dark-purple    „
   „ Blue         „ }      {Light-brown    „   }  a {Purple-brown   „.

Each Point traces a Line and ends in a Point.

  The Gold       point}      {Stone       line} and{Silver    point
   „ Fawn          „  }traces{Smoke         „ }ends{Turquoise   „
   „ Terra-cotta   „  }   a  {Magenta       „ } in {Earthen     „
   „ Buff          „  }      {Light-green   „ }  a {Blue-tint   „.

This completes the enumeration of the regions of Cube 3. It may seem a
little unnatural that it should come in downwards; but it must be
remembered that the new fourth direction has no more relation to
up-and-down than to right-and-left or to near-and-far.

And if, instead of thinking of a plane-being as living on the surface of
a table, we suppose his world to be the surface of the sheet of paper
touching the Dark-blue square of Cube 1, then we see that a turn round
the Orange line, which makes the Brown line go into the plane-being’s
unknown direction, brings the Blue line into his downwards direction.

There still remain to be described Models 4, 6, and 8. It will be shown
that Model 4 is to Model 3 what Model 2 is to Model 1. That is, if, when
3 is in our space, it be moved so as to trace a tessaract, 4 will be
the opposite cube in which the tessaract ends. There is no colour common
to 3 and 4. Similarly, 6 is the opposite boundary of the tessaract
generated by 5, and 8 of that by 7.

A little closer consideration will reveal several points. Looking at
Cube 5, we see proceeding from the Gold point a Brown, a Blue, and a
Stone line. The Orange line is wanting; therefore, it goes in the
unknown direction. If we want to discover what exists in the unknown
direction from Cube 5, we can get help from Cube 1. For, since the
Orange line lies in the unknown direction from Cube 5, the Gold point
will, if moved along the Orange line, pass in the unknown direction. So
also, the Vermilion square, if moved along in the direction of the
Orange line, will proceed in the unknown direction. Looking at Cube 1 we
see that the Vermilion square thus moved ends in a Blue-green square.
Then, looking at Model 6, on it, corresponding to the Vermilion square
on Cube 5, is a Blue-green square.

Cube 6 thus shows what exists an inch beyond 5 in the unknown direction.
Between the right-hand face on 5 and the right-hand face on 6 lies a
cube, the one which is shown in Model 1. Model 1 is traced by the
Vermilion square moving an inch along the direction of the Orange line.
In Model 5, the Orange line goes in the unknown direction; and looking
at Model 6 we see what we should get at the end of a movement of one
inch in that direction. We have still to enumerate the colours of Cubes
4, 6, and 8, and we do so in the following list. In the first column is
designated the part of the cube; in the columns under 4, 6, 8, come the
colours which 4, 6, 8, respectively have in the parts designated in the
corresponding line in the first column.

Cube itself:--

      4                6              8
  Chocolate        Oak-yellow       Salmon

Squares:--

  Lower face       Light-grey       Rose             Sea-blue
  Upper            White            Deep-brown       Deep-green
  Left-hand        Light-red        Yellow-ochre     Deep-crimson
  Right-hand       Deep-brown       Blue-green       Dark-grey
  Near             Ochre            Yellow-green     Dun
  Far              Deep-green       Dark-grey        Light-yellow

Lines:--

On ground, going round the square from left to right:--

         4              6                  8
  1. Brown-green      Smoke            Dark-purple
  2. Dark-green       Crimson          Magenta
  3. Pale-yellow      Magenta          Green-grey
  4. Dark             Dull-green       Light-green

Vertical, going round the sides from left to right:--

  1. Rich-red         Dark-pink        Indigo
  2. Green-blue       French-grey      Pale-pink
  3. Sea-green        Dark-slate       Dark-slate
  4. Emerald          Pale-pink        Green

Round upper face in same order:--

  1. Reddish          Green-blue       Pale-yellow
  2. Bright-blue      Bright-blue      Sea-green
  3. Leaden           Sea-green        Leaden
  4. Deep-yellow      Dark-green       Emerald

Points:--

On lower face, going from left to right:--

  1. Quaker-green     Turquoise        Blue-tint
  2. Peacock-blue     Fawn             Earthen
  3. Orange-vermilion Terra-cotta      Terra-cotta
  4. Purple           Earthen          Buff

On upper face:--

  1. Light-blue       Peacock-blue     Purple
  2. Dull-purple      Dull-purple      Orange-vermilion
  3. Deep-blue        Deep-blue        Deep-blue
  4. Red              Orange-vermilion Red

If any one of these cubes be taken at random, it is easy enough to find
out to what part of the Tessaract it belongs. In all of them, except 2,
there will be one face, which is a copy of a face on 1; this face is, in
fact, identical with the face on 1 which it resembles. And the model
shows what lies in the unknown direction from that face. This unknown
direction is turned into our space, so that we can see and touch the
result of moving a square in it. And we have sacrificed one of the three
original directions in order to do this. It will be found that the line,
which in 1 goes in the 4th direction, in the other models always runs in
a negative direction.

Let us take Model 8, for instance. Searching it for a face we know, we
come to a Light-yellow face away from us. We place this face parallel
with the Light-yellow face on Cube 1, and we see that it has a Green
line going up, and a Green-grey line going to the right from the Buff
point. In these respects it is identical with the Light-yellow face on
Cube 1. But instead of a Blue line coming towards us from the Buff
point, there is a Light-green line. This Light-green line, then, is that
which proceeds in the unknown direction from the Buff point. The line is
turned towards us in this Model 8 in the negative Y direction; and
looking at the model, we see exactly what is formed when in the motion
of the whole cube in the unknown direction, the Light-yellow face is
moved an inch in that direction. It traces out a Salmon cube (_v._ Table
on p. 127), and it has Sea-blue and Deep-green sides below and above,
and Deep-crimson and Dark-grey sides left and right, and Dun and
Light-yellow sides near and far. If we want to verify the correctness of
any of these details, we must turn to Models 1 and 2. What lies an inch
from the Light-yellow square in the unknown direction? Model 2 tells
us, a Dun square. Now, looking at 8, we see that towards us lies a Dun
square. This is what lies an inch in the unknown direction from the
Light-yellow square. It is here turned to face us, and we can see what
lies between it and the Light-yellow square.


CHAPTER IV.

TESSARACT MOVING THROUGH THREE-SPACE. MODELS OF THE SECTIONS.

In order to obtain a clear conception of the higher solid, a certain
amount of familiarity with the facts shown in these models is necessary.
But the best way of obtaining a systematic knowledge is shown hereafter.
What these models enable us to do, is to take a general review of the
subject. In all of them we see simply the boundaries of the tessaract in
our space; we can no more see or touch the tessaract’s solidity than a
plane-being can touch the cube’s solidity.

There remain the four models 9, 10, 11, 12. Model 9 represents what lies
between 1 and 2. If 1 be moved an inch in the unknown direction, it
traces out the tessaract and ends in 2. But, obviously, between 1 and 2
there must be an infinite number of exactly similar solid sections;
these are all like Model 9.

Take the case of a plane-being on the table. He sees the Black
square,--that is, he sees the lines round it,--and he knows that, if it
moves an inch in some mysterious direction, it traces a new kind of
figure, the opposite boundary whereof is the White square. If, then, he
has models of the White and Black squares, he has before him the end and
beginning of our cube. But between these squares are any number of
others, the plane sections of the cube. We can see what they are. The
interior of each is a Light-buff (the colour of the substance of the
cube), the sides are of the colours of the vertical faces of the cube,
and the points of the colours of the vertical lines of the cube, viz.,
Dark-blue, Blue-green, Light-yellow, Vermilion lines, and Brown,
French-grey, Dark-slate, Green points. Thus, the square, in moving in
the unknown direction, traces out a succession of squares, the
assemblage of which makes the cube in layers. So also the cube, moving
in the unknown direction, will at any point of its motion, still be a
cube; and the assemblage of cubes thus placed constitutes the tessaract
in layers. We suppose the cube to change its colour directly it begins
to move. Its colour between 1 and 2 we can easily determine by finding
what colours its different parts assume, as they move in the unknown
direction. The Gold point immediately begins to trace a Stone-line. We
will look at Cube 5 to see what the Vermilion face becomes; we know the
interior of that cube is Pale-green (_v._ Table, p. 122). Hence, as it
moves in the unknown direction, the Vermilion square forms in its course
a series of Pale-green squares. The Brown line gives rise to a Yellow
square; hence, at every point of its course in the fourth direction, it
is a Yellow line, until, on taking its final position, it becomes a
Dull-blue line. Looking at Cube 5, we see that the Deep yellow line
becomes a Light-red line, the Green line a Deep Crimson one, the Gold
point a Stone one, the Light-blue point a Rich-red one, the Red point an
Emerald one, and the Buff point a Light-green one. Now, take the Model
9. Looking at the left side of it, we see exactly that into which the
Vermilion square is transformed, as it moves in the unknown direction.
The left side is an exact copy of a section of Cube 5, parallel to the
Vermilion face.

But we have only accounted for one side of our Model 9. There are five
other sides. Take the near side corresponding to the Dark-blue square on
Cube 1. When the Dark-blue square moves, it traces a Dark-stone cube, of
which we have a copy in Cube 7. Looking at 7 (_v._ Table, p. 124), we
see that, as soon as the Dark-blue square begins to move, it becomes of
a Dark-stone colour, and has Yellow, Ochre, Yellow-green, and Azure
sides, and Stone, Rich-red, Green-blue, Smoke lines running in the
unknown direction from it. Now, the side of Model 9, which faces us, has
these colours the squares being seen as lines, and the lines as points.
Hence Model 9 is a copy of what the cube becomes, so far as the
Vermilion and Dark-blue sides are concerned, when, moving in the unknown
direction, it traces the tessaract.

We will now look at the lower square of our model. It is a Brick-red
square, with Azure, Rose, Sea-blue, and Light-brown lines, and with
Stone, Smoke, Magenta, and Light-green points. This, then, is what the
Black square should change into, as it moves in the unknown direction.
Let us look at Model 3. Here the Stone line, which is the line in the
unknown direction, runs downwards. It is turned into the downwards
direction, so that the cube traced by the Black square may be in our
space. The colour of this cube is Brick-red; the Orange line has traced
an Azure, the Blue line a Light-brown, the Crimson line a Rose, and the
Green-grey line a Sea-blue square. Hence, the lower square of Model 9
shows what the Black square becomes, as it traces the tessaract; or, in
other words, the section of Model 3 between the Black and Bright-green
squares exactly corresponds to the lower face of Model 9.

Therefore, it appears that Model 9 is a model of a section of the
tessaract, that it is to the tessaract what a square between the Black
and White squares is to the cube.

To prove the other sides correct, we have to see what the White,
Blue-green, and Light-yellow squares of Cube 1 become, as the cube moves
in the unknown direction. This can be effected by means of the Models 4,
6, 8. Each cube can be used as an index for showing the changes through
which any side of the first model passes, as it moves in the unknown
direction till it becomes Cube 2. Thus, what becomes of the White
square? Look at Cube 4. From the Light-blue corner of its White square
runs downwards the Rich-red line in the unknown direction. If we take a
parallel section below the White square, we have a square bounded by
Ochre, Deep-brown, Deep-green, and Light-red lines; and by Rich-red,
Green-blue, Sea-green, and Emerald points. The colour of the cube is
Chocolate, and therefore its section is Chocolate. This description is
exactly true of the upper surface of Model 9.

There still remain two sides, those corresponding to the Light-yellow
and Blue-green of Cube 1. What the Blue-green square becomes midway
between Cubes 1 and 2 can be seen on Model 6. The colour of the
last-named is Oak-yellow, and a section parallel to its Blue-green side
is surrounded by Yellow-green, Deep-brown, Dark-grey and Rose lines and
by Green-blue, Smoke, Magenta, and Sea-green points. This is exactly
similar to the right side of Model 9. Lastly, that which becomes of the
Light-yellow side can be seen on Model 8. The section of the cube is a
Salmon square bounded by Deep-crimson, Deep-green, Dark-grey and
Sea-blue lines and by Emerald, Sea-green, Magenta, and Light-green
points.

Thus the models can be used to answer any question about sections. For
we have simply to take, instead of the whole cube, a plane, and the
relation of the whole tessaract to that plane can be told by looking at
the model, which, starting with that plane, stretches from it in the
unknown direction.

We have not as yet settled the colour of the interior of Model 9. It is
that part of the tessaract which is traced out by the interior of Cube
1. The unknown direction starts equally and simultaneously from every
point of every part of Cube 1, just as the up direction starts equally
and simultaneously from every point of a square. Let us suppose that the
cube, which is Light-buff, changes to a Wood-colour directly it begins
to trace the tessaract. Then the internal part of the section between 1
and 2 will be a Wood-colour. The sides of the Model 9 are of the
greatest importance. They are the colour of the six cubes, 3, 4, 5, 6,
7, and 8. The colours of 1 and 2 are wanting, viz. Light-buff and
Sage-green. Thus the section between 1 and 2 can be found by its wanting
the colours of the Cubes 1 and 2.

Looking at Models 10, 11, and 12 in a similar manner, the reader will
find they represent the sections between Cubes 3 and 4, Cubes 5 and 6,
and Cubes 7 and 8 respectively.


CHAPTER V.

REPRESENTATION OF THREE-SPACE BY NAMES, AND IN A PLANE.

We may now ask ourselves the best way of passing on to a clear
comprehension of the facts of higher space. Something can be effected by
looking at these models; but it is improbable that more than a slight
sense of analogy will be obtained thus. Indeed, we have been trusting
hitherto to a method which has something vicious about it--we have been
trusting to our sense of what _must_ be. The plan adopted, as the
serious effort towards the comprehension of this subject, is to learn a
small portion of higher space. If any reader feel a difficulty in the
foregoing chapters, or if the subject is to be taught to young minds, it
is far better to abandon all attempt to see what higher space _must_ be,
and to learn what it _is_ from the following chapters.


NAMING A PIECE OF SPACE.

The diagram (Fig. 6) represents a block of 27 cubes, which form Set 1 of
the 81 cubes. The cubes are coloured, and it will be seen that the
colours are arranged after the pattern of Model 1 of previous chapters,
which will serve as a key to the block. In the diagram, G. denotes Gold,
O. Orange, F. Fawn, Br. Brown, and so on. We will give names to the
cubes of this block. They should not be learnt, but kept for reference.
We will write these names in three sets, the lowest consisting of the
cubes which touch the table, the next of those immediately above them,
and the third of those at the top. Thus the Gold cube is called Corvus,
the Orange, Cuspis, the Fawn, Nugæ, and the central one below, Syce. The
corresponding colours of the following set can easily be traced.

  Olus        Semita       Lama
  Via         Mel          Iter
  Ilex        Callis       Sors

  Bucina      Murex        Daps
  Alvus       Mala         Proes
  Arctos      Mœna         Far

  Cista       Cadus        Crus
  Dos         Syce         Bolus
  Corvus      Cuspis       Nugæ

Thus the central or Light-buff cube is called Mala; the middle one of
the lower face is Syce; of the upper face Mel; of the right face, Proes;
of the left, Alvus; of the front, Mœna (the Dark-blue square of Model
1); and of the back, Murex (the Light-yellow square).

Now, if Model 1 be taken, and considered as representing a block of 64
cubes, the Gold corner as one cube, the Orange line as two cubes, the
Fawn point as one cube, the Dark-blue square as four cubes, the
Light-buff interior as eight cubes, and so on, it will correspond to the
diagram (Fig. 7). This block differs from the last in the number of
cubes, but the arrangement of the colours is the same. The following
table gives the names which we will use for these cubes. There are no
new names; they are only applied more than once to all cubes of the same
colour.

        {Olus      Semita      Semita      Lama
  Fourth{Via       Mel         Mel         Iter
  Floor.{Via       Mel         Mel         Iter
        {Ilex      Callis      Callis      Sors

        {Bucina    Murex       Murex       Daps
  Third {Alvus     Mala        Mala        Proes
  Floor.{Alvus     Mala        Mala        Proes
        {Arctos    Mœna        Mœna        Far

        {Bucina    Murex       Murex       Daps
  Second{Alvus     Mala        Mala        Proes
  Floor.{Alvus     Mala        Mala        Proes
        {Arctos    Mœna        Mœna        Far

        {Cista     Cadus       Cadus       Crus
  First {Dos       Syce        Syce        Bolus
  Floor.{Dos       Syce        Syce        Bolus
        {Corvus    Cuspis      Cuspis      Nugæ

[Illustration: Fig. 6.]

[Illustration: Fig. 7.]

[Illustration: Fig. 8.]

If we now consider Model 1 to represent a block, five cubes each way,
built up of inch cubes, and colour it in the same way, that is, with
similar colours for the corner-cubes, edge-cubes, face-cubes, and
interior-cubes, we obtain what is represented in the diagram (Fig. 8).
Here we have nine Dark-blue cubes called Mœna; that is, Mœna denotes the
nine Dark-blue cubes, forming a layer on the front of the cube, and
filling up the whole front except the edges and points. Cuspis denotes
three Orange, Dos three Blue, and Arctos three Brown cubes.

Now, the block of cubes can be similarly increased to any size we
please. The corners will always consist of single cubes; that is, Corvus
will remain a single cubic inch, even though the block be a hundred
inches each way. Cuspis, in that case, will be 98 inches long, and
consist of a row of 98 cubes; Arctos, also, will be a long thin line of
cubes standing up. Mœna will be a thin layer of cubes almost covering
the whole front of the block; the number of them will be 98 times 98.
Syce will be a similar square layer of cubes on the ground, so also
Mel, Alvus, Proes, and Murex in their respective places. Mala, the
interior of the cube, will consist of 98 times 98 times 98 inch cubes.

[Illustration: Fig. 9]

Now, if we continued in this manner till we had a very large block of
thousands of cubes in each side Corvus would, in comparison to the whole
block, be a minute point of a cubic shape, and Cuspis would be a mere
line of minute cubes, which would have length, but very small depth or
height. Next, if we suppose this much sub-divided block to be reduced in
size till it becomes one measuring an inch each way, the cubes of which
it consists must each of them become extremely minute, and the corner
cubes and line cubes would be scarcely discernible. But the cubes on the
faces would be just as visible as before. For instance, the cubes
composing Mœna would stretch out on the face of the cube so as to fill
it up. They would form a layer of extreme thinness, but would cover the
face of the cube (all of it except the minute lines and points). Thus we
may use the words Corvus and Nugæ, etc., to denote the corner-points of
the cube, the words Mœna, Syce, Mel, Alvus, Proes, Murex, to denote the
faces. It must be remembered that these faces have a thickness, but it
is extremely minute compared with the cube. Mala would denote all the
cubes of the interior except those, which compose the faces, edges, and
points. Thus, Mala would practically mean the whole cube except the
colouring on it. And it is in this sense that these words will be used.
In the models, the Gold point is intended to be a Corvus, only it is
made large to be visible; so too the Orange line is meant for Cuspis,
but magnified for the same reason. Finally, the 27 names of cubes, with
which we began, come to be the names of the points, lines, and faces of
a cube, as shown in the diagram (Fig. 9). With these names it is easy
to express what a plane-being would see of any cube. Let us suppose that
Mœna is only of the thickness of his matter. We suppose his matter to be
composed of particles, which slip about on his plane, and are so thin
that he cannot by any means discern any thickness in them. So he has no
idea of thickness. But we know that his matter must have some thickness,
and we suppose Mœna to be of that degree of thickness. If the cube be
placed so that Mœna is in his plane, Corvus, Cuspis, Nugæ, Far, Sors,
Callis, Ilex and Arctos will just come into his apprehension; they will
be like bits of his matter, while all that is beyond them in the
direction he does not know, will be hidden from him. Thus a plane-being
can only perceive the Mœna or Syce or some one other face of a cube;
that is, he would take the Mœna of a cube to be a solid in his
plane-space, and he would see the lines Cuspis, Far, Callis, Arctos. To
him they would bound it. The points Corvus, Nugæ, Sors, and Ilex, he
would not see, for they are only as long as the thickness of his matter,
and that is so slight as to be indiscernible to him.

We must now go with great care through the exact processes by which a
plane-being would study a cube. For this purpose we use square slabs
which have a certain thickness, but are supposed to be as thin as a
plane-being’s matter. Now, let us take the first set of 81 cubes again,
and build them from 1 to 27. We must realize clearly that two kinds of
blocks can be built. It may be built of 27 cubes, each similar to Model
1, in which case each cube has its regions coloured, but all the cubes
are alike. Or it may be built of 27 differently coloured cubes like Set
1, in which case each cube is coloured wholly with one colour in all its
regions. If the latter set be used, we can still use the names Mœna,
Alvus, etc. to denote the front, side, etc., of any one of the cubes,
whatever be its colour. When they are built up, place a piece of card
against the front to represent the plane on which the plane-being lives.
The front of each of the cubes in the front of the block touches the
plane. In previous chapters we have supposed Mœna to be a Blue square.
But we can apply the name to the front of a cube of any colour. Let us
say the Mœna of each front cube is in the plane; the Mœna of the Gold
cube is Gold, and so on. To represent this, take nine slabs of the same
colours as the cubes. Place a stiff piece of cardboard (or a book-cover)
slanting from you, and put the slabs on it. They can be supported on the
incline so as to prevent their slipping down away from you by a thin
book, or another sheet of cardboard, which stands for the surface of the
plane-being’s earth.

We will now give names to the cubes of Block 1 of the 81 Set. We call
each one Mala, to denote that it is a cube. They are written in the
following list in floors or layers, and are supposed to run backwards or
away from the reader. Thus, in the first layer, Frenum Mala is behind or
farther away than Urna Mala; in the second layer, Ostrum is in front,
Uncus behind it, and Ala behind Uncus.

  Third, or {Mars Mala         Merces Mala       Tyro Mala
  Top       {Spicula Mala      Mora Mala         Oliva Mala
  Floor.    {Comes Mala        Tibicen Mala      Vestis Mala

  Second, or{Ala Mala          Cortis Mala       Aer Mala
  Middle    {Uncus Mala        Pallor Mala       Tergum Mala
  Floor.    {Ostrum Mala       Bidens Mala       Scena Mala

  First, or {Sector Mala       Hama Mala         Remus Mala
  Bottom    {Frenum Mala       Plebs Mala        Sypho Mala
  Floor.    {Urna Mala         Moles Mala        Saltus Mala

These names should be learnt so that the different cubes in the block
can be referred to quite easily and immediately by name. They must be
learnt in every order, that is, in each of the three directions
backwards and forwards, _e.g._ Urna to Saltus, Urna to Sector, Urna to
Comes; and the same reversed, viz., Comes to Urna, Sector to Urna, etc.
Only by so learning them can the mind identify any one individually
without even a momentary reference to the others around it. It is well
to make it a rule not to proceed from one cube to a distant one without
naming the intermediate cubes. For, in Space we cannot pass from one
part to another without going through the intermediate portions. And, in
thinking of Space, it is well to accustom our minds to the same
limitations.

Urna Mala is supposed to be solid Gold an inch each way; so too all the
cubes are supposed to be entirely of the colour which they show on their
faces. Thus any section of Moles Mala will be Orange, of Plebs Mala
Black, and so on.

[Illustration: Fig. 10.]

Let us now draw a pair of lines on a piece of paper or cardboard like
those in the diagram (Fig. 10). In this diagram the top of the page is
supposed to rest on the table, and the bottom of the page to be raised
and brought near the eye, so that the plane of the diagram slopes
upwards to the reader. Let Z denote the upward direction, and X the
direction from left to right. Let us turn the Block of cubes with its
front upon this slope _i.e._ so that Urna fits upon the square marked
Urna. Moles will be to the right and Ostrum above Urna, _i.e._ nearer
the eye. We might leave the block as it stands and put the piece of
cardboard against it; in this case our plane-world would be vertical. It
is difficult to fix the cubes in this position on the plane, and
therefore more convenient if the cardboard be so inclined that they will
not slip off. But the upward direction must be identified with Z. Now,
taking the slabs, let us compose what a plane-being would see of the
Block. He would perceive just the front faces of the cubes of the Block,
as it comes into his plane; these front faces we may call the Moenas of
the cubes. Let each of the slabs represent the Moena of its
corresponding cube, the Gold slab of the Gold cube and so on. They are
thicker than they should be; but we must overlook this and suppose we
simply see the thickness as a line. We thus build a square of nine slabs
to represent the appearance to a plane-being of the front face of the
Block. The middle one, Bidens Moena, would be completely hidden from him
by the others on all its sides, and he would see the edges of the eight
outer squares. If the Block now begin to move through the plane, that
is, to cut through the piece of paper at right angles to it, it will not
for some time appear any different. For the sections of Urna are all
Gold like the front face Moena, so that the appearance of Urna at any
point in its passage will be a Gold square exactly like Urna Moena, seen
by the plane-being as a line. Thus, if the speed of the Block’s passage
be one inch a minute, the plane-being will see no change for a minute.
In other words, this set of slabs lasting one minute will represent what
he sees.

When the Block has passed one inch, a different set of cubes appears.
Remove the front layer of cubes. There will now be in contact with the
paper nine new cubes, whose names we write in the order in which we
should see them through a piece of glass standing upright in front of
the Block:

  Spicula Mala        Mora Mala        Oliva Mala
  Uncus Mala          Pallor Mala      Tergum Mala
  Frenum Mala         Plebs Mala       Sypho Mala

We pick out nine slabs to represent the Moenas of these cubes, and
placed in order they show what the plane-being sees of the second set
of cubes as they pass through. Similarly the third wall of the Block
will come into the plane, and looking at them similarly, as it were
through an upright piece of glass, we write their names:

  Mars Mala        Merces Mala      Tyro Mala
  Ala Mala         Cortis Mala      Aer Mala
  Sector Mala      Hama Mala        Remus Mala

Now, it is evident that these slabs stand at different times for
different parts of the cubes. We can imagine them to stand for the Moena
of each cube as it passes through. In that case, the first set of slabs,
which we put up, represents the Moenas of the front wall of cubes; the
next set, the Moenas of the second wall. Thus, if all the three sets of
slabs be together on the table, we have a representation of the sections
of the cube. For some purposes it would be better to have four sets of
slabs, the fourth set representing the Murex of the third wall; for the
three sets only show the front faces of the cubes, and therefore would
not indicate anything about the back faces of the Block. For instance,
if a line passed through the Block diagonally from the point Corvus
(Gold) to the point Lama (Deep-blue), it would be represented on the
slabs by a point at the bottom left-hand corner of the Gold slab, a
second point at the same corner of the Light-buff slab, and a third at
the same corner of the Deep-blue slab. Thus, we should have the points
mapped at which the line entered the fronts of the walls of cubes, but
not the point in Lama at which it would leave the Block.

Let the Diagrams 1, 2, 3 (Fig. 11), be the three sets of slabs. To see
the diagrams properly, the reader must set the top of the page on the
table, and look along the page from the bottom of it. The line in
question, which runs from the bottom left-hand near corner to the top
right-hand far corner of the Block will be represented in the three sets
of slabs by the points A, B, C. To complete the diagram of its course,
we need a fourth set of slabs for the Murex of the third wall; the same
object might be attained, if we had another Block of 27 cubes behind the
first Block and represented its front or Moenas by a set of slabs. For
the point, at which the line leaves the first Block is identical with
that at which it enters the second Block.

[Illustration: Fig. 11.]

If we suppose a sheet of glass to be the plane-world, the Diagrams 1, 2,
3 (Fig. 11), may be drawn more naturally to us as Diagrams α, β, γ (Fig.
12). Here α represents the Moenas of the first wall, β those of the
second, γ those of the third. But to get the plane-being’s view we must
look over the edge of the glass down the Z axis.

[Illustration: Fig. 12.]

Set 2 of slabs represent the Moenas of Wall 2. These Moenas are in
contact with the Murex of Wall 1. Thus Set 2 will show where the line
issues from Wall 1 as well as where it enters Wall 2.

The plane-being, therefore, could get an idea of the Block of cubes by
learning these slabs. He ought not to call the Gold slab Urna Mala, but
Urna Moena, and so on, because all that he learns are Moenas, merely the
thin faces of the cubes. By introducing the course of time, he can
represent the Block more nearly. For, if he supposes it to be passing an
inch a minute, he may give the name Urna Mala to the Gold slab enduring
for a minute.

But, when he has learnt the slabs in this position and sequence, he has
only a very partial view of the Block. Let the Block turn round the Z
axis, as Model 1 turns round the Brown line. A different set of cubes
comes into his plane, and now they come in on the Alvus faces.
(Alvus is here used to denote the left-hand faces of the cubes, and is
not supposed to be Vermilion; it is simply the thinnest slice on the
left hand of the cube and of the same colour as the cube.) To represent
this, the plane-being should employ a fresh set of slabs, for there is
nothing common to the Moena and Alvus faces except an edge. But, since
each cube is of the same colour throughout, the same slab may be used
for its different faces. Thus the Alvus of Urna Mala can be represented
by a Gold slab. Only it must never be forgotten that it is meant to be a
new slab, and is not identical with the same slab used for Moena.

[Illustration: Fig. 13.]

[Illustration: Fig. 14.]

Now, when the Block of cubes has turned round the Brown line into the
plane, it is clear that they will be on the side of the Z axis opposite
to that on which were the Moena slabs. The line, which ran Y, now runs
-X. Thus the slabs will occupy the second quadrant marked by the axes,
as shown in the diagram (Fig. 13). Each of these slabs we will name
Alvus. In this view, as before, the book is supposed to be tilted up
towards the reader, so that the Z axis runs from O to his eye. Then, if
the Block be passed at right angles through the plane, there will come
into view the two sets of slabs represented in the Diagrams (Fig. 13).
In copying this arrangement with the slabs, the cardboard on which they
are arranged must slant upwards to the eye, _i.e._, OZ must run up to
the eye, and the sides of the slabs seen are in Diagram 2 (Fig. 13), the
upper edges of Tibicen, Mora, Merces; in Diagram 3, the upper edges of
Vestis, Oliva, Tyro.

There is another view of the Block possible to a plane-being. If the
Block be turned round the X axis, the lower face comes into the vertical
plane. This corresponds to turning Model 1 round the Orange line. On
referring to the diagram (Fig. 14), we now see that the name of the
faces of the cubes coming into the plane is Syce. Here the plane-being
looks from the extremity of the Z axis and the squares, which he sees
run from him in the -Z direction. (As this turn of the Block brings its
Syce into the vertical plane so that it extends three inches below the
base line of its Moena, it is evident that the turn is only possible if
the Moena be originally at a height of at least three inches above the
plane-being’s earth line in the vertical plane.) Next, if the Block be
passed through the plane, the sections shown in the Diagrams 2 and 3
(Fig. 14) are brought into view.

Thus, there are three distinct ways of regarding the cubic Block, each
of them equally primary; and if the plane-being is to have a correct
idea of the Block, he must be equally familiar with each view. By means
of the slabs each aspect can be represented; but we must remember in
each of the three cases, that the slabs represent different parts of the
cube.

When we look at the cube Pallor Mala in space, we see that it touches
six other cubes by its six faces. But the plane-being could only arrive
at this fact by comparing different views. Taking the three Moena
sections of the Block, he can see that Pallor Mala Moena touches Plebs
Moena, Mora Moena, Uncus Moena, and Tergum Moena by lines. And it takes
the place of Bidens Moena, and is itself displaced by Cortis Moena as
the Block passes through the plane. Next, this same Pallor Mala can
appear to him as an Alvus. In this case, it touches Plebs Alvus, Mora
Alvus, Bidens Alvus, and Cortis Alvus by lines, takes the place of Uncus
Alvus, and is itself displaced by Tergum Alvus as the Block moves.
Similarly he can observe the relations, if the Syce of the Block be in
his plane.

Hence, this unknown body Pallor Mala appears to him now as one
plane-figure now as another, and comes before him in different
connections. Pallor Mala is that which satisfies all these relations.
Each of them he can in turn present to sense; but the total conception
of Pallor Mala itself can only, if at all, grow up in his mind. The way
for him to form this mental conception, is to go through all the
practical possibilities which Pallor Mala would afford him by its
various movements and turns. In our world these various relations are
found by the most simple observations; but a plane-being could only
acquire them by considerable labour. And if he determined to obtain a
knowledge of the physical existence of a higher world than his own, he
must pass through such discipline.

       *       *       *       *       *

[Illustration: Fig. 15.]

[Illustration: Fig. 16.]

We will see what change could be introduced into the shapes he builds by
the movements, which he does not know in his world. Let us build up this
shape with the cubes of the Block: Urna Mala, Moles Mala, Bidens Mala,
Tibicen Mala. To the plane-being this shape would be the slabs, Urna
Moena, Moles Moena, Bidens Moena, Tibicen Moena (Fig. 15). Now let the
Block be turned round the Z axis, so that it goes past the position, in
which the Alvus sides enter the vertical plane. Let it move until,
passing through the plane, the same Moena sides come in again. The mass
of the Block will now have cut through the plane and be on the near side
of it towards us; but the Moena faces only will be on the plane-being’s
side of it. The diagram (Fig. 16) shows what he will see, and it will
seem to him similar to the first shape (Fig. 15) in every respect except
its disposition with regard to the Z axis. It lies in the direction -X,
opposite to that of the first figure. However much he turn these two
figures about in the plane, he cannot make one occupy the place of the
other, part for part. Hence it appears that, if we turn the
plane-being’s figure about a line, it undergoes an operation which is to
him quite mysterious. He cannot by any turn in his plane produce the
change in the figure produced by us. A little observation will show that
a plane-being can only turn round a point. Turning round a line is a
process unknown to him. Therefore one of the elements in a plane-being’s
knowledge of a space higher than his own, will be the conception of a
kind of turning which will change his solid bodies into their own
images.


CHAPTER VI.

THE MEANS BY WHICH A PLANE-BEING WOULD ACQUIRE A CONCEPTION OF OUR
FIGURES.

Take the Block of twenty-seven Mala cubes, and build up the following
shape (Fig. 18):--

Urna Mala, Moles Mala, Plebs Mala, Pallor Mala, Mora Mala.

If this shape, passed through the vertical plane, the plane-being would
perceive:--

(1) The squares Urna Moena and Moles Moena.

(2) The three squares Plebs Moena, Pallor Moena, Mora Moena,

and then the whole figure would have passed through his plane.

If the whole Block were turned round the Z axis till the Alvus sides
entered, and the figure built up as it would be in that disposition of
the cubes, the plane-being would perceive during its passage through the
plane:--

(1) Urna Alvus;

(2) Moles Alvus, Plebs Alvus, Pallor Alvus, Mora Alvus, which would all
enter on the left side of the Z axis.

Again, if the Block were turned round the X axis, the Syce side would
enter, and the cubes appear in the following order:--

(1) Urna Syce, Moles Syce, Plebs Syce;

(2) Pallor Syce;

(3) Mora Syce.

[Illustration: Fig. 17.]

[Illustration: Fig. 18.]

A comparison of these three sets of appearances would give the
plane-being a full account of the figure. It is that which can produce
these various appearances.

Let us now suppose a glass plate placed in front of the Block in its
first position. On this plate let the axes X and Z be drawn. They divide
the surface into four parts, to which we give the following names (Fig.
17):--

Z X = that quarter defined by the positive Z and positive X axis.

Z [=X] = that quarter defined by the positive Z and negative X axis
(which is called “Z negative X”).

[=Z] [=X] = that quarter defined by the negative Z and negative X axis.

[=Z] X = that quarter defined by the negative Z and positive X axis.

The Block appears in these different quarters or quadrants, as it is
turned round the different axes. In Z X the Moenas appear, in Z [=X] the
Alvus faces, in [=Z] X the Syces. In each quadrant are drawn nine
squares, to receive the faces of the cubes when they enter. For
instance, in Z X we have the Moenas of:--

  Z
  |    Comes       Tibicen      Vestis
  |    Ostrum      Bidens       Scena
  |    Urna        Moles        Saltus
  +--------------------------------------X

  And in Z [=X] we have the Alvus of:--

                                      Z
       Mars        Spicula      Comes    |
       Ala         Uncus        Ostrum   |
       Sector      Frenum       Urna     |
  -X-------------------------------------+

And in the [=Z] X we have the Syces of:--

   +-----------------------------------X
   | Urna        Moles        Saltus
   | Frenum      Plebs        Sypho
   | Sector      Hama         Remus
  -Z

Now, if the shape taken at the beginning of this chapter be looked at
through the glass, and the distance of the second and third walls of the
shape behind the glass be considered of no account--that is, if they be
treated as close up to the glass--we get a plane outline, which occupies
the squares Urna Moena, Moles Moena, Bidens Moena, Tibicen Moena. This
outline is called a projection of the figure. To see it like a
plane-being, we should have to look down on it along the Z axis.

It is obvious that one projection does not give the shape. For instance,
the square Bidens Moena might be filled by either Pallor or Cortis. All
that a square in the room of Bidens Moena denotes, is that there is a
cube somewhere in the Y, or unknown, direction from Bidens Moena. This
view, just taken, we should call the front view in our space; we are
then looking at it along the negative Y axis.

When the same shape is turned round on the Z axis, so as to be projected
on the Z [=X] quadrant, we have the squares--Urna Alvus, Frenum Alvus,
Uncus Alvus, Spicula Alvus. When it is turned round the X axis, and
projected on [=Z] X, we have the squares, Urna Syce, Moles Syce, Plebs
Syce, and no more. This is what is ordinarily called the ground plan;
but we have set it in a different position from that in which it is
usually drawn.

[Illustration: Fig. 19.]

Now, the best method for a plane-being of familiarizing himself with
shapes in our space, would be to practise the realization of them from
their different projections in his plane. Thus, given the three
projections just mentioned, he should be able to construct the figure
from which they are derived. The projections (Fig. 19) are drawn below
the perspective pictures of the shape (Fig. 18). From the front, or
Moena view, he would conclude that the shape was Urna Mala, Moles Mala,
Bidens Mala, Tibicen Mala; or instead of these, or also in addition to
them, any of the cubes running in the Y direction from the plane. That
is, from the Moena projection he might infer the presence of all the
following cubes (the word Mala is omitted for brevity): Urna, Frenum,
Sector, Moles, Plebs, Hama, Bidens, Pallor, Cortis, Tibicen, Mora,
Merces.

Next, the Alvus view or projection might be given by the cubes (the word
Mala being again omitted): Urna, Moles, Saltus, Frenum, Plebs, Sypho,
Uncus, Pallor, Tergum, Spicula, Mora, Oliva. Lastly, looking at the
ground plan or Syce view, he would infer the possible presence of Urna,
Ostrum, Comes, Moles, Bidens, Tibicen, Plebs, Pallor, Mora.

Now, the shape in higher space, which is usually there, is that which is
common to all these three appearances. It can be determined, therefore,
by rejecting those cubes which are not present in all three lists of
cubes possible from the projections. And by this process the plane-being
could arrive at the enumeration of the cubes which belong to the shape
of which he had the projections. After a time, when he had experience of
the cubes (which, though invisible to him as wholes, he could see part
by part in turn entering his space), the projections would have more
meaning to him, and he might comprehend the shape they expressed
fragmentarily in his space. To practise the realization from
projections, we should proceed in this way. First, we should think of
the possibilities involved in the Moena view, and build them up in cubes
before us. Secondly, we should build up the cubes possible from the
Alvus view. Again, taking the shape at the beginning of the chapter, we
should find that the shape of the Alvus possibilities intersected that
of the Moena possibilities in Urna, Moles, Frenum, Plebs, Pallor, Mora;
or, in other words, these cubes are common to both. Thirdly, we should
build up the Syce possibilities, and, comparing their shape with those
of the Moena and Alvus projections, we should find Urna, Moles, Plebs,
Pallor, Mora, of the Syce view coinciding with the same cubes of the
other views, the only cube present in the intersection of the Moena and
Alvus possibilities, and not present in the Syce view, being Frenum.

The determination of the figure denoted by the three projections, may be
more easily effected by treating each projection as an indication of
what cubes are to be cut away. Taking the same shape as before, we have
in the Moena projection Urna, Moles, Bidens, Tibicen; and the
possibilities from them are Urna, Frenum, Sector, Moles, Plebs, Hama,
Bidens, Pallor, Cortis, Tibicen, Mora, Merces. This may aptly be called
the Moena solution. Now, from the Syce projection, we learn at once that
those cubes, which in it would produce Frenum, Sector, Hama, Remus,
Sypho, Saltus, are not in the shape. This absence of Frenum and Sector
in the Syce view proves that their presence in the Moena solution is
superfluous. The absence of Hama removes the possibility of Hama,
Cortis, Merces. The absence of Remus, Sypho, Saltus, makes no
difference, as neither they nor any of their Syce possibilities are
present in the Moena solution. Hence, the result of comparison of the
Moena and Syce projections and possibilities is the shape: Urna, Moles,
Plebs, Bidens, Pallor, Tibicen, Mora. This may be aptly called the
Moena-Syce solution. Now, in the Alvus projection we see that Ostrum,
Comes, Sector, Ala, and Mars are absent. The absence of Sector, Ala, and
Mars has no effect on our Moena-Syce solution; as it does not contain
any of their Alvus possibilities. But the absence of Ostrum and Comes
proves that in the Moena-Syce solution Bidens and Tibicen are
superfluous, since their presence in the original shape would give
Ostrum and Comes in the Alvus projection. Thus we arrive at the
Moena-Alvus-Syce solution, which gives us the shape: Urna, Moles, Plebs,
Pallor, Mora.

It will be obvious on trial that a shape can be instantly recognised
from its three projections, if the Block be thoroughly well known in all
three positions. Any difficulty in the realization of the shapes comes
from the arbitrary habit of associating the cubes with some one
direction in which they happen to go with regard to us. If we remember
Ostrum as above Urna, we are not remembering the Block, but only one
particular relation of the Block to us. That position of Ostrum is a
fact as much related to ourselves as to the Block. There is, of course,
some information about the Block implied in that position; but it is so
mixed with information about ourselves as to be ineffectual knowledge of
the Block. It is of the highest importance to enter minutely into all
the details of solution written above. For, corresponding to every
operation necessary to a plane-being for the comprehension of our world,
there is an operation, with which we have to become familiar, if in our
turn we would enter into some comprehension of a world higher than our
own. Every cube of the Block ought to be thoroughly known in all its
relations. And the Block must be regarded, not as a formless mass out of
which shapes can be made, but as the sum of all possible shapes, from
which any one we may choose is a selection. In fact, to be familiar with
the Block, we ought to know every shape that could be made by any
selection of its cubes; or, in other words, we ought to make an
exhaustive study of it. In the Appendix is given a set of exercises in
the use of these names (which form a language of shape), and in various
kinds of projections. The projections studied in this chapter are not
the only, nor the most natural, projections by which a plane-being would
study higher space. But they suffice as an illustration of our present
purpose. If the reader will go through the exercises in the Appendix,
and form others for himself, he will find every bit of manipulation done
will be of service to him in the comprehension of higher space.

There is one point of view in the study of the Block, by means of slabs,
which is of some interest. The cubes of the Block, and therefore also
the representative slabs of their faces, can be regarded as forming rows
and columns. There are three sets of them. If we take the Moena view,
they represent the views of the three walls of the Block, as they pass
through the plane. To form the Alvus view, we only have to rearrange the
slabs, and form new sets. The first new set is formed by taking the
first, or left-hand, column of each of the Moena sets. The second Alvus
set is formed by taking the second or middle columns of the three Moena
sets. The third will consist of the remaining or right-hand columns of
the Moenas.

Similarly, the three Syce sets may be formed from the three horizontal
rows or floors of the Moena sets.

Hence, it appears that the plane-being would study our space by taking
all the possible combinations of the corresponding rows and columns. He
would break up the first three sets into other sets, and the study of
the Block would practically become to him the study of these various
arrangements.


CHAPTER VII.

FOUR-SPACE: ITS REPRESENTATION IN THREE-SPACE.

We now come to the essential difficulty of our task. All that has gone
before is preliminary. We have now to frame the method by which we shall
introduce through our space-figures the figures of a higher space. When
a plane-being studies our shapes of cubes, he has to use squares. He is
limited at the outset. A cube appears to him as a square. On Model 1 we
see the various squares as which the cube can appear to him. We suppose
the plane-being to look from the extremity of the Z axis down a vertical
plane. First, there is the Moena square. Then there is the square given
by a section parallel to Moena, which he recognises by the variation of
the bounding lines as soon as the cube begins to pass through his plane.
Then comes the Murex square. Next, if the cube be turned round the Z
axis and passed through, he sees the Alvus and Proes squares and the
intermediate section. So too with the Syce and Mel squares and the
section between them.

Now, dealing with figures in higher space, we are in an analogous
position. We cannot grasp the element of which they are composed. We can
conceive a cube; but that which corresponds to a cube in higher space is
beyond our grasp. But the plane-being was obliged to use two-dimensional
figures, squares, in arriving at a notion of a three-dimensional figure;
so also must we use three-dimensional figures to arrive at the notion
of a four-dimensional. Let us call the figure which corresponds to a
square in a plane and a cube in our space, a tessaract. Model 1 is a
cube. Let us assume a tessaract generated from it. Let us call the
tessaract Urna. The generating cube may then be aptly called Urna Mala.
We may use cubes to represent parts of four-space, but we must always
remember that they are to us, in our study, only what squares are to a
plane-being with respect to a cube.

Let us again examine the mode in which a plane-being represents a Block
of cubes with slabs. Take Block 1 of the 81 Set of cubes. The
plane-being represents this by nine slabs, which represent the Moena
face of the block. Then, omitting the solidity of these first nine
cubes, he takes another set of nine slabs to represent the next wall of
cubes. Lastly, he represents the third wall by a third set, omitting the
solidity of both second and third walls. In this manner, he evidently
represents the extension of the Block upwards and sideways, in the Z and
X directions; but in the Y direction he is powerless, and is compelled
to represent extension in that direction by setting the three sets of
slabs alongside in his plane. The second and third sets denote the
height and breadth of the respective walls, but not their depth or
thickness. Now, note that the Block extends three inches in each of the
three directions. The plane-being can represent two of these dimensions
on his plane; but the unknown direction he has to represent by a
repetition of his plane figures. The cube extends three inches in the Y
direction. He has to use 3 sets of slabs.

The Block is built up arbitrarily in this manner: Starting from Urna
Mala and going up, we come to a Brown cube, and then to a Light-blue
cube. Starting from Urna Mala and going right, we come to an Orange and
a Fawn cube. Starting from Urna Mala and going away from us, we come to
a Blue and a Buff cube. Now, the plane-being represents the Brown and
Orange cubes by squares lying next to the square which represents Urna
Mala. The Blue cube is as close as the Brown cube to Urna Mala, but he
can find no place in the plane where he can place a Blue square so as to
show this co-equal proximity of both cubes to the first. So he is forced
to put a Blue square anywhere in his plane and say of it: “This Blue
square represents what I should arrive at, if I started from Urna Mala
and moved away, that is in the Y or unknown direction.” Now, just as
there are three cubes going up, so there are three going away. Hence,
besides the Blue square placed anywhere on the plane, he must also place
a Buff square beyond it, to show that the Block extends as far away as
it does upwards and sideways. (Each cube being a different colour, there
will be as many different colours of squares as of cubes.) It will
easily be seen that not only the Gold square, but also the Orange and
every other square in the first set of slabs must have two other squares
set somewhere beyond it on the plane to represent the extension of the
Block away, or in the unknown Y direction.

Coming now to the representation of a four-dimensional block, we see
that we can show only three dimensions by cubic blocks, and that the
fourth can only be represented by repetitions of such blocks. There must
be a certain amount of arbitrary naming and colouring. The colours have
been chosen as now stated. Take the first Block of the 81 Set. We are
familiar with its colours, and they can be found at any time by
reference to Model 1. Now, suppose the Gold cube to represent what we
can see in our space of a Gold tessaract; the other cubes of Block 1
give the colours of the tessaracts which lie in the three directions X,
Y, and Z from the Gold one. But what is the colour of the tessaract
which lies next to the Gold in the unknown direction, W? Let us suppose
it to be Stone in colour. Taking out Block 2 of the 81 Set and arranging
it on the pattern of Model 9, we find in it a Stone cube. But, just as
there are three tessaracts in the X, Y, and Z directions, as shown by
the cubes in Block 1, so also must there be three tessaracts in the
unknown direction, W. Take Block 3 of the 81 Set. This Block can be
arranged on the pattern of Model 2. In it there is a Silver cube where
the Gold cube lies in Block 1. Hence, we may say, the tessaract which
comes next to the Stone one in the unknown direction from the Gold, is
of a Silver colour. Now, a cube in all these cases represents a
tessaract. Between the Gold and Stone cubes there is an inch in the
unknown direction. The Gold tessaract is supposed to be Gold throughout
in all four directions, and so also is the Stone. We may imagine it in
this way. Suppose the set of three tessaracts, the Gold, the Stone, and
the Silver to move through our space at the rate of an inch a minute. We
should first see the Gold cube which would last a minute, then the Stone
cube for a minute, and lastly the Silver cube a minute. (This is
precisely analogous to the appearance of passing cubes to the
plane-being as successive squares lasting a minute.) After that, nothing
would be visible.

Now, just as we must suppose that there are three tessaracts proceeding
from the Gold cube in the unknown direction, so there must be three
tessaracts extending in the unknown direction from every one of the 27
cubes of the first Block. The Block of 27 cubes is not a Block of 27
tessaracts, but it represents as much of them as we can see at once in
our space; and they form the first portion or layer (like the first
wall of cubes to the plane-being) of a set of eighty-one tessaracts,
extending to equal distances in all four directions. Thus, to represent
the whole Block of tessaracts there are 81 cubes, or three Blocks of 27
each.

Now, it is obvious that, just as a cube has various plane boundaries, so
a tessaract has various cube boundaries. The cubes of the tessaract,
which we have been regarding, have been those containing the X, Y, and Z
directions, just as the plane-being regarded the Moena faces containing
the X and Z directions. And, as long as the tessaract is unchanged in
its position with regard to our space, we can never see any portion of
it which is in the unknown direction. Similarly, we saw that a
plane-being could not see the parts of a cube which went in the third
direction, until the cube was turned round one of its edges. In order to
make it quite clear what parts of a cube came into the plane, we gave
distinct names to them. Thus, the squares containing the Z and X
directions were called Moena and Murex; those containing the Z and Y,
Alvus and Proes; and those the X and Y, Syce and Mel. Now, similarly
with our four axes, any three will determine a cube. Let the tessaract
in its normal position have the cube Mala determined by the axes Z, X,
Y. Let the cube Lar be that which is determined by X, Y, W, that is, the
cube which, starting from the X Y plane, stretches one inch in the
unknown or W direction. Let Vesper be the cube determined by Z, Y, W,
and Pluvium by Z, X, W. And let these cubes have opposite cubes of the
following names:

  Mala    has Margo
  Lar      „  Velum
  Vesper   „  Idus
  Pluvium  „  Tela

Another way of looking at the matter is this. When a cube is generated
from a square, each of the lines bounding the square becomes a square,
and the square itself becomes a cube, giving two squares in its initial
and final positions. When a cube moves in the new and unknown direction,
each of its planes traces a cube and it generates a tessaract, giving in
its initial and final positions two cubes. Thus there are eight cubes
bounding the tessaract, six of them from the six plane sides and two
from the cube itself. These latter two are Mala and Margo. The cubes
from the six sides are: Lar from Syce, Velum from Mel, Vesper from
Alvus, Idus from Proes, Pluvium from Moena, Tela from Murex. And just as
a plane-being can only see the squares of a cube, so we can only see the
cubes of a tessaract. It may be said that the cube can be pushed partly
through the plane, so that the plane-being sees a section between Moena
and Murex. Similarly, the tessaract can be pushed through our space so
that we can see a section between Mala and Margo.

There is a method of approaching the matter, which settles all
difficulties, and provides us with a nomenclature for every part of the
tessaract. We have seen how by writing down the names of the cubes of a
block, and then supposing that their number increases, certain sets of
the names come to denote points, lines, planes, and solid. Similarly, if
we write down a set of names of tessaracts in a block, it will be found
that, when their number is increased, certain sets of the names come to
denote the various parts of a tessaract.

For this purpose, let us take the 81 Set, and use the cubes to represent
tessaracts. The whole of the 81 cubes make one single tessaractic set
extending three inches in each of the four directions. The names must be
remembered to denote tessaracts. Thus, Corvus is a tessaract which has
the tessaracts Cuspis and Nugæ to the right, Arctos and Ilex above it,
Dos and Cista away from it, and Ops and Spira in the fourth or unknown
direction from it. It will be evident at once, that to write these names
in any representative order we must adopt an arbitrary system. We
require them running in four directions; we have only two on paper. The
X direction (from left to right) and the Y (from the bottom towards the
top of the page) will be assumed to be truly represented. The Z
direction will be symbolized by writing the names in floors, the upper
floors always preceding the lower. Lastly, the fourth, or W, direction
(which has to be symbolized in three-dimensional space by setting the
solids in an arbitrary position) will be signified by writing the names
in blocks, the name which stands in any one place in any block being
next in the W direction to that which occupies the same position in the
block before or after it. Thus, Ops is written in the same place in the
Second Block, Spira in the Third Block, as Corvus occupies in the First
Block.

Since there are an equal number of tessaracts in each of the four
directions, there will be three floors Z when there are three X and Y.
Also, there will be three Blocks W. If there be four tessaracts in each
direction, there will be four floors Z, and four blocks W. Thus, when
the number in each direction is enlarged, the number of blocks W is
equal to the number of tessaracts in each known direction.

On pp. 136, 137 were given the names as used for a cubic block of 27 or
64. Using the same and more names for a tessaractic Set, and remembering
that each name now represents, not a cube, but a tessaract, we obtain
the following nomenclature, the order in which the names are written
being that stated above:

THIRD BLOCK.

  Upper  { Solia         Livor          Talus
  Floor. { Lensa         Lares          Calor
         { Felis         Tholus         Passer
                    -----------------
  Middle { Lixa          Portica        Vena
  Floor. { Crux          Margo          Sal
         { Pagus         Silex          Onager
                    -----------------
  Lower  { Panax         Mensura        Mugil
  Floor. { Opex          Lappa          Mappa
         { Spira         Luca           Ancilla

SECOND BLOCK.

  Upper  { Orsa          Mango          Libera
  Floor. { Creta         Velum          Meatus
         { Lucta         Limbus         Pator
                    -----------------
  Middle { Camoena       Tela           Orca
  Floor. { Vesper        Tessaract      Idus
         { Pagina        Pluvium        Pactum
                    -----------------
  Lower  { Lis           Lorica         Offex
  Floor. { Lua           Lar            Olla
         { Ops           Lotus          Limus

FIRST BLOCK.

  Upper  { Olus          Semita         Lama
  Floor. { Via           Mel            Iter
         { Ilex          Callis         Sors
                    -----------------
  Middle { Bucina        Murex          Daps
  Floor. { Alvus         Mala           Proes
         { Arctos        Moena          Far
                    -----------------
  Lower  { Cista         Cadus          Crus
  Floor. { Dos           Syce           Bolus
         { Corvus        Cuspis         Nugæ

It is evident that this set of tessaracts could be increased to the
number of four in each direction, the names being used as before for the
cubic blocks on pp. 136, 137, and in that case the Second Block would be
duplicated to make the four blocks required in the unknown direction.
Comparing such an 81 Set and 256 Set, we should find that Cuspis, which
was a single tessaract in the 81 Set became two tessaracts in the 256
Set. And, if we introduced a larger number, it would simply become
longer, and not increase in any other dimension. Thus, Cuspis would
become the name of an edge. Similarly, Dos would become the name of an
edge, and also Arctos. Ops, which is found in the Middle Block of the 81
Set, occurs both in the Second and Third Blocks of the 256 Set; that is,
it also tends to elongate and not extend in any other direction, and may
therefore be used as the name of an edge of a tessaract.

Looking at the cubes which represent the Syce tessaracts, we find that,
though they increase in number, they increase only in two directions;
therefore, Syce may be taken to signify a square. But, looking at what
comes from Syce in the W direction, we find in the Middle Block of the
81 Set one Lar, and in the Second and Third Blocks of the 256 Set four
Lars each. Hence, Lar extends in three directions, X, Y, W, and becomes
a cube. Similarly, Moena is a plane; but Pluvium, which proceeds from
it, extends not only sideways and upwards like Moena, but in the unknown
direction also. It occurs in both Middle Blocks of the 256 Set. Hence,
it also is a cube. We have now considered such parts of the Sets as
contain one, two, and three dimensions. But there is one part which
contains four. It is that named Tessaract. In the 256 Set there are
eight such cubes in the Second, and eight in the Third Block; that is,
they extend Z, X, Y, and also W. They may, therefore, be considered to
represent that part of a tessaract or tessaractic Set, which is
analogous to the interior of a cube.

The arrangement of colours corresponding to these names is seen on Model
1 corresponding to Mala, Model 2 to Margo, and Model 9 to the
intermediate block.

When we take the view of the tessaract with which we commenced, and in
which Arctos goes Z, Cuspis X, Dos Y, and Ops W, we see Mala in our
space. But when the tessaract is turned so that the Ops line goes -X,
while Cuspis is turned W, the other two remaining as they were, then we
do not see Mala, but that cube which, in the original position of the
tessaract, contains the Z, Y, W, directions, that is, the Vesper cube.

A plane-being may begin to study a block of cubes by their Syce squares;
but if the block be turned round Dos, he will have Alvus squares in his
space, and he must then use them to represent the cubic Block. So, when
the tessaractic Set is turned round, Mala cubes leave our space, and
Vespers enter.

There are two ways which can be followed in studying the Set of
tessaracts.

I. Each tessaract of one inch every way can be supposed to be of the
same colour throughout, so that, whichever way it be turned, whichever
of its edges coincide with our known axes, it appears to us as a cube of
one uniform colour. Thus, if Urna be the tessaract, Urna Mala would be a
Gold cube, Urna Vesper a Gold cube, and so on. This method is, for the
most part, adopted in the following pages. In this case, a whole Set of
4 × 4 × 4 × 4 tessaracts would in colours resemble a set composed of
four cubes like Models 1, 9, 9, and 2. But, when any question about a
particular tessaract has to be settled, it is advantageous, for the sake
of distinctness, to suppose it coloured in its different regions as the
whole set is coloured.

II. The other plan is, to start with the cubic sides of the inch
tessaract, each coloured according to the scheme of the Models 1 to 8.
In this case, the lines, if shown at all, should be very thin. For, in
fact, only the faces would be seen, as the width of the lines would only
be equal to the thickness of our matter in the fourth dimension, which
is indistinguishable to the senses. If such completely coloured cubes be
used, less error is likely to creep in; but it is a disadvantage that
each cube in the several blocks is exactly like the others in that
block. If the reader make such a set to work with for a time, he will
gain greatly, for the real way of acquiring a sense of higher space is
to obtain those experiences of the senses exactly, which the observation
of a four-dimensional body would give. These Models 1-8 are called sides
of the tessaract.

To make the matter perfectly clear, it is best to suppose that any
tessaract or set of tessaracts which we examine, has a duplicate exactly
similar in shape and arrangement of parts, but different in their
colouring. In the first, let each tessaract have one colour throughout,
so that all its cubes, apprehended in turn in our space, will be of one
and the same colour. In the duplicate, let each tessaract be so coloured
as to show its different cubic sides by their different colours. Then,
when we have it turned to us in different aspects, we shall see
different cubes, and when we try to trace the contacts of the tessaracts
with each other, we shall be helped by realizing each part of every
tessaract in its own colour.


CHAPTER VIII.

REPRESENTATION OF FOUR-SPACE BY NAME. STUDY OF TESSARACTS.

We have now surveyed all the preliminary ground, and can study the
masses of tessaracts without obscurity.

We require a scaffold or framework for this purpose, which in three
dimensions will consist of eight cubic spaces or octants assembled round
one point, as in two dimensions it consisted of four squares or
quadrants round a point.

These eight octants lie between the three axes Z, X, Y, which intersect
at the given point, and can be named according to their positions
between the positive and negative directions of those axes. Thus the
octant Z, X, Y, is that which is contained by the positive portions of
all three axes; the octant Z, [=X], Y, that which is to the left of Z,
X, Y, and between the positive parts of Z and Y and the negative of X.
To illustrate this quite clearly, let us take the eight cubes--Urna,
Moles, Plebs, Frenum, Uncus, Pallor, Bidens, Ostrum--and place them in
the eight octants. Let them be placed round the point of intersection of
the axes; Pallor Corvus, Plebs Ilex, etc., will be at that point. Their
positions will then be:--

  Urna   in the Octant [=Z] [=X] [=Y]
  Moles    „      „    [=Z]   X  [=Y]
  Plebs    „      „    [=Z]   X    Y
  Frenum   „      „    [=Z] [=X]   Y
  Uncus    „      „      Z  [=X]   Y
  Pallor   „      „      Z    X    Y
  Bidens   „      „      Z    X  [=Y]
  Ostrum   „      „      Z  [=X] [=Y]

The names used for the cubes, as they are before us, are as follows:--

THIRD BLOCK.

  Third  { Arcus Mala        Ovis Mala          Portio Mala
  Floor. { Laurus Mala       Tigris Mala        Segmen Mala
         { Axis Mala         Troja Mala         Aries Mala

  Second { Postis Mala       Clipeus Mala       Tabula Mala
  Floor. { Orcus Mala        Lacerta Mala       Testudo Mala
         { Verbum Mala       Luctus Mala        Anguis Mala

  First  { Telum Mala        Nepos Mala         Angusta Mala
  Floor. { Polus Mala        Penates Mala       Vulcan Mala
         { Cervix Mala       Securis Mala       Vinculum Mala

SECOND BLOCK.

  Third  { Ara Mala          Vomer Mala         Pluma Mala
  Floor. { Praeda Mala       Sacerdos Mala      Hydra Mala
         { Cortex Mala       Mica Mala          Flagellum Mala

  Second { Pilum Mala        Glans Mala         Colus Mala
  Floor. { Ocrea Mala        Tessera Mala       Domitor Mala
         { Cardo Mala        Cudo Mala          Malleus Mala

  First  { Agmen Mala        Lacus Mala         Arvus Mala
  Floor. { Crates Mala       Cura Mala          Limen Mala
         { Thyrsus Mala      Vitta Mala         Sceptrum Mala

FIRST BLOCK.

  Third  { Mars Mala         Merces Mala        Tyro Mala
  Floor. { Spicula Mala      Mora Mala          Oliva Mala
         { Comes Mala        Tibicen Mala       Vestis Mala

  Second { Ala Mala          Cortis Mala        Aer Mala
  Floor. { Uncus Mala        Pallor Mala        Tergum Mala
         { Ostrum Mala       Bidens Mala        Scena Mala

  First  { Sector Mala       Hama Mala          Remus Mala
  Floor. { Frenum Mala       Plebs Mala         Sypho Mala
         { Urna Mala         Moles Mala         Saltus Mala

Their colours can be found by reference to the Models 1, 9, 2, which
correspond respectively to the First, Second, and Third Blocks. Thus,
Urna Mala is Gold; Moles, Orange; Saltus, Fawn; Thyrsus, Stone; Cervix,
Silver. The cubes whose colours are not shown in the Models, are Pallor
Mala, Tessera Mala, and Lacerta Mala, which are equivalent to the
interiors of the Model cubes, and are respectively Light-buff, Wooden,
and Sage-green. These 81 cubes are the cubic sides and sections of the
tessaracts of an 81 tessaractic Set, which measures three inches in
every direction. We suppose it to pass through our space. Let us call
the positive unknown direction Ana (_i.e._, +W) and the negative unknown
direction Kata (-W). Then, as the whole tessaract moves Kata at the rate
of an inch a minute, we see first the First Block of 27 cubes for one
minute, then the Second, and lastly the Third, each lasting one minute.

Now, when the First Block stands in the normal position, the edges of
the tessaract that run from the Corvus corner of Urna Mala, are: Arctos
in Z, Cuspis in X, Dos in Y, Ops in W. Hence, we denote this position by
the following symbol:--

   Z   X   Y   W
  _a_ _c_ _d_ _o_

where _a_ stands for Arctos, _c_ for Cuspis, _d_ for Dos, and _o_ for
Ops, and the other letters for the four axes in space. _a_, _c_, _d_,
_o_ are the axes of the tessaract, and can take up different directions
in space with regard to us.

       *       *       *       *       *

Let us now take a smaller four-dimensional set. Of the 81 Set let us
take the following:--

   Z   X   Y   W
  _a_ _c_ _d_ _o_

SECOND BLOCK.

  Second Floor. { Ocrea Mala        Tessera Mala
                { Cardo Mala        Cudo Mala

  First Floor.  { Crates Mala       Cura Mala
                { Thyrsus Mala      Vitta Mala

FIRST BLOCK.

  Second Floor. { Uncus Mala        Pallor Mala
                { Ostrum Mala       Bidens Mala

  First Floor.  { Frenum Mala       Plebs Mala
                { Urna Mala         Moles Mala

Let the First Block be put up before us in Z X Y, (Urna Corvus is at the
junction of our axes Z X Y). The Second Block is now one inch distant in
the unknown direction; and, if we suppose the tessaractic Set to move
through our space at the rate of one inch a minute, the Second will
enter in one minute, and replace the first. But, instead of this, let us
suppose the tessaracts to turn so that Ops, which now goes W, shall go
-X. Then we can see in our space that cubic side of each tessaract which
is contained by the lines Arctos, Dos, and Ops, the cube Vesper; and we
shall no longer have the Mala sides but the Vesper sides of the
tessaractic Set in our space. We will now build it up in its Vesper view
(as we built up the cubic Block in its Alvus view). Take the Gold cube,
which now means Urna Vesper, and place it on the left hand of its former
position as Urna Mala, that is, in the octant Z [=X] Y. Thyrsus Vesper,
which previously lay just beyond Urna Vesper in the unknown direction,
will now lie just beyond it in the -X direction, that is, to the left of
it. The tessaractic Set is now in the position

   Z   X   Y   W
  _a_ _ō_ _d_ _c_

(the minus sign over the _o_ meaning that Ops runs in the negative
direction), and its Vespers lie in the following order:--

SECOND BLOCK.

  Second Floor. { Tessara      Pallor
                { Cudo         Bidens

  First Floor.  { Cura         Plebs
                { Vitta        Moles

FIRST BLOCK.

  Second Floor. { Ocrea        Uncus
                { Cardo        Ostrum

  First Floor.  { Crates       Frenum
                { Thyrsus      Urna

The name Vesper is left out in the above list for the sake of brevity,
but should be used in studying the positions.

[Illustration: Fig. 20.]

On comparing the two lists of the Mala view and Vesper view, it will be
seen that the cubes presented in the Vesper view are new sides of the
tessaract, and that the arrangement of them is different from that in
the Mala view. (This is analogous to the changes in the slabs from the
Moena to Alvus view of the cubic Block.) Of course, the Vespers of all
these tessaracts are not visible at once in our space, any more than are
the Moenas of all three walls of a cubic Block to a plane-being. But if
the tessaractic Set be supposed to move through space in the unknown
direction at the rate of an inch a minute, the Second Block will present
its Vespers after the First Block has lasted a minute. The relative
position of the Mala Block and the Vesper Block may be represented in
our space as in the diagram, Fig. 20. But it must be distinctly
remembered that this arrangement is quite conventional, no more real
than a plane-being’s symbolization of the Moena Wall and the Alvus Wall
of the cubic Block by the arrangement of their Moena and Alvus faces,
with the solidity omitted, along one of his known directions.

The Vespers of the First and Second Blocks cannot be in our space
simultaneously, any more than the Moenas of all three walls in plane
space. To render their simultaneous presence possible, the cubic or
tessaractic Block or Set must be broken up, and its parts no longer
retain their relations. This fact is of supreme importance in
considering higher space. Endless fallacies creep in as soon as it is
forgotten that the cubes are merely representative as the slabs were,
and the positions in our space merely conventional and symbolical, like
those of the slabs along the plane. And these fallacies are so much
fostered by again symbolizing the cubic symbols and their symbolical
positions in perspective drawings or diagrams, that the reader should
surrender all hope of learning space from this book or the drawings
alone, and work every thought out with the cubes themselves.

If we want to see what each individual cube of the tessaractic faces
presented to us in the last example is like, we have only to consider
each of the Malas similar in its parts to Model 1, and each of the
Vespers to Model 5. And it must always be remembered that the cubes,
though used to represent both Mala and Vesper faces of the tessaract,
mean as great a difference as the slabs used for the Moena and Alvus
faces of the cube.

If the tessaractic Set move Kata through our space, when the Vesper
faces are presented to us, we see the following parts of the tessaract
Urna (and, therefore, also the same parts of the other tessaracts):

(1) Urna Vesper, which is Model 5.

(2) A parallel section between Urna Vesper and Urna Idus, which is Model
11.

(3) Urna Idus, which is Model 6.

When Urna Idus has passed Kata our space, Moles Vesper enters it; then a
section between Moles Vesper and Moles Idus, and then Moles Idus. Here
we have evidently observed the tessaract more minutely; as it passes
Kata through our space, starting on its Vesper side, we have seen the
parts which would be generated by Vesper moving along Cuspis--that is
Ana.

Two other arrangements of the tessaracts have to be learnt besides those
from the Mala and Vesper aspect. One of them is the Pluvium aspect.
Build up the Set in Z X [=Y], letting Arctos run Z, Cuspis X, and Ops
[=Y]. In the common plane Moena, Urna Pluvium coincides with Urna Mala,
though they cannot be in our space together; so too Moles Pluvium with
Moles Mala, Ostrum Pluvium with Ostrum Mala. And lying towards us, or
[=Y], is now that tessaract which before lay in the W direction from
Urna, viz., Thyrsus. The order will therefore be the following (a star
denotes the cube whose corner is at point of intersection of the axes,
and the name Pluvium must be understood to follow each of the names):

   Z    X    Y    W
  _a_  _c_  _ō_  _d_

  SECOND BLOCK.

  Second Floor. { Uncus        Pallor
                { Ocrea        Tessera

  First Floor.  { Frenum       Plebs
                { Crates       Cura

  FIRST BLOCK.

  Second Floor. { Ostrum       Bidens
                { Cardo        Cudo

  First Floor.  {*Urna         Moles
                { Thyrsus      Vitta

Thus the wall of cubes in contact with that wall of the Mala position
which contains the Urna, Moles, Ostrum, and Bidens Malas, is a wall
composed of the Pluviums of Urna, Moles, Ostrum, and Bidens. The wall
next to this, and nearer to us, is of Thyrsus, Vitta, Cardo, Cudo,
Pluviums. The Second Block is one inch out of our Space, and only enters
it if the Block moves Kata. Model 7 shows the Pluvium cube; and each of
the cubes of the tessaracts seen in the Pluvium position is a Pluvium.
If the tessaractic Set moved Kata, we would see the Section between
Pluvium and Tela for all but a minute; and then Tela would enter our
space, and the Tela of each tessaract would be seen. Model 12 shows the
Section from Pluvium to Tela. Model 8 is Tela. Tela only lasts for a
flash, as it has only the minutest magnitude in the unknown or Ana
direction. Then, Frenum Pluvium takes the place of Urna Tela; and, when
it passes through, we see a similar section between Frenum Pluvium and
Frenum Tela, and lastly Frenum Tela. Then the tessaractic Set passes
out, or Kata, our space. A similar process takes place with every other
tessaract, when the Set of tessaracts moves through our space.

There is still one more arrangement to be learnt. If the line of the
tessaract, which in the Mala position goes Ana, or W, be changed into
the [=Z] or downwards direction, the tessaract will then appear in our
space below the Mala position; and the side presented to us will not be
Mala, but that which contains the lines Dos, Cuspis, and Ops. This side
is Model 3, and is called Lar. Underneath the place which was occupied
by Urna Mala, will come Urna Lar; under the place of Moles Mala, Moles
Lar; under the place of Frenum Mala, Frenum Lar. The tessaract, which in
the Mala position was an inch out of our space Ana, or W, from Urna
Mala, will now come into it an inch downwards, or [=Z], below Urna
Mala, with its Lar presented to us; that is, Thyrsus Lar will be below
Urna Lar. In the whole arrangement of them written below, the highest
floors are written first, for now they stretch downwards instead of
upwards. The name Lar is understood after each.

   Z   X   Y   W
  _ō_ _c_ _d_ _a_

  SECOND BLOCK.

  Second Floor. { Uncus     Pallor
                { Ostrum    Bidens

  First Floor.  { Ocrea     Tessera
                { Cardo     Cudo

  FIRST BLOCK.

  Second Floor. { Frenum    Plebs
                { *Urna     Moles

  First Floor.  { Crates    Cura
                { Thyrsus   Vitta

Here it is evident that what was the lower floor of Malas, Urna, Moles,
Plebs, Frenum, now appears as if carried downwards instead of upwards,
Lars being presented in our space instead of Malas. This Block of Lars
is what we see of the tessaract Set when the Arctos line, which in the
Mala position goes up, is turned into the Ana, or W, direction, and the
Ops line comes in downwards.

The rest of the tessaracts, which consists of the cubes opposite to the
four treated above, and of the tessaractic space between them, is all
Ana in our space. If the tessaract be moved through our space--for
instance, when the Lars are present in it--we see, taking Urna alone,
first the section between Urna Lar and Urna Velum (Model 10), and then
Urna Velum (Model 4), and similarly the sections and Velums of each
tessaract in the Set. When the First Block has passed Kata our space,
Ostrum Lar enters; and the Lars of the Second Block of tessaracts occupy
the places just vacated by the Velums of the First Block. Then, as the
tessaractic Set moves on Kata, the sections between Velums and Lars of
the Second Block of tessaracts enter our space, and finally their
Velums. Then the whole tessaractic Set disappears from our space.

When we have learnt all these aspects and passages, we have experienced
some of the principal features of this small Set of tessaracts.


CHAPTER IX.

FURTHER STUDY OF TESSARACTS.

When the arrangement of a small set has been mastered, the different
views of the whole 81 Set should be learnt. It is now clear to us that,
in the list of the names of the eighty-one tessaracts given above, those
which lie in the W direction appear in different blocks, while those
that lie in the Z, X, or Y directions can be found in the same block.
Therefore, from the arrangement given, which is denoted by

   Z   X   Y   W  ,
  _a_ _c_ _d_ _o_

or more briefly by _a c d o_, we can form any other arrangement.

To confirm the meaning of the symbol _a c d o_ for position, let us
remember that the order of the axes known in our space will invariably
be Z X Y, and the unknown direction will be stated last, thus: Z X Y W.
Hence, if we write _a ō d c_, we know that the position or aspect
intended is that in which Arctos (_a_) goes Z, Ops (_ō_) negative X, Dos
(_d_) Y, and Cuspis (_c_) W. And such an arrangement can be made by
shifting the nine cubes on the left side of the First Block of the
eighty-one tessaracts, and putting them into the Z [=X] Y octant, so
that they just touch their former position. Next to them, to their left,
we set the nine of the left side of the Second Block of the 81 Set; and
next to these again, on their left, the nine of the left side of the
Third Block. This Block of twenty-seven now represents Vesper Cubes,
which have only one square identical with the Mala cubes of the
previous blocks, from which they were taken.

Similarly the Block which is one inch Ana, can be made by taking the
nine cubes which come vertically in the middle of each of the Blocks in
the first position, and arranging them in a similar manner. Lastly, the
Block which lies two inches Ana, can be made by taking the right sides
of nine cubes each from each of the three original Blocks, and arranging
them so that those in the Second original Block go to the left of those
in the First, and those in the Third to their left. In this manner we
should obtain three new Blocks, which represent what we can see of the
tessaracts, when the direction in which Urna, Moles, Saltus lie in the
original Set, is turned W.

The Pluvium Block we can make by taking the front wall of each original
Block, and setting each an inch nearer to us, that is -Y. The far sides
of these cubes are Moenas of Pluviums. By continuing this treatment of
the other walls of the three original Blocks parallel to the front wall,
we obtain two other Blocks of tessaracts. The three together are the
tessaractic position _a c ō d_, for in all of them Ops lies in the -Y
direction, and Dos has been turned W.

The Lar position is more difficult to construct. To put the Lars of the
Blocks in their natural position in our space, we must start with the
original Mala Blocks, at least three inches above the table. The First
Lar Block is made by taking the lowest floors of the three Mala Blocks,
and placing them so that that of the Second is below that of the First,
and that of the Third below that of the Second. The floor of cubes whose
diagonal runs from Urna Lar to Remus Lar, will be at the top of the
Block of Lars; and that whose diagonal goes from Cervix Lar to Angusta
Lar, will be at the bottom. The next Block of Lars will be made by
taking the middle horizontal floors of the three original Blocks, and
placing them in a similar succession--the floor from Ostrum Lar to Aer
Lar being at the top, that from Cardo Lar to Colus Lar in the middle,
and Verbum Lar to Tabula Lar at the bottom. The Third Lar Block is
composed of the top floor of the First Block on the top--that is, of
Comes Lar to Tyro Lar, of Cortex Lar to Pluma Lar in the middle, and
Axis Lar to Portio Lar at the bottom.


CHAPTER X.

CYCLICAL PROJECTIONS.

Let us denote the original position of the cube, that wherein Arctos
goes Z, Cuspis X, and Dos Y, by the expression,

   Z   X   Y       (1)
  _a_ _c_ _d_

If the cube be turned round Cuspis, Dos goes [=Z], Cuspis remains
unchanged, and Arctos goes Y, and we have the position,

     Z    X   Y
  _[=d]_ _c_ _a_

where

     Z
  _[=d]_

means that Dos runs in the negative direction of the Z axis from the
point where the axes intersect. We might write

  [=Z]
  _d_

but it is preferable to write

     Z
  _[=d]_.

If we next turn the cube round the line, which runs Y, that is, round
Arctos, we obtain the position,

   Z   X   Y       (2)
  _c_ _d_ _a_

and by means of this double turn we have put _c_ and _d_ in the places
of _a_ and _c_. Moreover, we have no negative directions. This position
we call simply _c d a_. If from it we turn the cube round _a_, which
runs Y, we get

   Z     X    Y
  _d_ _[=c]_ _a_,

and if, then, we turn it round Dos we get

   Z   X   Y
  _d_ _a_ _c_

or simply _d a c_. This last is another position in which all the lines
are positive, and the projections, instead of lying in different
quadrants, will be contained in one.

The arrangement of cubes in _a c d_ we know. That in _c d a_ is:

           { Vestis   Oliva    Tyro
  Third    { Scena    Tergum   Aer
  Floor.   { Saltus   Sypho    Remus

           { Tibicen  Mora     Merces
  Second   { Bidens   Pallor   Cortis
  Floor.   { Moles    Plebs    Hama

           { Comes    Spicula  Mars
  First    { Ostrum   Uncus    Ala
  Floor.   { Urna     Frenum   Sector

It will be found that learning the cubes in this position gives a great
advantage, for thereby the axes of the cube become dissociated with
particular directions in space.

The _d a c_ position gives the following arrangement:

  Remus     Aer       Tyro
  Hama      Cortis    Merces
  Sector    Ala       Mars

  Sypho     Tergum    Oliva
  Plebs     Pallor    Mora
  Frenum    Uncus     Spicula

  Saltus    Scena     Vestis
  Moles     Bidens    Tibicen
  Urna      Ostrum    Comes

The sides, which touch the vertical plane in the first position, are
respectively, in _a c d_ Moena, in _c d a_ Syce, in _d a c_ Alvus.

Take the shape Urna, Ostrum, Moles, Saltus, Scena, Sypho, Remus, Aer,
Tyro. This gives in _a c d_ the projection: Urna Moena, Ostrum Moena,
Moles Moena, Saltus Moena, Scena Moena, Vestis Moena. (If the different
positions of the cube are not well known, it is best to have a list of
the names before one, but in every case the block should also be built,
as well as the names used.) The same shape in the position _c d a_ is,
of course, expressed in the same words, but it has a different
appearance. The front face consists of the Syces of

  Saltus    Sypho      Remus
  Moles     Plebs      Hama
  Urna      Frenum     Sector

And taking the shape we find we have Urna, and we know that Ostrum lies
behind Urna, and does not come in; next we have Moles, Saltus, and we
know that Scena lies behind Saltus and does not come in; lastly, we have
Sypho and Remus, and we know that Aer and Tyro are in the Y direction
from Remus, and so do not come in. Hence, altogether the projection will
consist only of the Syces of Urna, Moles, Saltus, Sypho, and Remus.

Next, taking the position _d a c_, the cubes in the front face have
their Alvus sides against the plane, and are:

  Sector     Ala        Mars
  Frenum     Uncus      Spicula
  Urna       Ostrum     Comes

And, taking the shape, we find Urna, Ostrum; Moles and Saltus are hidden
by Urna, Scena is behind Ostrum, Sypho gives Frenum, Remus gives Sector,
Aer gives Ala, and Tyro gives Mars. All these are Alvus sides.

Let us now take the reverse problem, and, given the three cyclical
projections, determine the shape. Let the _a c d_ projection be the
Moenas of Urna, Ostrum, Bidens, Scena, Vestis. Let the _c d a_ be the
Syces of Urna, Frenum, Plebs, Sypho, and the _d a c_ be the Alvus of
Urna, Frenum, Uncus, Spicula. Now, from _a c d_ we have Urna, Frenum,
Sector, Ostrum, Uncus, Ala, Bidens, Pallor, Cortis, Scena, Tergum, Aer,
Vestis, Oliva, Tyro. From _c d a_ we have Urna, Ostrum, Comes, Frenum,
Uncus, Spicula, Plebs, Pallor, Mora, Sypho, Tergum, Oliva. In order to
see how these will modify each other, let us consider the _a c d_
solution as if it were a set of cubes in the _c d a_ arrangement. Here,
those that go in the Arctos direction, go away from the plane of
projection, and must be represented by the Syce of the cube in contact
with the plane. Looking at the _a c d_ solution we write down (keeping
those together which go away from the plane of projection): Urna and
Ostrum, Frenum and Uncus, Sector and Ala, Bidens, Pallor, Cortis, Scena
and Vestis, Tergum and Oliva, Aer and Tyro. Here we see that the whole
_c d a_ face is filled up in the projection, as far as this solution is
concerned. But in the _c d a_ solution we have only Syces of Urna,
Frenum, Plebs, Sypho. These Syces only indicate the presence of a
certain number of the cubes stated above as possible from the Moena
projection, and those are Urna, Ostrum, Frenum, Uncus, Pallor, Tergum,
Oliva. This is the result of a comparison of the Moena projection with
the Syce projection. Now, writing these last named as they come in the
_d a c_ projection, we have Urna, Ostrum, Frenum, Uncus and Pallor and
Tergum, Oliva. And of these Ostrum Alvus is wanting in the _d a c_
projection as given above. Hence Ostrum will be wanting in the final
shape, and we have as the final solution: Urna, Frenum, Uncus, Pallor,
Tergum, Oliva.


CHAPTER XI.

A TESSARACTIC FIGURE AND ITS PROJECTIONS.

We will now consider a fourth-dimensional shape composed of tessaracts,
and the manner in which we can obtain a conception of it. The operation
is precisely analogous to that described in chapter VI., by which a
plane being could obtain a conception of solid shapes. It is only a
little more difficult in that we have to deal with one dimension or
direction more, and can only do so symbolically.

We will assume the shape to consist of a certain number of the 81
tessaracts, whose names we have given on p. 168. Let it consist of the
thirteen tessaracts: Urna, Moles, Plebs, Frenum, Pallor, Tessera, Cudo,
Vitta, Cura, Penates, Polus, Orcus, Lacerta.

Firstly, we will consider what appearances or projections these
tessaracts will present to us according as the tessaractic set touches
our space with its (_a_) Mala cubes, (_b_) Vesper cubes, (_c_) Pluvium
cubes, or (_d_) Lar cubes. Secondly, we will treat the converse
question, how the shape can be determined when the projections in each
of those views are given.

Let us build up in cubes the four different arrangements of the
tessaracts according as they enter our space on their Mala, Vesper,
Pluvium or Lar sides. They can only be printed by symbolizing two of the
directions. In the following tabulations the directions Y, X will at
once be understood. The direction Z (expressed by the wavy line)
indicates that the floors of nine, each printed nearer the top of the
page, lie above those printed nearer the bottom of it. The direction W
is indicated by the dotted line, which shows that the floors of nine
lying to the left or right are in the W direction (Ana) or the -W
direction (Kata) from those which lie to the right or left. For
instance, in the arrangement of the tessaracts, as Malas (Table A) the
tessaract Tessara, which is exactly in the middle of the eighty-one
tessaracts has

  Domitor on its right side or in the  X direction.
  Ocrea on its left     „      „      -X     „
  Glans away from us    „      „       Y     „
  Cudo nearer to us     „      „      -Y     „
  Sacerdos above it     „      „       Z     „
  Cura below it         „      „      -Z     „
  Lacerta in the Ana or                W     „
  Pallor in the Kata or               -W     „

Similarly Cervix lies in the Ana or W direction from Urna, with Thyrsus
between them. And to take one more instance, a journey from Saltus to
Arcus would be made by travelling Y to Remus, thence -X to Sector,
thence Z to Mars, and finally W to Arcus. A line from Saltus to Arcus is
therefore a diagonal of the set of 81 tessaracts, because the full
length of its side has been traversed in each of the four directions to
reach one from the other, _i.e._ Saltus to Remus, Remus to Sector,
Sector to Mars, Mars to Arcus.

TABLE A.

Mala presentation of 81 Tessaracts.

   Z W------------------------------------------------------- -W
   |
   |  Y                  Y                  Y
   |  |                  |                  |
   |  |    Block A       |    Block B       |    Block C
   |  |                  |                  |
   |  +---------------X  +---------------X  +---------------X
   |
   |  Y                  Y                  Y
   |  |                  |                  |
   |  |    Block D       |    Block E       |    Block F
   |  |                  |                  |
   |  +---------------X  +---------------X  +---------------X
   |
   |  Y                  Y                  Y
   |  |                  |                  |
   |  |    Block G       |    Block H       |    Block I
   |  |                  |                  |
   |  +---------------X  +---------------X  +---------------X
  -Z

  Block A:
  Arcus          Ovis           Portio
  Laurus         Tigris         Segmen
  Axis           Troja          Aries

  Block B:
  Ara            Vomer          Pluma
  Praeda         Sacerdos       Hydra
  Cortex         Mica           Flagellum

  Block C:
  Mars           Merces         Tyro
  Spicula        Mora           Oliva
  Comes          Tibicen        Vestis

  Block D:
  Postis         Clipeus        Tabula
  _Orcus_        _Lacerta_      Testudo
  Verbum         Luctus         Anguis

  Block E:
  Pilum          Glans          Coins
  Ocrea          _Tessera_      Domitor
  Cardo          _Cudo_         Malleus

  Block F:
  Ala            Cortis         Aer
  Uncus‡         _Pallor_‡      Tergum
  Ostrum         Bidens‡        Scena

  Block G:
  Telum          Nepos          Angusta
  _Polus_        _Penates_      Vulcan
  Cervix         Securis        Vinculum

  Block H:
  Agmen          Lacus          Arvus
  Crates         _Cura_         Limen
  Thyrsus        _Vitta_        Sceptrum

  Block I:
  Sector         Hama           Remus
  _Frenum_‡      _Plebs_‡       Sypho
  _Urna_‡        _Moles_‡       Saltus

TABLE B.

Vesper presentation of 81 Tessaracts.

   Z  W------------------------------------------------------ -W
   |
   |                  Y                  Y                  Y
   |                  |                  |                  |
   |       Block A    |       Block B    |       Block C    |
   |                  |                  |                  |
   | -X---------------+ -X---------------+ -X---------------+
   |
   |                  Y                  Y                  Y
   |                  |                  |                  |
   |       Block D    |       Block E    |       Block F    |
   |                  |                  |                  |
   | -X---------------+ -X---------------+ -X---------------+
   |
   |                  Y                  Y                  Y
   |                  |                  |                  |
   |       Block G    |       Block H    |       Block I    |
   |                  |                  |                  |
   | -X---------------+ -X---------------+ -X---------------+
  -Z

  Block A:
  Portio         Pluma          Tyro
  Segmen         Hydra          Oliva
  Aries          Flagellum      Vestis

  Block B:
  Ovis           Vomer          Merces
  Tigris         Sacerdos       Mora
  Troja          Mica           Tibicen

  Block C:
  Arcus          Ara            Mars
  Laurus         Praeda         Spicula
  Axis           Cortex         Comes

  Block D:
  Tabula         Colus          Aer
  Testudo        Domitor        Tergum
  Anguis         Malleus        Scena

  Block E:
  Clipeus        Glans          Cortis
  _Lacerta_*     _Tessera_*     _Pallor_*
  Luctus*        _Cudo_*        Bidens*

  Block F:
  Postis         Pilum          Ala
  _Orcus_*       Ocrea*         Uncus*
  Verbum†        Cardo†         Ostrum†

  Block G:
  Angusta        Arvus          Remus
  Vulcan         Limen          Sypho
  Vinculum       Sceptrum       Saltus

  Block H:
  Nepos          Lacus          Hama
  _Penates_*     _Cura_*        _Plebs_*
  Securis*       _Vitta_*       _Moles_*

  Block I:
  Telum          Agmen          Sector
  _Polus_*       Crates*        _Frenum_*
  Cervix*        Thyrsus*       _Urna_*

TABLE C.

Pluvium presentation of 81 Tessaracts.

   Z W------------------------------------------------------- -W
   |
   |  +----------------X +----------------X +---------------X
   |  |                  |                  |
   |  |    Block A       |    Block B       |    Block C
   |  |                  |                  |
   | -Y                 -Y                 -Y
   |
   |  +----------------X +----------------X +---------------X
   |  |                  |                  |
   |  |    Block D       |    Block E       |    Block F
   |  |                  |                  |
   | -Y                 -Y                 -Y
   |
   |  +----------------X +----------------X +---------------X
   |  |                  |                  |
   |  |    Block G       |    Block H       |    Block I
   |  |                  |                  |
   | -Y                 -Y                 -Y
  -Z

  Block A:
  Mars           Merces         Tyro
  Ara            Vomer          Pluma
  Arcus          Ovis           Portio

  Block B:
  Spicula        Mora           Oliva
  Praeda         Sacerdos       Hydra
  Laurus         Tigris         Segmen

  Block C:
  Comes          Tibicen        Vestis
  Cortex         Mica           Flagellum
  Axis           Troja          Aries

  Block D:
  Ala            Cortis         Aer
  Pilum          Glans          Colus
  Postis         Clipeus        Tabula

  Block E:
  Uncus*         _Pallor_*      Tergum
  Ocrea*         _Tessera_*     Domitor
  _Orcus_*       _Lacerta_*     Testudo

  Block F:
  Ostrum†        Bidens†        Scena
  Cardo†         _Cudo_*        Malleus
  Verbum†        Luctus†        Anguis

  Block G:
  Sector         Hama           Remus
  Agmen          Lacus          Arvus
  Telum          Nepos          Angusta

  Block H:
  _Frenum_*      _Plebs_*       Sypho
  Crates*        _Cura_*        Limen
  _Polus_*       _Penates_*     Vulcan

  Block I:
  _Urna_*        _Moles_*       Saltus
  Thyrsus*       _Vitta_*       Sceptrum
  Cervix†        Securis†       Vinculum

TABLE D.

Lar presentation of 81 Tessaracts.

   Z W------------------------------------------------------- -W
   |
   |  Y                  Y                  Y
   |  |                  |                  |
   |  |    Block A       |    Block A       |    Block A
   |  |                  |                  |
   |  +---------------X  +---------------X  +---------------X
   |
   |  Y                  Y                  Y
   |  |                  |                  |
   |  |    Block A       |    Block A       |    Block A
   |  |                  |                  |
   |  +---------------X  +---------------X  +---------------X
   |
   |  Y                  Y                  Y
   |  |                  |                  |
   |  |    Block A       |    Block A       |    Block A
   |  |                  |                  |
   |  +---------------X  +---------------X  +---------------X
  -Z

  Block A:
  Mars           Merces         Tyro
  Spicula        Mora           Oliva
  Comes          Tibicen        Vestis

  Block B:
  Ala            Cortis         Aer
  Uncus          _Pallor_*      Tergum
  Ostrum         Bidens         Scena

  Block C:
  Sector         Hama           Remus
  _Frenum_*      _Plebs_*       Sypho
  _Urna_*        _Moles_*       Saltus

  Block D:
  Ara            Vomer          Pluma
  Proeda         Sacerdos       Hydra
  Cortex         Mica           Flagellum

  Block E:
  Pilum          Glans          Colus
  Ocrea          _Tessera_*     Domitor
  Cardo          _Cudo_*        Malleus

  Block F:
  Agmen          Laurus         Arvus
  Crates         _Cura_*        Limen
  Thyrsus        _Vitta_*       Sceptrum

  Block G:
  Arcus          Ovis           Portio
  Laurus         Tigris         Segmen
  Axis           Troja          Aries

  Block H:
  Postis         Clipeus        Tabula
  _Orcus_*       _Lacerta_*     Testudo
  Verbum         Luctus         Anguis

  Block I:
  Telum          Nepos          Angusta
  _Polus_*       _Penates_*     Vulcan
  Cervix         Securis        Vinculum

The relation between the four different arrangements shown in the tables
A, B, C, and D, will be understood from what has been said in chapter
VIII. about a small set of sixteen tessaracts. A glance at the lines,
which indicate the directions in each, will show the changes effected by
turning the tessaracts from the Mala presentation.

  In the Vesper presentation:

  The tessaracts--
  (_e.g._ Urna, Ostrum, Comes),   which ran Z still run  Z.
  (_e.g._ Urna, Frenum, Sector),      „     Y    „       Y.
  (_e.g._ Urna, Moles, Saltus),       „     X now run    W.
  (_e.g._ Urna, Thyrsus, Cervix),     „     W    „      -X.

  In the Pluvium presentation:

  The tessaracts--
  (_e.g._ Urna, Ostrum, Comes),   which ran Z still run  Z.
  (_e.g._ Urna, Moles, Saltus),       „     X    „       X.
  (_e.g._ Urna, Frenum, Sector),      „     Y now run    W.
  (_e.g._ Urna, Thyrsus, Cervix),     „     W    „      -Y.

  In the Lar presentation:

  The tessaracts--
  (_e.g._ Urna, Moles, Saltus),   which ran X still run  X.
  (_e.g._ Urna, Frenum, Sector),      „     Y    „       Y.
  (_e.g._ Urna, Ostrum, Comes),       „     Z now run    W.
  (_e.g._ Urna, Thyrsus, Cervix),     „     W    „      -Z.

This relation was already treated in chapter IX., but it is well to have
it very clear for our present purpose. For it is the apparent change of
the relative positions of the tessaracts in each presentation, which
enables us to determine any body of them.

In considering the projections, we always suppose ourselves to be
situated Ana or W towards the tessaracts, and any movement to be Kata or
-W through our space. For instance, in the Mala presentation we have
first in our space the Malas of that block of tessaracts, which is the
last in the -W direction. Thus, the Mala projection of any given
tessaract of the set is that Mala in the extreme -W block, whose place
its (the given tessaract’s) Mala would occupy, if the tessaractic set
moved Kata until the given tessaract reached our space. Or, in other
words, if all the tessaracts were transparent except those which
constitute the body under consideration, and if a light shone through
Four-space from the Ana (W) side to the Kata (-W) side, there would be
darkness in each of those Malas, which would be occupied by the Mala of
any opaque tessaract, if the tessaractic set moved Kata.

Let us look at the set of 81 tessaracts we have built up in the Mala
arrangements, and trace the projections in the extreme -W block of the
thirteen of our shape. The latter are printed in italics in Table A, and
their projections are marked ‡.

Thus the cube Uncus Mala is the projection of the tessaract Orcus,
Pallor Mala of Pallor and Tessera and Tacerta, Bidens Mala of Cudo,
Frenum Mala of Frenum and Polus, Plebs Mala of Plebs and Cura and
Penates, Moles Mala of Moles and Vitta, Urna Mala of Urna.

Similarly, we can trace the Vesper projections (Table B). Orcus Vesper
is the projection of the tessaracts Orcus and Lacerta, Ocrea Vesper of
Tessera, Uncus Vesper of Pallor, Cardo Vesper of Cudo, Polus Vesper of
Polus and Penates, Crates Vesper of Cura, Frenum Vesper of Frenum and
Plebs, Urna Vesper of Urna and Moles, Thyrsus Vesper of Vitta. Next in
the Pluvium presentation (Table C) we find that Bidens Pluvium is the
projection of the tessaract Pallor, Cudo Pluvium of Cudo and Tessera,
Luctus Pluvium of Lacerta, Verbum Pluvium of Orcus, Urna Pluvium of Urna
and Frenum, Moles Pluvium of Moles and Plebs, Vitta Pluvium of Vitta and
Cura, Securis Pluvium of Penates, Cervix Pluvium of Polus. Lastly, in
the Lar presentation (Table D) we observe that Frenum Lar is the
projection of Frenum, Plebs Lar of Plebs and Pallor, Moles Lar of
Moles, Urna Lar of Urna, Cura Lar of Cura and Tessara, Vitta Lar of
Vitta and Cudo, Penates Lar of Penates and Lacerta, Polur Lar of Polus
and Orcus.

Secondly, we will treat the converse problem, how to determine the shape
when the projections in each presentation are given. Looking back at the
list just given above, let us write down in each presentation the
projections only.

  Mala projections:

  Uncus, Pallor, Bidens, Frenum, Plebs, Moles, Urna.

  Vesper projections:

  Orcus, Ocrea, Uncus, Cardo, Polus, Crates, Frenum, Urna, Thyrsus.

  Pluvium projections:

  Bidens, Cudo, Luctus, Verbum, Urna, Moles, Vitta, Securis, Cervix.

  Lar projections:

  Frenum, Plebs, Moles, Urna, Cura, Vitta, Polus, Penates.

Now let us determine the shape indicated by these projections. In now
using the same tables we must not notice the italics, as the shape is
supposed to be unknown. It is assumed that the reader is building the
problem in cubes. From the Mala projections we might infer the presence
of all or any of the tessaracts written in the brackets in the following
list of the Mala presentation.

  (Uncus, Ocrea, Orcus); (Pallor, Tessera, Lacerta);

  (Bidens, Cudo, Luctus); (Frenum, Crates, Polus);

  (Plebs, Cura, Penates); (Moles, Vitta, Securis);

  (Urna, Thyrsus, Cervix).

Let us suppose them all to be present in our shape, and observe what
their appearance would be in the Vesper presentation. We mark them all
with an asterisk in Table B. In addition to those already marked we must
mark (†) Verbum, Cardo, Ostrum, and then we see all the Vesper
projections, which would be formed by all the tessaracts possible from
the Mala projections. Let us compare these Vesper projections, viz.
Orcus, Ocrea, Uncus, Verbum, Cardo, Ostrum, Polus, Crates, Frenum,
Cervix, Thyrsus, Urna, with the given Vesper projections. We see at once
that Verbum, Ostrum, and Cervix are absent. Therefore, we may conclude
that all the tessaracts, which would be implied as possible by their
presence, are absent, and of the Mala possibilities may exclude the
tessaracts Bidens, Luctus, Securis, and Cervix itself. Thus, of the 21
tessaracts possible in the Mala view, there remain only 17 possible,
both in the Mala and Vesper views, viz. Uncus, Ocrea, Orcus, Pallor,
Tessera, Lacerta, Cudo, Frenum, Crates, Polus, Plebs, Cura, Penates,
Moles, Vitta, Urna, Thyrsus. This we call the Mala-Vesper solution.

Next let us take the Pluvium presentation. We again mark with an
asterisk in Table C the possibilities inferred from the Mala-Vesper
solution, and take the projections those possibilities would produce.
The additional projections are again marked (†). There are twelve
Pluvium projections altogether, viz. Bidens, Ostrum, Cudo, Cardo,
Luctus, Verbum, Urna, Moles, Vitta, Thyrsus, Securis, Cervix. Again we
compare these with the given Pluvium projections, and find three are
absent, viz. Ostrum, Cardo, Thyrsus. Hence the tessaracts implied by
Ostrum and Cardo and Thyrsus cannot be in our shape, viz. Uncus, Ocrea,
Crates, nor Thyrsus itself. Excluding these four from the seventeen
possibilities of the Mala-Vesper solution we have left the thirteen
tessaracts: Orcus, Pallor, Tessera, Lacerta, Cudo, Frenum, Polus,
Plebs, Cura, Penates, Moles, Vitta, Urna. This we call the
Mala-Vesper-Pluvium solution.

Lastly, we have to consider whether these thirteen tessaracts are
consistent with the given Lar projections. We mark them again on Table D
with an asterisk, and we find that the projections are exactly those
given, viz. Frenum, Plebs, Moles, Urna, Cura, Vitta, Polus, Penates.
Therefore, we have not to exclude any of the thirteen, and can infer
that they constitute the shape, which produces the four different given
views or projections.

In fine, any shape in space consists of the possibilities common to the
projections of its parts upon the boundaries of that space, whatever be
the number of its dimensions. Hence the simple rule for the
determination of the shape would be to write down all the possibilities
of the sets of projections, and then cancel all those possibilities
which are not common to all. But the process adopted above is much
preferable, as through it we may realize the gradual delimitation of the
shape view by view. For once more we must remind ourselves that our
great object is, not to arrive at results by symbolical operations, but
to realize those results piece by piece through realized processes.



APPENDICES.


APPENDIX A.

This set of 100 names is useful for studying Plane Space, and forms a
square 10 × 10.

  Aiōn   Bios   Hupar   Neas    Kairos  Enos    Thlipsis Cheimas Theion Epei

  Itea   Hagios Phaino  Geras   Tholos  Ergon   Pachūs   Kiōn    Eris   Cleos

  Loma   Etēs   Trochos Klazo   Lutron  Hēdūs   Ischūs   Paigma  Hedna  Demas

  Numphe Bathus Pauo    Euthu   Holos   Para    Thuos    Karē    Pylē   Spareis

  Ania   Eōn    Seranx  Mesoi   Dramo   Thallos Aktē     Ozo     Onos   Magos

  Notos  Mēnis  Lampas  Ornis   Thama   Eni     Pholis   Mala    Strizo Rudon

  Labo   Helor  Rupa    Rabdos  Doru    Epos    Theos    Idris   Ēdē    Hepo

  Sophos Ichor  Kaneōn  Ephthra Oxis    Lukē    Blue     Helos   Peri   Thelus

  Eunis  Limos  Keedo   Igde    Matē    Lukos   Pteris   Holmos  Oulo   Dokos

  Aeido  Ias    Assa    Muzo    Hippeus Eōs     Atē      Akme    Ōrē    Gua


APPENDIX B.

The following list of names is used to denote cubic spaces. It makes a
cubic block of six floors, the highest being the sixth.

  _ F  Fons       Plectrum   Vulnus     Arena      Mensa      Terminus
  S l  Testa      Plausus    Uva        Collis     Coma       Nebula
  i o  Copia      Cornu      Solum      Munus      Rixum      Vitrum
  x o  Ars        Fervor     Thyma      Colubra    Seges      Cor
  t r. Lupus      Classis    Modus      Flamma     Mens       Incola
  h _  Thalamus   Hasta      Calamus    Crinis     Auriga     Vallum

  _ F  Linteum    Pinnis     Puppis     Nuptia     Aegis      Cithara
  F l  Triumphus  Curris     Lux        Portus     Latus      Funis
  i o  Regnum     Fascis     Bellum     Capellus   Arbor      Custos
  f o  Sagitta    Puer       Stella     Saxum      Humor      Pontus
  t r. Nomen      Imago      Lapsus     Quercus    Mundus     Proelium
  h _  Palaestra  Nuncius    Bos        Pharetra   Pumex      Tibia
  _
  F F  Lignum     Focus      Ornus      Lucrum     Alea       Vox
  o l  Caterva    Facies     Onus       Silva      Gelu       Flumen
  u o  Tellus     Sol        Os         Arma       Brachium   Jaculum
  r o  Merum      Signum     Umbra      Tempus     Corona     Socius
  t r. Moena      Opus       Honor      Campus     Rivus      Imber
  h _  Victor     Equus      Miles      Cursus     Lyra       Tunica

  _ F  Haedus     Taberna    Turris     Nox        Domus      Vinum
  T l  Pruinus    Chorus     Luna       Flos       Lucus      Agna
  h o  Fulmen     Hiems      Ver        Carina     Arator     Pratum
  i o  Oculus     Ignis      Aether     Cohors     Penna      Labor
  r r. Aes        Pectus     Pelagus    Notus      Fretum     Gradus
  d _  Princeps   Dux        Ventus     Navis      Finis      Robur
  _
  S F  Vultus     Hostis     Figura     Ales       Coelum     Aura
  e l  Humerus    Augur      Ludus      Clamor     Galea      Pes
  c o  Civis      Ferrum     Pugna      Res        Carmen     Nubes
  o o  Litus      Unda       Rex        Templum    Ripa       Amnis
  n r. Pannus     Ulmus      Sedes      Columba    Aequor     Dama
  d _  Dexter     Urbs       Gens       Monstrum   Pecus      Mons

  _ F  Nemus      Sidus      Vertex     Nix        Grando     Arx
  F l  Venator    Cerva      Aper       Plagua     Hedera     Frons
  i o  Membrum    Aqua       Caput      Castrum    Lituus     Tuba
  r o  Fluctus    Rus        Ratis      Amphora    Pars       Dies
  s r. Turba      Ager       Trabs      Myrtus     Fibra      Nauta
  t _  Decus      Pulvis     Meta       Rota       Palma      Terra


APPENDIX C.

The following names are used for a set of 256 Tessaracts.

             FOURTH BLOCK.                        THIRD BLOCK.

            _Fourth Floor._                      _Fourth Floor._
  Dolium  Caballus Python   Circaea    Charta  Cures    Quaestor Cliens
  Cussis  Pulsus   Drachma  Cordax     Frux    Pyra     Lena     Procella
  Porrum  Consul   Diota    Dyka       Hera    Esca     Secta    Rugæ
  Columen Ravis    Corbis   Rapina     Eurus   Gloria   Socer    Sequela

            _Third Floor._                       _Third Floor._
  Alexis  Planta   Corymbus Lectrum    Arche   Agger    Cumulus  Cassis
  Aestus  Labellum Calathus Nux        Arcus   Ovis     Portio   Mimus
  Septum  Sepes    Turtur   Ordo       Laurus  Tigris   Segmen   Obolus
  Morsus  Aestas   Capella  Rheda      Axis    Troja    Aries    Fuga

           _Second Floor._                      _Second Floor._
  Corydon Jugum    Tornus   Labrum     Ruina   Culmen   Fenestra Aedes
  Lac     Hibiscus Donum    Caltha     Postis  Clipeus  Tabula   Lingua
  Senex   Palus    Salix    Cespes     Orcus   Lacerta  Testudo  Scala
  Amictus Gurges   Otium    Pomum      Verbum  Luctus   Anguis   Dolus

            _First Floor._                       _First Floor._
  Odor    Aprum    Pignus   Messor     Additus Salus    Clades   Rana
  Color   Casa     Cera     Papaver    Telum   Nepos    Angusta  Mucro
  Spes    Lapis    Apis     Afrus      Polus   Penates  Vulcan   Ira
  Vitula  Clavis   Fagus    Cornix     Cervix  Securis  Vinculum Furor

             SECOND BLOCK.                        FIRST BLOCK.

            _Fourth Floor._                      _Fourth Floor._
  Actus   Spadix   Sicera   Anser      Horreum Fumus    Hircus   Erisma
  Auspex  Praetor  Atta     Sonus      Anulus  Pluor    Acies    Naxos
  Fulgor  Ardea    Prex     Aevum      Etna    Gemma    Alpis    Arbiter
  Spina   Birrus   Acerra   Ramus      Alauda  Furca    Gena     Alnus

            _Third Floor._                        _Third Floor._
  Machina Lex      Omen     Artus      Fax     Venenum  Syrma    Ursa
  Ara     Vomer    Pluma    Odium      Mars    Merces   Tyro     Fama
  Proeda  Sacerdos Hydra    Luxus      Spicula Mora     Oliva    Conjux
  Cortex  Mica     Flagellum Mas       Comes   Tibicen  Vestis   Plenum

           _Second Floor._                      _Second Floor._
  Ardor   Rupes    Pallas   Arista     Rostrum Armiger  Premium  Tribus
  Pilum   Glans    Colus    Pellis     Ala     Cortis   Aer      Fragor
  Ocrea   Tessara  Domitor  Fera       Uncus   Pallor   Tergum   Reus
  Cardo   Cudo     Malleus  Thorax     Ostrum  Bidens   Scena    Torus

            _First Floor._                       _First Floor._
  Regina  Canis    Marmor   Tectum     Pardus  Rubor    Nurus    Hospes
  Agmen   Lacus    Arvus    Rumor      Sector  Hama     Remus    Fortuna
  Crates  Cura     Limen    Vita       Frenum  Plebs    Sypho    Myrrha
  Thyrsus Vitta    Sceptrum Pax        Urna    Moles    Saltus   Acus


APPENDIX D.

The following list gives the colours, and the various uses for them.
They have already been used in the foregoing pages to distinguish the
various regions of the Tessaract, and the different individual cubes or
Tessaracts in a block. The other use suggested in the last column of the
list has not been discussed; but it is believed that it may afford great
aid to the mind in amassing, handling, and retaining the quantities of
formulae requisite in scientific training and work.

                  _Region of    _Tessaract
    _Colour._      Tessaract._  in 81 Set._  _Symbol._
  Black              Syce         Plebs         0
  White              Mel          Mora          1
  Vermilion          Alvus        Uncus         2
  Orange             Cuspis       Moles         3
  Light-yellow       Murex        Cortis        4
  Bright-green       Lappa        Penates       5
  Bright-blue        Iter         Oliva         6
  Light-grey         Lares        Tigris        7
  Indian-red         Crux         Orcus         8
  Yellow-ochre       Sal          Testudo       9
  Buff               Cista        Sector        + (plus)
  Wood               Tessaract    Tessara       - (minus)
  Brown-green        Tholus       Troja         ± (plus or minus)
  Sage-green         Margo        Lacerta       × (multiplied by)
  Reddish            Callis       Tibicen       ÷ (divided by)
  Chocolate          Velum        Sacerdos      = (equal to)
  French-grey        Far          Scena         ≠ (not equal to)
  Brown              Arctos       Ostrum        > (greater than)
  Dark-slate         Daps         Aer           < (less than)
  Dun                Portica      Clipeus       ∶ }    signs
  Orange-vermilion   Talus        Portio        ∷ } of proportion
  Stone              Ops          Thyrsus       · (decimal point)
  Quaker-green       Felis        Axis          ∟ (factorial)
  Leaden             Semita       Merces        ∥ (parallel)
  Dull-green         Mappa        Vulcan        ∦ (not parallel)
  Indigo             Lixa         Postis        π⁄2 (90°) (at right
                                                angles)
  Dull-blue          Pagus        Verbum        log. base 10
  Dark-purple        Mensura      Nepos         sin. (sine)
  Pale-pink          Vena         Tabula        cos. (cosine)
  Dark-blue          Moena        Bidens        tan. (tangent)
  Earthen            Mugil        Angusta       ∞ (infinity)
  Blue               Dos          Frenum        a
  Terracotta         Crus         Remus         b
  Oak                Idus         Domitor       c
  Yellow             Pagina       Cardo         d
  Green              Bucina       Ala           e
  Rose               Olla         Limen         f
  Emerald            Orsa         Ara           g
  Red                Olus         Mars          h
  Sea-green          Libera       Pluma         i
  Salmon             Tela         Glans         j
  Pale-yellow        Livor        Ovis          k
  Purple-brown       Opex         Polus         l
  Deep-crimson       Camoena      Pilum         m
  Blue-green         Proes        Tergum        n
  Light-brown        Lua          Crates        o
  Deep-blue          Lama         Tyro          p
  Brick-red          Lar          Cura          q
  Magenta            Offex        Arvus         r
  Green-grey         Cadus        Hama          s
  Light-red          Croeta       Praeda        t
  Azure              Lotus        Vitta         u
  Pale-green         Vesper       Ocrea         v
  Blue-tint          Panax        Telum         w
  Yellow-green       Pactum       Malleus       x
  Deep-green         Mango        Vomer         y
  Light-green        Lis          Agmen         z
  Light-blue         Ilex         Comes         α
  Crimson            Bolus        Sypho         β
  Ochre              Limbus       Mica          γ
  Purple             Solia        Arcus         δ
  Leaf-green         Luca         Securis       ε
  Turquoise          Ancilla      Vinculum      ζ
  Dark-grey          Orca         Colus         η
  Fawn               Nugæ         Saltus        θ
  Smoke              Limus        Sceptrum      ι
  Light-buff         Mala         Pallor        κ
  Dull-purple        Sors         Vestis        λ
  Rich-red           Lucta        Cortex        μ
  Green-blue         Pator        Flagellum     ν
  Burnt-sienna       Silex        Luctus        ξ
  Sea-blue           Lorica       Lacus         ο
  Peacock-blue       Passer       Aries         π
  Deep-brown         Meatus       Hydra         ρ
  Dark-pink          Onager       Anguis        σ
  Dark               Lensa        Laurus        τ
  Dark-stone         Pluvium      Cudo          υ
  Silver             Spira        Cervix        φ
  Gold               Corvus       Urna          χ
  Deep-yellow        Via          Spicula       ψ
  Dark-green         Calor        Segmen        ω


APPENDIX E.

A THEOREM IN FOUR-SPACE.

If a pyramid on a triangular base be cut by a plane which passes through
the three sides of the pyramid in such manner that the sides of the
sectional triangle are not parallel to the corresponding sides of the
triangle of the base; then the sides of these two triangles, if produced
in pairs, will meet in three points which are in a straight line,
namely, the line of intersection of the sectional plane and the plane of
the base.

Let A B C D be a pyramid on a triangular base A B C, and let a b c be a
section such that A B, B C, A C, are respectively not parallel to a b,
b c, a c. It must be understood that a is a point on A D, b is a point
on B D, and c a point on C D. Let, A B and a b, produced, meet in m. B C
and b c, produced, meet in n; and A C and a c, produced, meet in o.
These three points, m, n, o, are in the line of intersection of the two
planes A B C and a b c.

Now, let the line a b be projected on to the plane of the base, by
drawing lines from a and b at right angles to the base, and meeting it
in a′ b′; the line a′ b′, produced, will meet A B produced in m. If the
lines b c and a c be projected in the same way on to the base, to the
points b′ c′ and a′ c′; then B C and b′ c′ produced, will meet in n, and
A C and a′ c′ produced, will meet in o. The two triangles A B C and
a′ b′ c′ are such, that the lines joining A to a′, B to b′, and C to c′,
will, if produced, meet in a point, namely, the point on the base A B C
which is the projection of D. Any two triangles which fulfil this
condition are the possible base and projection of the section of a
pyramid; therefore the sides of such triangles, if produced in pairs,
will meet (if they are not parallel) in three points which lie in one
straight line.

A four-dimensional pyramid may be defined as a figure bounded by a
polyhedron of any number of sides, and the same number of pyramids whose
bases are the sides of the polyhedron, and whose apices meet in a point
not in the space of the base.

If a four-dimensional pyramid on a tetrahedral base be cut by a space
which passes through the four sides of the pyramid in such a way that
the sides of the sectional figure be not parallel to the sides of the
base; then the sides of these two tetrahedra, if produced in pairs, will
meet in lines which all lie in one plane, namely, the plane of
intersection of the space of the base and the space of the section.

If now the sectional tetrahedron be projected on to the base (by drawing
lines from each point of the section to the base at right angles to it),
there will be two tetrahedra fulfilling the condition that the line
joining the angles of the one to the angles of the other will, if
produced, meet in a point, which point is the projection of the apex of
the four-dimensional pyramid.

Any two tetrahedra which fulfil this condition, are the possible base
and projection of a section of a four-dimensional pyramid. Therefore, in
any two such tetrahedra, where the sides of the one are not parallel to
the sides of the other, the sides, if produced in pairs (one side of the
one with one side of the other), will meet in four straight lines which
are all in one plane.


APPENDIX F.


EXERCISES ON SHAPES OF THREE DIMENSIONS.

The names used are those given in Appendix B.

Find the shapes from the following projections:

  1. Syce projections: Ratis, Caput, Castrum, Plagua.

  Alvus projections: Merum, Oculus, Fulmen, Pruinus.

  Moena projections: Miles, Ventus, Navis.

  2. Syce: Dies, Tuba, Lituus, Frons.

  Alvus: Sagitta, Regnum, Tellus, Fulmen, Pruinus.

  Moena: Tibia, Tunica, Robur, Finis.

  3. Syce: Nemus, Sidus, Vertex, Nix, Cerva.

  Alvus: Lignum, Haedus, Vultus, Nemus, Humerus.

  Moena: Dexter, Princeps, Equus, Dux, Urbs, Pullis, Gens, Monstrum,
  Miles.

  4. Syce: Amphora, Castrum, Myrtus, Rota, Palma, Meta, Trabs, Ratis.

  Alvus: Dexter, Princeps, Moena, Aes, Merum, Oculus, Littus, Civis,
  Fulmen.

  Moena: Gens, Ventus, Navis, Finis, Monstrum, Cursus.

  5. Syce: Castrum, Plagua, Nix, Vertex, Aper, Caput, Cerva, Venator.

  Alvus: Triumphus, Tellus, Caterva, Lignum, Haedus, Pruinus, Fulmen,
  Civis, Humerus, Vultus.

  Moena: Pharetra, Cursus, Miles, Equus, Dux, Navis, Monstrum, Gens,
  Urbs, Dexter.


ANSWERS.

The shapes are:

  1. Umbra, Aether, Ver, Carina, Flos.

  2. Pontus, Custos, Jaculum, Pratum, Arator, Agna.

  3. Focus, Omus, Haedus, Tabema, Vultus, Hostis, Figura, Ales, Sidus,
  Augur.

  4. Tempus, Campus, Finis, Navis, Ventus, Pelagus, Notus, Cohors,
  Aether, Carina, Res, Templum, Rex, Gens, Monstrum.

  5. Portus, Arma, Sylva, Lucrum, Ornus, Onus, Os, Facies, Chorus,
  Carina, Flos, Nox, Ales, Clamor, Res, Pugna, Ludus, Figura, Augur,
  Humerus.


FURTHER EXERCISES IN SHAPES OF THREE DIMENSIONS.

The Names used are those given in Appendix C; and this set of exercises
forms a preparation for their use in space of four dimensions. All are
in the 27 Block (Urna to Syrma).

  1. Syce: Moles, Frenum, Plebs, Sypho.

  Alvus: Urna, Frenum, Uncus, Spicula, Comes.

  Moena: Moles, Bidens, Tibicen, Comes, Saltus.

  2. Syce: Urna, Moles, Plebs, Hama, Remus.

  Alvus: Urna, Frenum, Sector, Ala, Mars.

  Moena: Urna, Moles, Saltus, Bidens, Tibicen.

  3. Syce: Moles, Plebs, Hama, Remus.

  Alvus: Uma, Ostrum, Comes, Spicula, Frenum, Sector.

  Moena: Moles, Saltus, Bidens, Tibicen.

  4. Syce: Frenum, Plebs, Sypho, Moles, Hama.

  Alvus: Urna, Frenum, Uncus, Sector, Spicula.

  Moena: Urna, Moles, Saltus, Scena, Vestis.

  5. Syce: Urna, Moles, Plebs, Hama, Remus, Sector.

  Alvus: Urna, Frenum, Sector, Uncus, Spicula, Comes, Mars.

  Moena: Urna, Moles, Saltus, Bidens, Tibicen, Comes.

  6. Syce: Uma, Moles, Saltus, Sypho, Remus, Hama, Sector.

  Alvus: Comes, Ostrum, Uncus, Spicula, Mars, Ala, Sector.

  Moena: Urna, Moles, Saltus, Scena, Vestis, Tibicen, Comes, Ostrum.

  7. Syce: Sypho, Saltus, Moles, Urna, Frenum, Sector.

  Alvus: Urna, Frenum, Uncus, Spicula, Mars.

  Moena: Saltus, Moles, Urna, Ostrum, Comes.

  8. Syce: Moles, Plebs, Hama, Sector.

  Alvus: Ostrum, Frenum, Uncus, Spicula, Mars, Ala.

  Moena: Moles, Bidens, Tibicen, Ostrum.

  9. Syce: Moles, Saltus, Sypho, Plebs, Frenum, Sector.

  Alvus: Ostrum, Comes, Spicula, Mars, Ala.

  Moena: Ostrum, Comes, Tibicen, Bidens, Scena, Vestis.

  10. Syce: Urna, Moles, Saltus, Sypho, Remus, Sector, Frenum.

  Alvus: Urna, Ostrum, Comes, Spicula, Mars, Ala, Sector.

  Moena: Urna, Ostrum, Comes, Tibicen, Vestis, Scena, Saltus.

  11. Syce: Frenum, Plebs, Sypho, Hama.

  Alvus: Frenum, Sector, Ala, Mars, Spicula.

  Moena: Urna, Moles, Saltus, Bidens, Tibicen.


ANSWERS.

The shapes are:

  1. Moles, Plebs, Sypho, Pallor, Mora, Tibicen, Spicula.

  2. Urna, Moles, Plebs, Hama, Cortis, Merces, Remus.

  3. Moles, Bidens, Tibicen, Mora, Plebs, Hama, Remus.

  4. Frenum, Plebs, Sypho, Tergum, Oliva, Moles, Hama.

  5. Urna, Moles, Plebs, Hama, Remus, Pallor, Mora, Tibicen, Mars,
  Merces, Comes, Sector.

  6. Ostrum, Comes, Tibicen, Vestis, Scena, Tergum, Oliva, Tyro, Aer,
  Remus, Hama, Sector, Merces, Mars, Ala.

  7. Sypho, Saltus, Moles, Urna, Frenum, Uncus, Spicula, Mars.

  8. Plebs, Pallor, Mora, Bidens, Merces, Cortis, Ala.

  9. Bidens, Tibicen, Vestis, Scena, Oliva, Mora, Spicula, Mars, Ala.

  10. Urna, Ostrum, Comes, Spicula, Mars, Tibicen, Vestis, Oliva, Tyro,
  Aer, Remus, Sector, Ala, Saltus, Scena.

  11. Frenum, Plebs, Sypho, Hama, Cortis, Merces, Mora.


APPENDIX G.


EXERCISES ON SHAPES OF FOUR DIMENSIONS.

The Names used are those given in Appendix C. The first six exercises
are in the 81 Set, and the rest in the 256 Set.

  1. Mala projection: Urna, Moles, Plebs, Pallor, Cortis, Merces.

  Lar projection: Urna, Moles, Plebs, Cura, Penates, Nepos.

  Pluvium projection: Urna, Moles, Vitta, Cudo, Luctus, Troja.

  Vesper projection: Urna, Frenum, Crates, Ocrea, Orcus, Postis, Arcus.

  2. Mala: Urna, Frenum, Uncus, Pallor, Cortis, Aer.

  Lar: Urna, Frenum, Crates, Cura, Lacus, Arvus, Angusta.

  Pluvium: Urna, Thyrsus, Cardo, Cudo, Malleus, Anguis.

  Vesper: Urna, Frenum, Crates, Ocrea, Pilum, Postis.

  3. Mala: Comes, Tibicen, Mora, Pallor.

  Lar: Urna, Moles, Vitta, Cura, Penates.

  Pluvium: Comes, Tibicen, Mica, Troja, Luctus.

  Vesper: Comes, Cortex, Praeda, Laurus, Orcus.

  4. Mala: Vestis, Oliva, Tyro.

  Lar: Saltus, Sypho, Remus, Arvus, Angusta.

  Pluvium: Vestis, Flagellum, Aries.

  Vesper: Comes, Spicula, Mars, Ara, Arcus.

  5. Mala: Mars, Merces, Tyro, Aer, Tergum, Pallor, Plebs.

  Lar: Sector, Hama, Lacus, Nepos, Angusta, Vulcan, Penates.

  Pluvium: Comes, Tibicen, Mica, Troja, Aries, Anguis, Luctus, Securis.

  Vesper: Mars, Ara, Arcus, Postis, Orcus, Polus.

  6. Mala: Pallor, Mora, Oliva, Tyro, Merces, Mars, Spicula, Comes,
  Tibicen, Vestis.

  Lar: Plebs, Cura, Penates, Vulcan, Angusta, Nepos, Telum, Polus,
  Cervix, Securis, Vinculum.

  Pluvium: Bidens, Cudo, Luctus, Troja, Axis, Aries.

  Vesper: Uncus, Ocrea, Orcus, Laurus, Arcus, Axis.

  7. Mala: Hospes, Tribus, Fragor, Aer, Tyro, Mora, Oliva.

  Lar: Hospes, Tectum, Rumor, Arvus, Angusta, Cera, Apis, Lapis.

  Pluvium: Acus, Torus, Malleus, Flagellum, Thorax, Aries, Aestas,
  Capella.

  Vesper: Pardus, Rostrum, Ardor, Pilum, Ara, Arcus, Aestus, Septum.

  8. Mala: Pallor, Tergum, Aer, Tyro, Cortis, Syrma, Ursa, Fama, Naxos,
  Erisma.

  Lar: Plebs, Cura, Limen, Vulcan, Angusta, Nepos, Cera, Papaver,
  Pignus, Messor.

  Pluvium: Bidens, Cudo, Malleus, Anguis, Aries, Luctus, Capella, Rheda,
  Rapina.

  Vesper: Uncus, Ocrea, Orcus, Postis, Arcus, Aestus, Cussis, Dolium,
  Alexis.

  9. Mala: Fama, Conjux, Reus, Torus, Acus, Myrrha, Sypho, Plebs,
  Pallor, Mora, Oliva, Alpis, Acies, Hircus.

  Lar: Missale, Fortuna, Vita, Pax, Furor, Ira, Vulcan, Penates, Lapis,
  Apis, Cera, Pignus.

  Pluvium: Torus, Plenum, Pax, Thorax, Dolus, Furor, Vinculum, Securis,
  Clavis, Gurges, Aestas, Capella, Corbis.

  Vesper: Uncus, Spicula, Mars, Ocrea, Cardo, Thyrsus, Cervix, Verbum,
  Orcus, Polus, Spes, Senex, Septum, Porrum, Cussis, Dolium.


ANSWERS.

The shapes are:

  1. Urna, Moles, Plebs, Cura, Tessara, Lacerta, Clipeus, Ovis.

  2. Urna, Frenum, Crates, Ocrea, Tessara, Glans, Colus, Tabula.

  3. Comes, Tibicen, Mica, Sacerdos, Tigris, Lacerta.

  4. Vestis, Oliva, Tyro, Pluma, Portio.

  5. Mars, Merces, Vomer, Ovis, Portio, Tabula, Testudo, Lacerta,
  Penates.

  6. Pallor, Tessara, Lacerta, Tigris, Segmen, Portio, Ovis, Arcus,
  Laurus, Axis, Troja, Aries.

  7. Hospes, Tribus, Arista, Pellis, Colus, Pluma, Portio, Calathus,
  Turtur, Sepes.

  8. Pallor, Tessara, Domitor, Testudo, Tabula, Clipeus, Portio,
  Calathus, Nux, Lectrum, Corymbus, Circaea, Cordax.

  9. Fama, Conjux, Reus, Fera, Thorax, Pax, Furor, Dolus, Scala, Ira,
  Vulcan, Penates, Lapis, Palus, Sepes, Turtur, Diota, Drachma, Python.


APPENDIX H.


SECTIONS OF CUBE AND TESSARACT.

There are three kinds of sections of a cube.

1. The sectional plane, which is in all cases supposed to be infinite,
can be taken parallel to two of the opposite faces of the cube; that is,
parallel to two of the lines meeting in Corvus, and cutting the third.

2. The sectional plane can be taken parallel to one of the lines meeting
in Corvus and cutting the other two, or one or both of them produced.

3. The sectional plane can be taken cutting all three lines, or any or
all of them produced.

Take the first case, and suppose the plane cuts Dos half-way between
Corvus and Cista. Since it does not cut Arctos or Cuspis, or either of
them produced, it will cut Via, Iter, and Bolus at the middle point of
each; and the figure, determined by the intersection of the Plane and
Mala, is a square. If the length of the edge of the cube be taken as the
unit, this figure may be expressed thus:

  Z   X    Y
  0 . 0 . ¹⁄₂

showing that the Z and X lines from Corvus are not cut at all, and that
the Y line is cut at half-a-unit from Corvus.

Sections taken

  Z   X    Y
  0 . 0 . ¹⁄₄

and

  Z   X   Y
  0 . 0 . 1

would also be squares.

Take the second case.

Let the plane cut Cuspis and Dos, each at half-a-unit from Corvus, and
not cut Arctos or Arctos produced; it will also cut through the middle
points of Via and Callis. The figure produced, is a rectangle which has
two sides of one unit, and the other two are each the diagonal of a
half-unit squared.

If the plane cuts Cuspis and Dos, each at one unit from Corvus, and is
parallel to Arctos, the figure will be a rectangle which has two sides
of one unit in length; and the other two the diagonal of one unit
squared.

If the plane passes through Mala, cutting Dos produced and Cuspis
produced, each at one-and-a-half unit from Corvus, and is parallel to
Arctos, the figure will be a parallelogram like the one obtained by the
section

  Z    X     Y
  0 . ¹⁄₂ . ¹⁄₂.

This set of figures will be expressed

  Z    X     Y     Z   X   Y    Z     X      Y
  0 . ¹⁄₂ . ¹⁄₂    0 . 1 . 1    0 . 1¹⁄₂ . 1¹⁄₂

It will be seen that these sections are parallel to each other; and that
in each figure Cuspis and Dos are cut at equal distances from Corvus.

We may express the whole set thus:--

  Z   X   Y
  O . I . I

it being understood that where Roman figures are used, the numbers do
not refer to the length of unit cut off any given line from Corvus, but
to the proportion between the lengths. Thus

  Z   X    Y
  O . I . II

means that Arctos is not cut at all, and that Cuspis and Dos are cut,
Dos being cut twice as far from Corvus as is Cuspis.

These figures will also be rectangles.

Take the third case.

Suppose Arctos, Cuspis, and Dos are each cut half-way. This figure is an
equilateral triangle, whose sides are the diagonal of a half-unit
squared. The figure

  Z   X   Y
  1 . 1 . 1

is also an equilateral triangle, and the figure

    Z      X      Y
  1¹⁄₂ . 1¹⁄₂ . 1¹⁄₂

is an equilateral hexagon.

It is easy for us to see what these shapes are, and also, what the
figures of any other set would be, as

  Z    X    Y
  I . II . II

or

  Z    X    Y
  I . II . III

but we must learn them as a two-dimensional being would, so that we may
see how to learn the three-dimensional sections of a tessaract.

It is evident that the resulting figures are the same whether we fix the
cube, and then turn the sectional plane to the required position, or
whether we fix the sectional plane, and then turn the cube. Thus, in the
first case we might have fixed the plane, and then so placed the cube
that one plane side coincided with the sectional plane, and then have
drawn the cube half-way through, in a direction at right angles to the
plane, when we should have seen the square first mentioned. In the
second case

  (Z   X   Y)
  (O . I . I)

we might have put the cube with Arctos coinciding with the plane and
with Cuspis and Dos equally inclined to it, and then have drawn the cube
through the plane at right angles to it until the lines (Cuspis and Dos)
were cut at the required distances from Corvus. In the third case we
might have put the cube with only Corvus coinciding with the plane and
with Cuspis, Dos, and Arctos equally inclined to it (for any of the
shapes in the set

  Z   X   Y)
  I . I . I)

and then have drawn it through as before. The resulting figures are
exactly the same as those we got before; but this way is the best to
use, as it would probably be easier for a two-dimensional being to think
of a cube passing through his space than to imagine his whole space
turned round, with regard to the cube.

We have already seen (p. 117) how a two-dimensional being would observe
the sections of a cube when it is put with one plane side coinciding
with his space, and is then drawn partly through.

Now, suppose the cube put with the line Arctos coinciding with his
space, and the lines Cuspis and Dos equally inclined to it. At first he
would only see Arctos. If the cube were moved until Dos and Cuspis were
each cut half-way, Arctos still being parallel to the plane, Arctos
would disappear at once; and to find out what he would see he would have
to take the square sections of the cube, and find on each of them what
lines are given by the new set of sections. Thus he would take Moena
itself, which may be regarded as the first section of the square set.
One point of the figure would be the middle point of Cuspis, and since
the sectional plane is parallel to Arctos, the line of intersection of
Moena with the sectional plane will be parallel to Arctos. The required
line then cuts Cuspis half-way, and is parallel to Arctos, therefore it
cuts Callis half-way.

[Illustration: Fig. 21.]

Next he would take the square section half-way between Moena and Murex.
He knows that the line Alvus of this section is parallel to Arctos, and
that the point Dos at one of its ends is half-way between Corvus and
Cista, so that this line itself is the one he wants (because the
sectional plane cuts Dos half-way between Corvus and Cista, and is
parallel to Arctos). In Fig. 21 the two lines thus found are shown. a b
is the line in Moena, and c d the line in the section. He must now find
out how far apart they are. He knows that from the middle point of
Cuspis to Corvus is half-a-unit, and from the middle point of Dos to
Corvus is half-a-unit, and Cuspis and Dos are at right angles to each
other; therefore from the middle point of Cuspis to the middle point of
Dos is the diagonal of a square whose sides are half-a-unit in length.
This diagonal may be written d (¹⁄₂)². He would also see that from the
middle point of Callis to the middle point of Via is the same length;
therefore the figure is a parallelogram, having two of its sides, each
one unit in length, and the other two each d (¹⁄₂)².

He could also see that the angles are right, because the lines a c and
b d are made up of the X and Y directions, and the other two, a b and
d, are purely Z, and since they have no tendency in common, they are at
right angles to each other.

[Illustration: Fig. 22.]

If he wanted the figure made by

  Z     X      Y
  0 . 1¹⁄₂ . 1¹⁄₂

it would be a little more difficult. He would have to take Moena, a
section halfway between Moena and Murex, Murex and another square which
he would have to regard as an _imaginary_ section half-a-unit further Y
than Murex (Fig. 22). He might now draw a ground plan of the sections;
that is, he would draw Syce, and produce Cuspis and Dos half-a-unit
beyond Nugæ and Cista. He would see that Cadus and Bolus would be cut
half-way, so that in the half-way section he would have the point a
(Fig. 23), and in Murex the point c. In the imaginary section he would
have g; but this he might disregard, since the cube goes no further than
Murex. From the points c and a there would be lines going Z, so that
Iter and Semita would be cut half-way.

[Illustration: _Groundplan of Sections shown in Fig. 22._

Fig. 23.]

He could find out how far the two lines a b and c d (Fig. 22) are apart
by referring d and b to Lama, and a and c to Crus.

In taking the third order of sections, a similar method may be followed.

[Illustration: Fig. 24.]

Suppose the sectional plane to cut Cuspis, Dos, and Arctos, each at one
unit from Corvus. He would first take Moena, and as the sectional plane
passes through Ilex and Nugæ, the line on Moena would be the diagonal
passing through these two points. Then he would take Murex, and he would
see that as the plane cuts Dos at one unit from Corvus, all he would
have is the point Cista. So the whole figure is the Ilex to Nugæ
diagonal, and the point Cista.

Now Cista and Ilex are each one inch from Corvus, and measured along
lines at right angles to each other; therefore, they are d (1)² from
each other. By referring Nugæ and Cista to Corvus he would find that
they are also d (1)² apart; therefore the figure is an equilateral
triangle, whose sides are each d (1)².

Suppose the sectional plane to pass through Mala, cutting Cuspis, Dos,
and Arctos each at unit from Corvus. To find the figure, the plane-being
would have to take Moena, a section half-way between Moena and Murex,
Murex, and an imaginary section half-a-unit beyond Murex (Fig. 24). He
would produce Arctos and Cuspis to points half-a-unit from Ilex and
Nugæ, and by joining these points, he would see that the line passes
through the middle points of Callis and Far (a, b, Fig. 24). In the last
square, the imaginary section, there would be the point m; for this is
1¹⁄₂ unit from Corvus measured along Dos produced. There would also be
lines in the other two squares, the section and Murex, and to find these
he would have to make many observations. He found the points a and b
(Fig. 24) by drawing a line from r to s, r and s being each 1¹⁄₂ unit
from Corvus, and simply seeing that it cut Callis and Far at the middle
point of each. He might now imagine a cube Mala turned about Arctos, so
that Alvus came into his plane; he might then produce Arctos and Dos
until they were each unit long, and join their extremities, when he
would see that Via and Bucina are each cut half-way. Again, by turning
Syce into his plane, and producing Dos and Cuspis to points 1¹⁄₂ unit
from Corvus and joining the points, he would see that Bolus and Cadus
are cut half-way. He has now determined six points on Mala, through
which the plane passes, and by referring them in pairs to Ilex, Olus,
Cista, Crus, Nugæ, Sors, he would find that each was d (¹⁄₂)² from the
next; so he would know that the figure is an equilateral hexagon. The
angles he would not have got in this observation, and they might be a
serious difficulty to him. It should be observed that a similar
difficulty does not come to us in our observation of the sections of a
tessaract: for, if the angles of each side of a solid figure are
determined, the solid angles are also determined.

There is another, and in some respects a better, way by which he might
have found the sides of this figure. If he had noticed his plane-space
much, he would have found out that, if a line be drawn to cut two other
lines which meet, the ratio of the parts of the two lines cut off by the
first line, on the side of the angle, is the same for those lines, and
any other two that are parallel to them. Thus, if a b and a c (Fig. 25)
meet, making an angle at a, and b c crosses them, and also crosses a′ b′
and a′ c′, these last two being parallel to a b and a c, then a b ∶
a c ∷ a′ b′ ∶ a′ c′.

[Illustration: Fig. 25]

If the plane-being knew this, he would rightly assume that if three
lines meet, making a solid angle, and a plane passes through them, the
ratio of the parts between the plane and the angle is the same for those
three lines, and for any other three parallel to them.

In the case we are dealing with he knows that from Ilex to the point on
Arctos produced where the plane cuts, it is half-a-unit; and as the Z,
X, and Y lines are cut equally from Corvus, he would conclude that the X
and Y lines are cut the same distance from Ilex as the Z line, that is
half-a-unit. He knows that the X line is cut at 1¹⁄₂ units from Corvus;
that is, half-a-unit from Nugæ: so he would conclude that the Z and Y
lines are cut half-a-unit from Nugæ. He would also see that the Z and X
lines from Cista are cut at half-a-unit. He has now six points on the
cube, the middle points of Callis, Via, Bucina, Cadus, Bolus, and Far.
Now, looking at his square sections, he would see on Moena a line going
from middle of Far to middle of Callis, that is, a line d (¹⁄₂)² long.
On the section he would see a line from middle of Via to middle of Bolus
d (1)² long, and on Murex he would see a line from middle of Cadus to
middle of Bucina, d (¹⁄₂)² long. Of these three lines a b, c d, e f,
(Fig. 24)--a b and e f are sides, and c d is a section of the required
figure. He can find the distances between a and c by reference to
Ilex, between b and d by reference to Nugæ, between c and e by reference
to Olus, and between d and f by reference to Crus; and he will find that
these distances are each d (¹⁄₂)².

Thus, he would know that the figure is an equilateral hexagon with its
sides d (¹⁄₂)² long, of which two of the opposite points (c and d) are d
(1)² apart, and the only figure fulfilling all these conditions is an
equilateral and equiangular hexagon.

Enough has been said about sections of a cube, to show how a plane-being
would find the shapes in any set as in

  Z    X    Y
  I . II . II

or

  Z   X    Y
  I . I . II.

He would always have to bear in mind that the ratio of the lengths of
the Z, X, and Y lines is the same from Corvus to the sectional plane as
from any other point to the sectional plane. Thus, if he were taking a
section where the plane cuts Arctos and Cuspis at one unit from Corvus
and Dos at one-and-a-half, that is where the ratio of Z and of X to Y is
as two to three, he would see that Dos itself is not cut at all; but
from Cista to the point on Dos produced is half-a-unit; therefore from
Cista, the Z and X lines will be cut at ²⁄₃ of ¹⁄₂ unit from Cista.

It is impossible in writing to show how to make the various sections of
a tessaract; and even if it were not so, it would be unadvisable; for
the value of doing it is not in seeing the shapes themselves, so much as
in the concentration of the mind on the tessaract involved in the
process of finding them out.

Any one who wishes to make them should go carefully over the sections of
a cube, not looking at them as he himself can see them, or determining
them as he, with his three-dimensional conceptions, can; but he must
limit his imagination to two dimensions, and work through the problems
which a plane-being would have to work through, although to his higher
mind they may be self-evident. Thus a three-dimensional being can see at
a glance, that if a sectional plane passes through a cube at one unit
each way from Corvus, the resulting figure is an equilateral triangle.

If he wished to prove it, he would show that the three bounding lines
are the diagonals of equal squares. This is all a two-dimensional being
would have to do; but it is not so evident to him that two of the lines
are the diagonals of squares.

Moreover, when the figure is drawn, we can look at it from a point
outside the plane of the figure, and can thus see it all at once; but
he who has to look at it from a point in the plane can only see an edge
at a time, or he might see two edges in perspective together.

Then there are certain suppositions he has to make. For instance, he
knows that two points determine a line, and he assumes that three points
determine a plane, although he cannot conceive any other plane than the
one in which he exists. We assume that four points determine a solid
space. Or rather, we say that _if_ this supposition, together with
certain others of a like nature, are true, we can find all the sections
of a tessaract, and of other four-dimensional figures by an infinite
solid.

When any difficulty arises in taking the sections of a tessaract, the
surest way of overcoming it is to suppose a similar difficulty occurring
to a two-dimensional being in taking the sections of a cube, and, step
by step, to follow the solution he might obtain, and then to apply the
same or similar principles to the case in point.

A few figures are given, which, if cut out and folded along the lines,
will show some of the sections of a tessaract. But the reader is
earnestly begged not to be content with _looking_ at the shapes only.
That will teach him nothing about a tessaract, or four-dimensional
space, and will only tend to produce in his mind a feeling that “the
fourth dimension” is an unknown and unthinkable region, in which any
shapes may be right, as given sections of its figures, and of which any
statement may be true. While, in fact, if it is the case that the laws
of spaces of two and three dimensions may, with truth, be carried on
into space of four dimensions; then the little our solidity (like the
flatness of a plane-being) will allow us to learn of these shapes and
relations, is no more a matter of doubt to us than what we learn of two-
and three-dimensional shapes and relations.

There are given also sections of an octa-tessaract, and of a
tetra-tessaract, the equivalents in four-space of an octahedron and
tetrahedron.

A tetrahedron may be regarded as a cube with every alternate corner cut
off. Thus, if Mala have the corner towards Corvus cut off as far as the
points Ilex, Nugæ, Cista, and the corner towards Sors cut off as far as
Ilex, Nugæ, Lama, and the corner towards Crus cut off as far as Lama,
Nugæ, Cista, and the corner towards Olus cut off as far as Ilex, Lama,
Cista, what is left of the cube is a tetrahedron, whose angles are at
the points Ilex, Nugæ, Cista, Lama. In a similar manner, if every
alternate corner of a tessaract be cut off, the figure that is left is a
tetra-tessaract, which is a figure bounded by sixteen regular
tetrahedrons.

[Illustration: (i)

Fig. 26.

Fig. 27.

Fig. 27.

Fig. 26.]

[Illustration: (ii)

Fig. 28.

Fig. 29.

Fig. 30.]

[Illustration: (iii)

Fig. 31.

Fig. 32.]

[Illustration: (iv)

Fig. 33.

Fig. 34.

Fig. 35.]

[Illustration: (v)

Fig. 36.

Fig. 37.

Fig. 38.]

[Illustration: (vi)

Fig. 39.

Fig. 40.

Fig. 41.]

The octa-tessaract is got by cutting off every corner of the tessaract.
If every corner of a cube is cut off, the figure left is an octa-hedron,
whose angles are at the middle points of the sides. The angles of the
octa-tessaract are at the middle points of its plane sides. A careful
study of a tetra-hedron and an octa-hedron as they are cut out of a cube
will be the best preparation for the study of these four-dimensional
figures. It will be seen that there is much to learn of them, as--How
many planes and lines there are in each, How many solid sides there are
round a point in each.


A DESCRIPTION OF FIGURES 26 TO 41.

                                              Z      X     Y       W
  Z   X   Y   W    {26 is a section taken     1   .  1   .  1   .  1
  I . I . I . I    {27   „    „    „         1¹⁄₂ . 1¹⁄₂ . 1¹⁄₂ . 1¹⁄₂
                   {28   „    „   „           2   .  2   .  2   .  2

                                              Z      X      Y      W
  Z     X    Y   W {29 is a section taken     1   .  1   .  1   . ¹⁄₂
  II . II . II . I {30   „    „    „         1¹⁄₂ . 1¹⁄₂ . 1¹⁄₂ . ³⁄₄
                   {31   „    „    „          2   .  2   .  2   .  1
                    32   „    „    „         2¹⁄₂ . 2¹⁄₂ . 2¹⁄₂ . 1¹⁄₄

The above are sections of a tessaract. Figures 33 to 35 are of a
tetra-tessaract. The tetra-tessaract is supposed to be imbedded in a
tessaract, and the sections are taken through it, cutting the Z, X and Y
lines equally, and corresponding to the figures given of the sections of
the tessaract.

Figures 36, 37, and 38 are similar sections of an octa-tessaract.

Figures 39, 40, and 41 are the following sections of a tessaract.

                                              Z      X      Y      W
  Z   X   Y   W  {39 is a section taken       0   . ¹⁄₂  .  ¹⁄₂  .  ¹⁄₂
  O . I . I . I  {40  „    „    „             0   .  1   .  1   .  1
                 {41  „    „    „             0   . 1¹⁄₂ . 1¹⁄₂  . 1¹⁄₂

It is clear that there are four orders of sections of every
four-dimensional figure; namely, those beginning with a solid, those
beginning with a plane, those beginning with a line, and those beginning
with a point. There should be little difficulty in finding them, if the
sections of a cube with a tetra-hedron, or an octa-hedron enclosed in
it, are carefully examined.


APPENDIX K.

[Illustration: MODEL 1. MALA.]

  COLOURS: MALA, LIGHT-BUFF.

  _Points_: Corvus, Gold. Nugæ, Fawn. Crus, Terra-cotta. Cista, Buff.
  Ilex, Light-blue. Sors, Dull-purple. Lama, Deep-blue. Olus, Red.

  _Lines_: Cuspis, Orange. Bolus, Crimson. Cadus, Green-grey. Dos, Blue.
  Arctos, Brown. Far, French-grey. Daps, Dark-slate. Bucina, Green.
  Callis, Reddish. Iter, Bright-blue. Semita, Leaden. Via, Deep-yellow.

  _Surfaces_: Moena, Dark-blue. Proes, Blue-green. Murex, Light-yellow.
  Alvus, Vermilion. Mel, White. Syce, Black.

[Illustration: MODEL 2. MARGO.]

  COLOURS: MARGO, SAGE-GREEN.

  _Points_: Spira, Silver. Ancilla, Turquoise. Mugil, Earthen. Panax,
  Blue-tint. Felis, Quaker-green. Passer, Peacock-blue. Talus,
  Orange-vermilion. Solia, Purple.

  _Lines_: Luca, Leaf-green. Mappa, Dull-green. Mensura, Dark-purple.
  Opex, Purple-brown. Pagus, Dull-blue. Onager, Dark-pink. Vena,
  Pale-pink. Lixa, Indigo. Tholus, Brown-green. Calor, Dark-green.
  Livor, Pale-yellow. Lensa, Dark.

  _Surfaces_: Silex, Burnt-sienna. Sal, Yellow-ochre. Portica, Dun.
  Crux, Indian-red. Lares, Light-grey. Lappa, Bright-green.

[Illustration: MODEL 3. LAR.]

  COLOURS: LAR, BRICK-RED.

  _Points_: Spira, Silver. Ancilla, Turquoise. Mugil, Earthen. Panax,
  Blue-tint. Corvus, Gold. Nugæ, Fawn. Crus, Terra-cotta. Cista, Buff.

  _Lines_: Luca, Leaf-green. Mappa, Dull-green. Mensura, Dark-purple.
  Opex, Purple-brown. Ops, Stone. Limus, Smoke. Offex, Magenta. Lis,
  Light-green. Cuspis, Orange. Bolus, Crimson. Cadus, Green-grey. Dos,
  Blue.

  _Surfaces_: Lotus, Azure. Olla, Rose. Lorica, Sea-blue. Lua,
  Bright-brown. Syce, Black. Lappa, Bright-green.

[Illustration: MODEL 4. VELUM.]

  COLOURS: VELUM, CHOCOLATE.

  _Points_: Felis, Quaker-green. Passer, Peacock-blue. Talus,
  Orange-vermilion. Solia, Purple. Ilex, Light-blue. Sors, Dull-purple.
  Lama, Deep-blue. Olus, Red.

  _Lines_: Tholus, Brown-green. Calor, Dark-green. Livor, Pale-yellow.
  Lensa, Dark. Lucta, Rich-red. Pator, Green-blue. Libera, Sea-green.
  Orsa, Emerald. Callis, Reddish. Iter, Bright-blue. Semita, Leaden.
  Via, Deep-yellow.

  _Surfaces_: Limbus, Ochre. Meatus, Deep-brown. Mango, Deep-green.
  Croeta, Light-red. Mel, White. Lares, Light-grey.

[Illustration: MODEL 5. VESPER.]

  COLOURS: VESPER, PALE-GREEN.

  _Points_: Spira, Silver. Corvus, Gold. Cista, Buff. Panax, Blue-tint.
  Felis, Quaker-green. Ilex, Light-blue. Olus, Red. Solia, Purple.

  _Lines_: Ops, Stone. Dos, Blue. Lis, Light-green. Opex, Purple-brown.
  Pagus, Dull-blue. Arctos, Brown. Bucina, Green. Lixa, Indigo. Lucta,
  Rich-red. Via, Deep-yellow. Orsa, Emerald. Lensa, Dark.

  _Surfaces_: Pagina, Yellow. Alvus, Vermilion. Camoena, Deep-crimson.
  Crux, Indian-red. Croeta, Light-red. Lua, Light-brown.

[Illustration: MODEL 6. IDUS.]

  COLOURS: IDUS, OAK.

  _Points_: Ancilla, Turquoise. Nugæ, Fawn. Crus, Terra-cotta. Mugil,
  Earthen. Passer, Peacock-blue. Sors, Dull-purple. Lama, Deep-blue.
  Talus, Orange-vermilion.

  _Lines_: Limus, Smoke. Bolus, Crimson. Offex, Magenta. Mappa,
  Dull-green. Onager, Dark-pink. Far, French-grey. Daps, Dark-slate.
  Vena, Pale-pink. Pator, Green-blue. Iter, Bright-blue. Libera,
  Sea-green. Calor, Dark-green.

  _Surfaces_: Pactum, Yellow-green. Proes, Blue-green. Orca, Dark-grey.
  Sal, Yellow-ochre. Meatus, Deep-brown. Olla, Rose.

[Illustration: MODEL 7. PLUVIUM.]

  COLOURS: PLUVIUM, DARK-STONE.

  _Points_: Spira, Silver. Ancilla, Turquoise. Nugæ, Fawn. Corvus, Gold.
  Felis, Quaker-green. Passer, Peacock-blue. Sors, Dull-purple. Ilex,
  Light-blue.

  _Lines_: Luca, Leaf-green. Limus, Smoke. Cuspis, Orange. Ops, Stone.
  Pagus, Dull-blue. Onager, Dark-pink. Far, French-grey. Arctos, Brown.
  Tholos, Brown-green. Pator, Green-blue. Callis, Reddish. Lucta,
  Rich-red.

  _Surfaces_: Silex, Burnt-Sienna. Pactum, Yellow-green. Moena,
  Dark-blue. Pagina, Yellow. Limbus, Ochre. Lotus, Azure.

[Illustration: MODEL 8. TELA.]

  COLOURS: TELA, SALMON.

  _Points_: Panax, Blue-tint. Mugil, Earthen. Crus, Terra-cotta. Cista,
  Buff. Solia, Purple. Talus, Orange-vermilion. Lama, Deep-blue. Olus,
  Red.

  _Lines_: Mensura, Dark-purple. Offex, Magenta. Cadus, Green-grey. Lis,
  Light-green. Lixa, Indigo. Vena, Pale-pink. Daps, Dark-slate. Bucina,
  Green. Livor, Pale-yellow. Libera, Sea-green. Semita, Leaden. Orsa,
  Emerald.

  _Surfaces_: Portica, Dun. Orca, Dark-grey. Murex, Light-yellow.
  Camoena, Deep-crimson. Mango, Deep-green. Lorica, Sea-blue.

[Illustration: MODEL 9. SECTION BETWEEN MALA AND MARGO.]

  COLOURS: INTERIOR OR TESSARACT, WOOD.

  _Points_ (_Lines_): Ops, Stone. Limus, Smoke. Offex, Magenta. Lis,
  Light-green. Lucta, Rich-red. Pator, Green-blue. Libera, Sea-green.
  Orsa, Emerald.

  _Lines_ (_Surfaces_): Lotus, Azure. Olla, Rose. Lorica, Sea-blue. Lua
  Bright-brown. Pagina, Yellow. Pactum, Yellow-green. Orca, Dark-grey.
  Camoena, Deep-crimson. Limbus, Ochre. Meatus, Deep-brown. Mango,
  Deep-green. Croeta, Light red.

  _Surfaces_ (_Solids_): Pluvium, Dark-stone. Idus, Oak. Tela, Salmon.
  Vesper, Pale-green. Velum, Chocolate. Lar, Brick-red.

[Illustration: MODEL 10. SECTION BETWEEN LAR AND VELUM.]

  COLOURS: INTERIOR OR TESSARACT, WOOD.

  _Points_ (_Lines_): Pagus, Dull-blue. Onager, Dark-pink. Vena,
  Pale-pink. Lixa, Indigo. Arctos, Brown. Far, French-grey. Daps,
  Dark-slate. Bucina, Green.

  _Lines_ (_Surfaces_): Silex, Burnt-sienna. Sal, Yellow-ochre. Portica,
  Dun. Crux, Indian-red. Pagina, Yellow. Pactum, Yellow-green. Orca,
  Dark-grey. Camoena, Deep-crimson. Moena, Dark-blue. Proes, Blue-green.
  Murex, Light-yellow. Alvus, Vermilion.

  _Surfaces_ (_Solids_): Pluvium, Dark-stone. Idus, Oak. Tela, Salmon.
  Vesper, Pale-green. Mala, Light-buff. Margo, Sage-green.

[Illustration: MODEL 11. SECTION BETWEEN VESPER AND IDUS.]

  COLOURS: INTERIOR OR TESSARACT, WOOD.

  _Points_ (_Lines_): Luca, Leaf-green. Cuspis, Orange. Cadus,
  Green-grey. Mensura, Dark-purple. Tholus, Brown-green. Callis,
  Reddish. Semita, Leaden. Livor, Pale-yellow.

  _Lines_ (_Surfaces_): Lotus, Azure. Syce, Black. Lorica, Sea-blue.
  Lappa, Bright-green. Silex, Burnt-sienna. Moena, Dark-blue. Murex,
  Light-yellow. Portica, Dun. Limbus, Ochre. Mel, White. Mango,
  Deep-green. Lares, Light-grey.

  _Surfaces_ (_Solids_): Pluvium, Dark-stone. Mala, Light-buff. Tela,
  Salmon. Margo, Sage-green. Velum, Chocolate. Lar, Brick-red.

[Illustration: MODEL 12. SECTION BETWEEN PLUVIUM AND TELA.]

  COLOURS: INTERIOR OR TESSARACT, WOOD.

  _Points_ (_Lines_): Opex, Purple-brown. Mappa, Dull-green. Bolus,
  Crimson. Dos, Blue. Lensa, Dark. Calor, Dark-green. Iter, Bright-blue.
  Via, Deep-yellow.

  _Lines_ (_Surfaces_): Lappa, Bright-green. Olla, Rose. Syce, Black.
  Lua, Bright-brown. Crux, Indian-red. Sal, Yellow-ochre. Proes,
  Blue-green. Alvus, Vermilion. Lares, Light-grey. Meatus, Deep-brown.
  Mel, White. Croeta, Light-red.

  _Surfaces_ (_Solids_): Margo, Sage-green. Idus, Oak. Mala, Light-buff.
  Vesper, Pale-green. Velum, Chocolate. Lar, Brick-red.



  Transcriber’s Notes


  Lay-out and formatting have been optimised for browser html (available
  display all elements of the book as intended, depending on the hard-
  and software used and their settings. For this text file, several
  diagrams and tables have been split or otherwise re-arranged in order
  to fit the available width. Wherever possible, these splits and
  re-arrangements have been done so that the meaning of the lay-out has
  been retained. The contents of Tables A through D have been replaced
  with place holders; their meanings are listed below the diagrams.

  Inconsistencies in spelling (Mœnas v. Moenas; Praeda v. Proeda),
  hyphenation (Deep-blue v. Deep blue, etc.) have been retained.

  Page 197, row starting Sophos: the last letter of Blue has been
  assumed.

  Changes made:

  Footnotes, tables, diagrams and illustrations have been moved outside
  text paragraphs. Indications for the location of illustrations (To
  face p. ...) have been removed; the illustrations concerned have been
  moved to where they are discussed.

  Some minor obvious typographical errors have been corrected silently.

  Page 42: ... the flat, being ... changed to ... the flat being ...

  Page 127: Cube itself: considered to be the table header rather than a
  table element

  Page 175: is all Ana our space changed to is all Ana in our space

  Page 187: Clipens changed to Clipeus; legend Y added to right-hand
  side grid axes

  Page 219: Part II. Appendix K. changed to Appendix K. cf. other
  Appendices.





*** End of this LibraryBlog Digital Book "A New Era of Thought" ***

Copyright 2023 LibraryBlog. All rights reserved.



Home